Philosophy and Philosophers - an Introduction to Western Philosophy - Chapter 9

back to ...

https://sites.google.com/site/philosophygreekancient/philosophy-and-philosophers---an-introduction-to-western-philosophy---chapter

or ...

CHAPTER NINE

Phenomenology and existentialism: Husserl, Sartre

Historically and intellectually there are complex connections between

phenomenology and the later manifestations of existentialism. The

phenomenology of Husserl was one of the major influences on Sartre,

although Sartre came to reject some of Husserl’s most distinctive

doctrines. Some of the connecting and discussed doctrines are: that the

defining feature of consciousness is intentionality so that every and

only acts of consciousness are directed to a meant or intended object;

the nature of the ego or I; the question of which is logically prior,

essence or existence; and the possibility and adequacy of a

disinterested or pure transcendental conceptualization of reality or

being.

Husserl

Edmund Husserl (1859–1938) was born in Prossnitz, a village in

Czechoslovakian Moravia, at that time part of the Austrian Empire.

His early university studies at Leipzig and Berlin were in

mathematics, and he received his PhD in mathematics in 1881. He also

attended the philosophy lectures of Wilhelm Wundt at the University

of Leipzig. Husserl decided to devote himself entirely to philosophy

and he moved to Vienna, where he attended philosophy lectures by

Franz Brentano (1838–1917), at which students were acquainted with

the philosophy of David Hume and John Stuart Mill. Husserl taught

at the universities of Halle and Göttingen, and from 1916 to 1929 at

Freiburg, where he spent the rest of his life. Husserl was an important

influence on Martin Heidegger (1889–1976), who became Rector of

232

Freiburg University in 1933. Husserl had a dedicated attitude to

philosophy and saw it as a calling rather than merely a job. During

the thirties, following the rise of Nazism, life became increasingly

difficult for Husserl because of his Jewishness. If he had not died in

1938, he might well have gone the way of multitudes of other

European Jews. At his death his unpublished manuscripts were under

threat of being lost. High drama accompanied their removal to safety;

following some failed attempts to transport the manuscripts over the

Swiss border, they were eventually taken in the diplomatic baggage of

the Belgian Embassy to Louvain, where the Husserl Archives were

established.

The chief concern of the philosophy of Husserl is that philosophy

should develop as a truly universal “rigorous science”. Philosophy

must be a science that begins right at the beginning, taking nothing for

granted; that is to say, it must be a presuppositionless science of

sciences. All deductive or inductive reasoning depends for its validity

on the immediate, intuitive apprehension of truths for which further

justification neither can be given nor is required; such apodictic

(necessary) evident truths require no further foundation. If there is not

to be an infinite regress of justification, so that nothing is in fact ever

categorically justifiable, there must be such apodictic truths; not

everything can be justified. In this sense Husserl’s project of

establishing a unified certain foundation for all knowledge is close to

that of Descartes.

Husserl’s first major work in philosophy was closely connected

with mathematics. In the Philosophy of arithmetic he sought an

epistemological account of the origin of our ideas, understanding and

knowledge of the central concepts of arithmetic: numbers, functions,

arithmetical truths and the like. For example, the foundation of the

possession of the concept of number derives from intuitions of

aggregates as such. This was construed by the mathematician and

logician Gottlob Frege (1824–1925) as an attempt to set out a

naturalistic, and specifically a psychologistic or subjective, account of

arithmetical objects and truths themselves, and Husserl consequently

encountered Frege’s fierce criticism. The conventional opinion is that,

partly as a result of Frege’s criticism, Husserl did a complete

intellectual turnabout in his early philosophical studies from a view

supporting psychologism to a view rejecting it which resulted in the

philosophy of phenomenology. However, it can be argued that

Frege’s view of the Philosophy of arithmetic has spawned

misinterpretation, and that Husserl was concerned to study the

nature and origin of our ideas of arithmetical concepts and truths,

and that that inquiry is neutral with regard to the objectivity or

otherwise of those concepts and truths themselves. Indeed, it seems

clear that Husserl was fully aware of the need to distinguish our

ideas of numbers from numbers themselves.

