Wiki

http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Necessary_and_sufficient_condition

  • This page was last modified on 21 January 2010 at 15:09.

Necessary and sufficient condition

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

This article discusses only the formal meanings of necessary andsufficient. For the causal meanings see causation.

In logic, the words necessity and sufficiency refer to the implicational relationships between statements. The assertion that one statement is a necessary and sufficient condition of another means that the former statement is true if and only if the latter is true.

    • A necessary condition of a statement must be satisfied for the statement to be true. Formally, a statement P is a necessary condition of a statement Q if Q implies P. For example, the ability to breathe is necessary to a human's survival. Likewise, for the whole numbers greater than two, being odd is necessary to being prime, since two is the only whole number that is both even and prime.
    • A sufficient condition is one that, if satisfied, assures the statement's truth. Formally, a statement P is a sufficient condition of a statement Q if P implies Q. Thus, jumping is sufficient to leave the ground, since an intrinsic element of the concept jumping is leaving the ground. A number's being divisible by 4 is sufficient for its being even.

A condition can be either necessary or sufficient without being the other. For instance, being a mammal (P) is necessary but not sufficient to being human (Q), and that a number q is rational (P) is sufficient but not necessary to q‘s being areal number (Q). A condition can be both necessary and sufficient. For example, at present, "today is the Fourth of July" is a necessary and sufficient condition for "today is Independence Day in the United States." Similarly, a necessary and sufficient condition for invertibility of a matrix M is that M have a nonzero determinant.

Lightning is both necessary and sufficient forthunder, and vice versa. This is because the two events are part of the same phenomenon.

Necessary conditions

The assertion that P is necessary for Q is colloquially equivalent to "Q cannot be true unless P is true," or "if P is false then Q is false." By contraposition, this is the same thing as "whenever Q is true, so is P". The logical relation between them is expressed as "If Q then P" and denoted "Q

\Rightarrow

P" (Q implies P), and may also be expressed as any of "P, if Q," "P whenever Q," and "P when Q." One often finds, in mathematical prose for instance, several necessary conditions which, taken together, constitute a sufficient condition, as shown in Example 3.

Example 1: Consider thunder, technically the acoustic quality demonstrated by the shock wave that inevitably results from any lightning bolt in the atmosphere. It may fairly be said that thunder is necessary for lightning, since lightning cannot occur without thunder, too, occurring. That is, if lightning does occur, then there is thunder.

Example 2: Being at least 30 years old is necessary for serving in the U.S. Senate. If you are under 30 years old then it is impossible for you to be a senator. That is, if you are a senator, it follows that you are at least 30 years old.

Example 3: In algebra, in order for some set S together with an operation

to form a group, it is necessary that be associative. It is also necessary that S include a special element e such that for every x in S it is the case that e

\star
\star
\star
\star

x and x e both equal x. It is also necessary that for every x in S there exist a corresponding element x” such that both x

x” and xx equal the special element e. None of these three necessary conditions by itself is sufficient, but the conjunction of the three is.

Sufficient conditions

To say that P is sufficient for Q is to say that in and of itself, knowing P to be true is adequate grounds to conclude that Q is true. The logical relation is expressed as "If P then Q" or "P

\star
\star

The sun being above the horizon is a necessary condition for direct sunlight; but it is not a sufficient condition as something (else) may be casting a shadow.

Q," and may also be expressed as "P implies Q." Several sufficient conditions may, taken together, constitute a single necessary condition, as illustrated in example 3.

Example 1: An occurrence of thunder is a sufficient condition for the occurrence of lightning in the sense that hearing thunder, and unambiguously recognizing it as such, justifies concluding that there has been a lightning bolt.

Example 2: A U.S. president's signing a bill that Congress passed is sufficient to make the bill law, regardless of the fact that even in the event of a presidentialveto it still could have become law through a congressional override.

Example 3: That the center of a playing card should be marked with a single large spade (♠) is sufficient for the card to be an ace. Three other sufficient conditions are that the center of the card be marked with a diamond (♦), heart (♥), or club (♣), respectively. None of these conditions is necessary to the card's being an ace, but their disjunction is, since no card can be an ace without fulfilling at least (in fact, exactly) one of the conditions.

Relationship between necessity and sufficiency

Mathematically speaking, necessity and sufficiency are dual to one another. For any statements P and Q, the assertion that P(effect) implication Q(cause). Another facet of this duality is that, as illustrated above, conjunctions of necessary conditions may achieve sufficiency, while disjunctions of sufficient conditions may achieve necessity. For a third facet, identify every mathematical predicate P with the set S(P) of objects for which P holds true; then asserting the necessity of P for Q is equivalent to claiming that S(P) is a superset of S(Q), while asserting the sufficiency of P for Q is equivalent to claiming that S(P) is a subset of S(Q).

Simultaneous necessity and sufficiency

See also: Material equivalence

To say that P is necessary and sufficient for Q is to say two things, that P is necessary for Q and that P is sufficient forQ. Of course, it may instead be understood to say a different two things, namely that each of P and Q is necessary for the other. And it may be understood in a third equivalent way: as saying that each is sufficient for the other. One may summarize any—and thus all—of these cases by the statement "P if and only if Q," which is denoted by P

Q.

For example, in graph theory a graph G is called bipartite if it is possible to assign to each of its vertices the color blackor white in such a way that every edge of G has one endpoint of each color. And for any graph to be bipartite, it is a necessary and sufficient condition that it contain no odd-length cycles. Thus, discovering whether a graph has any odd cycles tells one whether it is bipartite and vice versa. A philosopher might characterize this state of affairs thus: "Although the concepts of bipartiteness and absence of odd cycles differ in intension, they have identical extension."

See also

Argument forms involving necessary and sufficient conditions

\Rightarrow
\Leftrightarrow

That a train runs on schedule is often a sufficient condition for arriving on time; but it is not always a necessary condition—there are other ways to travel.

External links

Text document with red question mark.svg

This article includes a list of references, related reading or external links, but its sources remain unclear because it lacks inline citations. Please improve this article by introducing more precise citations where appropriate. (April 2009)