Husserl 233

Whatever is the truth of the matter, Husserl’s later work does

involve an attack on psychologism. The psychologistic account of

deductive reasoning suggests that the justification of deductive

reasoning and of logical or mathematical truths such as 2+2=4 rests

upon their displaying certain very fundamental facts about the way we

think, even if such logical truths are not dependent on facts about the

physical world. This position, however, rests on a confusion; such a

view both removes the absolute necessity of logical truths and is also

question-begging. If logical truths did rest on any kind of facts—even

universally true facts about the way human beings think—then they

would rest upon facts that might have been otherwise since such facts

are always contingent. If we take the deductive inference involving

any two propositions “p” and “q”, “If p then q, p, therefore q”, it is

tempting to regard this as receiving its justification as a valid inference

from its describing a psychological fact about the way people must

think: if someone thinks “If p then q,” and thinks “p”, then they must

think “q”, or must see that “q” follows. This, however, confuses a

factual causal psychological compulsion, which is contingent even if

universal, with a logical inference which is necessary regardless of

whether anyone in fact makes the inference or not. Now the inference

may describe the way all people think—although that is extremely

doubtful—but that is not what the validity of the inference rests on.

The validity of the deduction does not depend on any general facts

about psychological processes; and, indeed, a rejection of all forms of

naturalism holds that logical truths do not depend on any facts at all.

Logic is prescriptive, not descriptive. Moreover, any such naturalistic

attempt to give logic a psychological justification would be viciously

circular, since all reasoning, including that required to do psychology

and produce arguments in psychology, already assumes the validity of

logical rules of inference. In short, the natural sciences presuppose the

validity of the rules of logic and so arguments using the propositions

of natural science cannot be used to justify the rules of logic. Such

naturalism would encourage various forms of relativism: if logical

rules describe psychological laws of thought, then these laws might for

us, or other beings, in another time or place, be different. The

connections in logic between premises and conclusions, between

evidence and conclusions—reasons and their logical consequences

generally—are not mechanical or causal but are conceptual and

concern meanings. Husserl rejects, in the Logical investigations,

psychologism and the universalization of naturalism, and the

misplacing of naturalistic explanation.

One of the initial motivations of Husserl’s philosophy can, then, be

seen as a reaction against scientism: the belief that everything is

explicable in naturalistic scientific terms. Husserl is not hostile to

science, he merely wants to point to its limitations: it makes

presuppositions about the nature and existence of reality which it does

234 Phenomenology and existentialism

not question, and so cannot give fundamental explanations in the

required sense of an ultimate starting-point for a rational explanation

of the world. Naturalism has its place: in natural science. Natural

science is too underpinned by unquestioned presuppositions, which

cannot be questioned within naturalism, to be a certain foundation for

all knowledge. For philosophy to be a rigorous science it must return

to what is given in experience in its generality prior to all theorizing

and interpretation, and approach what is given with an attitude shorn

of preconceptions or assumptions both apparent and hidden.

Philosophy must aim to reach apodictic certain truths: absolutely

necessary and certain truths which are devoid of the presuppositions

that would undermine their absoluteness. Philosophy seeks what

remains and self-evidently must be the case once all that need not be

the case—the contingent—is set aside: we are left with that which must

be presupposed in every form of rational inquiry.

Husserl speaks of the “crisis of European man”, by which he

means that the inability to establish rationalism on firm foundations

has led to irrationalism and barbarism; however, it is not the essence

of rationalism that is at fault, but the misconception that rationalism

and scientific naturalism are one, and that scientific naturalism can

provide ultimate rational explanations. When this is seen to fail,

rationalism itself is in danger of abandonment, whereas it is the false

identification of rationalism with naturalism that should be rejected.

That naturalistic science fails to deliver ultimate certain truths about

the universe should not be seen as a failure of that rationalist project

itself.

The historical starting-point of Husserl’s phenomenology is

Brentano. Brentano believed he had discovered the essence of the

mental or consciousness: that which is common to all and only the

mental. This common defining feature is intentionality: what the mental

is—what its existence consists in—is uniquely characterized by its

being intentional. Each mental act (or mental attitude) is directed

towards an object, an intentional object. Consciousness in its various

modes (thinking, believing, desiring, loving, hating, remembering etc.)

always has an object or content. In the different mental acts,

intentional objects will be related to consciousness in different ways.

But in all cases consciousness is consciousness of something: it always

has an object, and it is moreover directed upon or towards—it

“intends”—some object. The intentional object is the object of one’s

attention in a mental act. The notion of intentionality developed when

it was realized that consciousness is distinguished by its directedness

towards an intended object regardless of whether that object actually

exists in the world or not. The objects of mental acts may be

“intentionally inexistent” in being neither physical nor minddependent.

Thus if I am scared of the spider in the room, the

intentional object is the spider of which I am scared; the intentional

Husserl 235

object is the content of that mental act of being afraid, regardless of

whether there is actually a spider or not. I might believe I see a man

walking towards me in the fog: the intentional object of what I believe

I see is the man I believe I see, although the extensional object in the

world may turn out to be a tree. It is always indisputably true that my

mental act has such-and-such an object; my consciousness, and its acts

(recognizing, believing, remembering, etc.) are not accidently

associated with their intentional objects which are a necessary part of

the mental act whether the object turns out to exist or not: the

intentional object is immanent in the act. By contrast, any physical (nonmental)

act always requires an existent object on which to perform the

act: kicking a chair requires a chair that exists which is kicked, but

thinking of a chair does not require any chair to exist.

The view that intentionality is the essence of the mental seems to

work well as a defining feature of some mental acts, such as believing,

judging, and remembering, but it seems less applicable to other mental

occurrences, such as general moods like anxiety or well being, which

appear to be objectless. Brentano’s answer to this, which maintains

intentionality as the essence of the mental, is that in the cases of

occurrences such as moods the mood itself is its own object. The notion

that the mental is essentially intentional undermines the dualism of

Descartes’ view of mind as an autonomous mental substance which

might exist independently of all objects of consciousness; for,

according to the thesis of intentionality, thought (the cogito) and the

object of thought (the cogitatum) are inextricably linked: there is no

consciousness without consciousness of objects—there is no such thing

as bare consciousness devoid of an object—there can be no objects with

meanings without consciousness.

Husserl’s acceptance of the role played by intentionality in defining

consciousness further expresses the limitations of causal naturalism;

the realm of conscious acts and of their meant or intended objects

gives a field where the connections are understood only through the

notion of a connection of meanings and rational justification, which is

irreducible to merely causal or associationist psychological

explanations. The intelligibility of the sequences of mental acts and

their objects as meanings (believing x because of believing y) is one

where the connections require an account in terms of concepts, reasons

and purposes, not in terms of the causal or mechanical association of

mental events. “What justifies your certain belief that 1,574×6,266

=9,862,684?” or “Why do you hate the man who sold you the cat?”

require not causal answers or explanations, but reasons or evidence:

rational or logical justification. There are, on the one hand, situations

where someone as a matter of causal psychological fact holds a belief

or draws a certain conclusion, even though it does not rationally or

logically follow; and, on the other hand, there are cases where a belief

or conclusion does rationally or logically follow, but as a matter of

236 Phenomenology and existentialism

causal psychological fact people do not hold that belief or draw that

conclusion. So the question of the causal circumstances in which

someone as a matter of psychological fact does hold a certain belief or

draw a certain conclusion is distinct from the question of whether he is

rationally or logically justified in doing so.

Husserl is not really so concerned to argue for the conclusion that

intentionality is the distinguishing feature of the mental; what is

important for Husserl is that the realm of intentional objects or

meanings gives philosophy an autonomous guaranteed subject for

study independent of, and irreducible to, any wider naturalistic causal

assumptions concerning the nature or existence of those objects: we

have in any case objects as meanings of which we are conscious if we

are conscious at all. Whatever assumptions we make about the nature

of reality, it is nevertheless the case that our mental acts will be

possessed of certain contents or meant objects in virtue of their

intentionality: things appear to us a certain way. The mental always

involves reference to an object or content which in any sense other

than as the object intended in our mental act need not exist. The

subject matter of phenomenology is the essential nature of these

contents taken or viewed purely as the intentional objects of mental

acts. It is important to note that “object of consciousness” does not just

denote the sensuous objects of empirical experience. Anything that can

be an object of consciousness—colours, physical objects, mathematical

equations, love, time, comradeship, etc.—is a potential subject for

phenomenological study: it can be studied as it is as a phenomenon.

What underpins phenomenology is the idea that in coming to view

objects (in the most general sense) just as appearances to consciousness

we can see certain and necessary truths concerning the essential

features of those objects, for we can then see those features of things

which cannot, without self-contradiction as to what they are, be

thought away; we thereby understand objects as they are in themselves

stripped of all presuppositions and added-on interpretation of any

sort. The essential—necessary and sufficient—invariable features of

objects, of which we can be certain, are those features which, if they

appear to us at all, cannot be thought away if those objects are to

appear to us as objects of such-and-such a sort. The way objects must be

if they are to appear to us at all as those objects constitutes their

essence.

The word “phenomenology” derives from the Greek phainomenon

meaning an appearance, and logos meaning a reason or law. The

ultimate objects of presuppositionless science are phenomena: the

word “phenomenon” designates that which is what it appears to be,

which is therefore something seen as it is in itself. Phenomenology is in

fact the science of the intentional objects of consciousness; it consists of

laws based on meanings which describe the necessary structural or

formal features of appearances of various sorts. In the case of

Husserl 237

phenomenal objects there can be no appearance/reality distinction:

what they are is what they appear to be, for we are concerned with

them only as they appear. One cannot be mistaken that things appear in

a certain way: and as long as one does not go beyond (transcend)

things as appearances, one has a realm of objects about which one can

form necessary and certain descriptive truths. Appearances themselves

cannot present themselves in varying perspectives, although we can

have various different appearances. The force of the slogan of

phenomenology “To the things themselves” (Zu den Sachen selbst) is

that we must confront things just as experienced by consciousness,

independently of any theoretical or metaphysical presuppositions,

rather than as objects in any other sense—as physical objects for

example. We must return to experiences themselves, to

“transcendental experience”: a realm of “pure consciousness” or “pure

subjectivity”. That there is subjectivity or consciousness as such

Husserl called “the wonder of all wonders”. The wonder resides not in

being or existence itself but in that there is a being that is aware of

being.

Beneath the various natural sciences and the common-sense view of

the world there is a network of presuppositions as to the nature of

reality which are trans-phenomenal or “transcendent”: we make

assumptions about objects which go beyond what the objects are when

considered as pure phenomena. These assumptions go beyond what is

essential to those objects as phenomena. The pre-philosophical view of

the world Husserl calls the “natural attitude”. Even logic and

mathematics do not have the required presuppositionlessness, for they

do not within their subject question all the grounds of their basic

concepts and rules of inference. Indeed, it became apparent by the end

of the nineteenth century that it was possible to set up a variety of

equally consistent but mutually contradictory formal systems. There

are for example several different geometries.

The means of achieving the lowest level of presuppositionless

awareness which is required for a truly philosophical attitude is through

what Husserl calls the phenomenological reduction, “bracketing”, or

“epoché” (from the Greek word “epoche¯” referring to a “suspension”, in

this case of belief or judgement). The phenomenological epoché is the

heart of the phenomenological method. What we are left with when all

presuppositions concerning objects are set aside is only what is certain

and necessary about those objects. In fact the phenomenological

reduction has two stages:

(I) That in which we suspend judgement as to the existence or nonexistence

of the objects of consciousness so we can concentrate on

them as pure phenomena: that is, as they are as appearances.

(II) That in which we view the objects reduced to pure phenomena

not in their particularity, but in their generality and essence: we

238 Phenomenology and existentialism

are to concern ourselves with phenomena only as samples or

examples of types or sorts of phenomena, not with what makes

them particular “thises”; we thus bracket off the particularities of

phenomena. This is termed the “eidetic reduction” because it

reduces phenomena to the residue of whatever makes them the

type or sort of phenomena they are, without which they could

not appear at all. “Eidetic” derives from the Greek “eidos” for

“form”, which alludes to Platonic Forms which are essences.

In order to concentrate on objects merely as they are given to

consciousness as such, we bracket off all our normal everyday and

scientific theories and presuppositions as to the nature and existence of

those objects. In this way we set aside the presuppositions which are

unquestioned in both the common-sense and the natural scientific

views of the world in order to study the contents of pure “reduced”

consciousness as such. Whatever assumptions we previously made

about the contents of consciousness—concerning their cause, their

existence, their nature, their representing or not representing objects in

the external world—are suspended. Independently of all these

assumptions, everything that can come before the mind can be studied

as purely phenomenal objects: as they appear to consciousness. This

epoché involves neither denying nor affirming the existence or being of

the external world; the reality of the external world is not eliminated

but simply set aside from consideration, as are judgements concerning

the truth or falsity of the claim. In this way one attains the proper

philosophical attitude.

Philosophy, once it has attained the required phenomenological

attitude to the “reduced” objects of consciousness, is not concerned

with them as the contents of particular mental events, rather it is

concerned with them in their significance or meaning. The epoché

detaches the pure phenomenal objects of consciousness from both their

existence or non-existence and all that is inessential for them to be

what they are: we then see them as they are in themselves: as they must

be from any point of view in order for them to be whatever kind of

phenomenal object they are. Phenomenology is concerned with

phenomenal objects in themselves and as essences: the “whatness”

whereby the phenomenal object is an object of the kind it is. Husserl

uses “eidos” to mean “essence” or “pure essence”. We are concerned

with objects as appearances to consciousness in their universal or

essential aspects, whereby all and only objects of that sort must

possess such-and-such a set of characteristics if they are to be that kind

of object at all. Phenomenology, and indeed true philosophy, aims in

Husserl’s view to be nothing less than a “science of essences” or

“eidetic science”.

These essences are independent of any individual consciousness,

and are absolutely objective and universally valid, for they reveal to us

Husserl 239

what, if a certain object or content is present to consciousness at all,

must be part of the consciousness of that object. Indeed, knowledge of

essences is independent of all questions or knowledge of existence or

fact: the “whatness” of an object is totally independent of whether any

instances of that object actually exist.

Husserl is further convinced that such essences are intuited: there is

an immediate intellectual vision or grasping of essences (Wesensschau).

In a sense we confusedly apprehend essence all the time. When a

certain object is present to consciousness, it is always present as suchand-such

an appearance, not as mere appearance: that is, it has a

significance or meaning. That significance or meaning is captured by

its essence. Without these essences or significances, objects would be

nothing to us at all. But objects have a significance, and whatever the

accidental circumstances or features of their presentation, their

essential features deliver the significance or meaning of that

experience. Essences—giving significances as…—are the ultimate

phenomena of consciousness. In the Cartesian manner Husserl argues

that the essences of a thing are those features which it has beyond

doubt, for without them it would not be presented as that sort of thing

at all. It is this common meaning that is invariant in all our varying

perspectival presentations of a thing (for example as we move round

an object), that unites those varying presentations in referring to the

same object. Thus the consciousness-of-house means house only in

virtue of its including the essence of house: in this way the various acts

of consciousness are related and directed towards a house, rather than

something else.

This is related to an idea in Frege. Expressions can have meaning or

sense (Sinn) even though no object or reference (Bedeutung) exists that

satisfies that sense: the sense has a reference only if something satisfies

the sense, otherwise it has no existing meant object or reference. Thus

sense is independent of whether anything satisfies that sense, that is,

whether the meant or intended object exists or not. In addition

different singular naming expressions or signs and definite

descriptions can designate the same object either through their having

the same sense or through their different senses being different senses

for—modes of presenting—one and the same object: as with “the

Morning Star” and “the Evening Star” picking out Venus, or “1+1” and

“5–3” designating the number 2. If the meaning of an expression were

identified with its reference, then if I understood two expressions I

would as a consequence know whether they referred to the same

object or to different objects. If understanding the meaning of an

expression is knowing its reference, it is impossible, if I understand

what is meant by “the Morning Star” and “the Evening Star”, not to

realize that the two expressions refer to the same object: Venus. For to

understand the meaning of the expressions would involve in each case

being acquainted with their common reference. Such a consequence is

240 Phenomenology and existentialism

clearly false. It is obviously the case that the statement “the Morning

Star=the Evening Star” is an informative discovery of astronomy and

is not equivalent to the trivial logical statement “a=a”. The upshot of

this is to make it clear that there can be meaningful expressions which

may or may not have references; so the meanings are not to be

identified with their references and are independent of them. There is

no need to postulate the mysterious “subsistence” of Pegasus in order

for the expression “Pegasus” to have a sense and hence be meaningful.

Husserl accepts that we will need to experience individual cases of

white in order to grasp the essence “whiteness”; but one then

immediately grasps the essence of whiteness, since one sees the object

as white. Seeing an object as white implies that one already

understands what whiteness is. Objects are perceived with a certain

significance. It is a mistake to think that our grasp of the essence or

concept “whiteness” derives from inductively abstracting from a series

of particular white objects some feature they all and only they have in

common, for this process already involves the ability to pick out white

objects; we are already picking out some objects, and rejecting other

objects, as white objects. It is rather that in seeing something as white

we do, in that very mental act of seeing as, intuitively “see” the essence

of white. We already have the ability to pick out white objects:

phenomenology articulates the awareness of the essence implicit in

that ability. An analogy might be the way in which we could recognize

the man who robbed the bank (“I would know him if I saw him”—

which gives the point to identity parades) although we are quite

incapable of giving any defining description of the man.

Phenomenology aims to produce a state of mind where such an

intuitive descriptive articulation of essence is possible by setting aside

all that is neither necessary nor sufficient for a phenomenal object to be

the phenomenal object it is; we are left with an essential residue of

necessary and sufficient features which will give us certain and

necessary truths.

Particular objects of consciousness may be used as examples in

order to identify essences, rather in the way that a particular geometric

drawing of a triangle may be used to illustrate some theorem of

geometry such as Pythagoras’ theorem; but the truth concerning the

nature of the essence in no way depends upon the existence of the

particular item used as an example or on any other item existing. In

using examples, we describe what Husserl terms the “horizon” of a

thing; by the free play of the imagination—“free variation”—we

determine the limits within which a thing can vary while still

remaining the kind of thing it is. Thus we transform our experience of

an individual entity into experience of essence: we have then a nonsensuous

eidetic intuition.

Another way of looking at this is to say that in intuiting essences,

we are aware of pure possibilities independent of actual being: that

Husserl 241

which is essential to any actualization of that sort of object. Without its

essence no concrete actualization of the object whose essence it is

could occur, whatever else may be true of the object. It must therefore

be present in any possible experience of that object. For example, the

essence of any physical object, or a man, or a colour, is not identical

with any individual physical object, man or colour; the essence is what

is common to all and only things of those kinds, which describes what

is required for them to be things of those kinds, and without which

they would not be those things at all.

Through intuitions we describe the essential structure of our

experiences viewed as pure phenomena. The phenomena include

reflexively mental acts and the phenomenal objects of those acts: the

thought and the object of thought. Phenomenology, and hence

philosophy, is the foundation of any science whatsoever because any

intelligible awareness of the world at all must begin with this

fundamental grasping of essences: without these essences the world

would have no significance for us at all. In this sense Husserl regards

phenomenology as a priori: the apprehension of fundamental essential

meanings, significances, and “whatnesses” is logically prior to all

theorizing and independent of all contingent facts; phenomenology is

concerned with the characteristics known to be necessarily connected

with kinds of phenomena. Phenomenology aims to produce absolutely

certain objective necessary truths that are pure in having no relativity

to cognitive, spatial or temporal perspective. Such truths are in this

sense absolutely categorical: they are directly intuited from experience

and do not depend for their acceptance on the acceptance of any other

truths. Thus such truths cannot be argued for, inferred, or derived, for

then their truth would not be guaranteed as absolute because we

would not have to accept them until we had accepted other truths.

Such basic truths concerning the structure of phenomenal objects must

be seen immediately or not seen at all. They cannot be argued for

because any argument would presuppose the most basic level at which

intelligibility or significance arises. Such intuitions of essences are selfgiven

because there is nothing else from which the essence could be

inferred which does not itself assume an intuitive grasp of categories

of meaning or concepts. So, unlike in Kant, the preconditions for any

significant experience are not deduced, but intuited directly. Any

attempt at deduction, since the deduction itself is also a phenomenon

with significance as a deduction, already assumes the lowest level of

classificatory categories of consciousness without which no experience

would have any significance at all, and an experience without any

significance at all—not of an object of a certain sort—would be no

experience at all. To construct any argument presupposes that we can

understand what an argument is; so understanding what an argument

is cannot itself be derived from an argument. We cannot in any way

derive the essences of phenomena from anything more fundamental.

242 Phenomenology and existentialism

We may need through experience to acquaint ourselves with the

various kinds of intentional objects and mental acts there are: but the

essence, in virtue of which any mental act is aware of a certain kind of

object, is utterly independent of whether there is such an object or

anyone in particular experiencing that object as a content of

consciousness. If phenomena were utterly neutral with no significance

or meaning at all, there would be no hope of getting any science off the

ground; the absence of the basic meanings or significances of the

objects of consciousness would destroy any possibility of a science

connecting items in our experience into any intelligible repeatable

patterns whatsoever. The aim of phenomenology is to return to the

ultimate original or primordial significances of experiences shorn of

the baggage of accumulated significances embodied in the theories of

science and everyday assumptions. We then view the world with new

wonder and freshness.

The philosophy of Husserl involves a further radical application of

the epoché. The phenomenological reduction brackets the natural

external world, and all of the assumptions associated with belief in

such a world. But something still remains to be subject to epoché: the

individual ego or consciousness. Any act of consciousness

presupposes an ego: but the particularity of the ego is unimportant;

what is important is what is essential to the ego. The individual ego

too must be bracketed in order to intuit the essence of the thinking

individual itself. As with other essences, the existence of any

particular ego is irrelevant to the identification of the universal

“whatness” of ego in general which is pure intentionality. That which

is engaged in the process of bracketing the natural world, including

the empirical ego itself, must be something, and Husserl calls it the

transcendental ego, which stands outside the world. The essence of this

transcendental ego is that it stands as a precondition of any mental act

or experience whatsoever, including all acts of phenomenological

reduction. We now have a triadic structure for consciousness, egocogito-cogitatum;

these are the three logically linked elements of: pure

ego (the “I”, what it is that thinks), mental act (thought), and content

(the object of thought). This gives us full transcendental

phenomenology, the ultimate objects of which are a vast variety of

sorts of meaning or significance (noema, adjective noematic) which are

correlated with meaningful acts (noesis, adjective noetic) of the

transcendental ego. The ultimate phenomenological noetic-noematic

relation is not between psychic elements and empirical objects, but

between their essential meanings. The transcendental ego is,

ultimately, the only absolute, for it remains after all bracketing: it is

presupposed in every act of consciousness or experience whatsoever,

even the activity of bracketing itself. The transcendental ego is the

precondition of all meaning: it alone cannot be thought away because

it is presupposed in all thinking.

Husserl 243

The later philosophy of Husserl led him to give an active role to the

transcendental ego; the conclusion is that not the individual ego, but

the transcendental ego, actively constitutes or constructs the

significance or meaning of the objects of consciousness. Pure ego gives

objects their meaning or significance which makes them objects for

consciousness. This does not necessarily lead to idealism—that reality

is existentially dependent on consciousness—because it might be the

case that the transcendental ego simply places an existentially

independent reality under intelligible categories or concepts and so

makes that reality an object for consciousness. If, however, the only

reality an object can be said to have is that significance actively given

to it by the transcendental ego, then reality or the world is existentially

dependent on the transcendental ego, and that is idealism. If a world

without significance for consciousness is existentially impossible, and

all significance is a product of the transcendental ego, it follows that

the world is existentially dependent on the transcendental ego. This

suggests that the transcendental ego is the only absolute because

everything is existentially dependent on it, and it is not existentially

dependent on anything else.

Husserl’s view points towards a form of subjective idealism—reality

is existentially dependent on the subject—where existence is exhausted

by and tied to the meaning given to objects by the transcendental

subject or the subject as such. It might still be argued that such

significances in the form of essences are objective by being

independent of the existence of any particular consciousness and are

common to all consciousness as such: that objects present themselves

with the meanings or essences that they do is not an accidental feature

of any empirical ego but a product of consciousness as such. Husserl’s

later views tend towards idealism because he holds that to speak of the

world really existing, independently of the categories of significance

which are dependent on pure consciousness, is senseless and absurd.

Still, it might be said that the world would continue to exist

independently of pure consciousness. If this were granted, then it can

be replied that the world so characterized would be without

significance in the same way that a written sentence would be without

significance if there were no minds to grasp its sense; it would be a

“world” that is literally inconceivable. Husserl moves from the view

that nothing can be conceived except as an object for consciousness to

the view that nothing can exist except as an object of consciousness.

His answer to scepticism about the nature and existence of the external

world is to say that the world that appears with meaning just is the

real world and the positing of some other world which might exist or

fail to exist is senseless.

Husserl also became concerned with a phenomenological analysis of

time: the experience of duration itself as it appears to consciousness.

Time is particularly fundamental to the constitution of experiences.

244 Phenomenology and existentialism

The phenomenological analysis of time concerns the essence of time as

it appears: that is, what is necessarily and invariably involved in an

appearance which is temporal. He says that every real experience is

one that endures, and this duration takes place within the stream of an

endless filled continuum of durations which forms an infinite unity;

every present moment of experience—every now—is fringed by a

before and after as limits.

In the last part of Husserl’s life he introduced the concept of

Lebenswelt: the “lived-world”. Before any theorizing, including

philosophizing, one is confronted with the world as it appears in life.

The Lebenswelt is in some sense primary: the theoretical sciences are

derivative of, or parasitic on, its meanings. Objects already appear to

us loaded with a significance that points beyond themselves: their

meaning points to their own horizon, which is not currently present in

the experience, and defines them as the objects they are and indicates

the context in which the objects occur. The meaning of experiencing

the front of a house includes, among many other things, the presently

unseen back of the house. Husserl also became concerned with

avoiding solipsism by discussing the dependence of intentional

objects on the intersubjectivity of a community of individual egos. The

essence or meaning of objects as experienced often points beyond my

subjective awareness and depends on the awareness of others. This is

obvious if we think of the meaning to us of a great work of art. On the

face of it this seems like a rejection of eidetic phenomenology. Some

commentators have taken it that way, but Husserl seems to have seen

no discontinuity between his earlier and later work. Others have

viewed the later Lebenswelt as an indication that the eidetic

intuitions—the essences—we seek are to be found in the objects of the

world as lived.

Sartre

Jean-Paul Sartre (1905–80) was born in Paris. In 1924 he went to the

École Normale Supérieure where he studied philosophy, and in 1929

he began teaching philosophy. From 1933 to 1935 he studied in Berlin

and Freiburg. While still a student Sartre met Simone de Beauvoir with

whom he had lifelong connections. In 1939 he joined the French Army;

because of his poor eyesight his duties were non-combatant; in 1940 he

was taken prisoner by the Germans. His experience of captivity was to

hone his views on the true nature of human freedom. The war also

aroused his interest in politics. In 1941 he was repatriated; he returned

to Paris where he taught philosophy and took an active part in the

Resistance.

There is a strong German influence on Sartre’s philosophy, which

started with his Protestant Calvinist upbringing. Many of the

Sartre 245

philosophers most influential on Sartre are from the German

intellectual tradition, such as Kant, Hegel, Husserl, and Heidegger

(1889–1976). But an ever present influence for a French thinker such as

Sartre is Descartes. Talk of influence does not necessarily entail

agreement, of course. At one time Sartre was also in close contact with

philosopher and contemporary Maurice Merleau-Ponty (1908–61).

After the war Sartre became one of the founders of the literary and

political journal Les temps modernes. He was increasingly involved in

contemporary political and ideological controversy; he was part of an

unsuccessful attempt to found a socialist, but non-communist, political

party. His later political writing espouses a form of Marxism which he

attempts to reconcile with his underlying philosophy of existentialism.

It is difficult to give any general characterization of existentialism.

Existentialism has been characterized as a form of anti-intellectualism,

or irrationalism or subjectivism; but the view of existentialism put

forward here accepts none of these accounts. The view advocated here

is that existentialism is a philosophy concerned to go back to what it

regards as the logically prior description of what it is like to be a

human being in the world before the accretion of a world-view based

on supposedly detached or disinterested theorizing. The philosophical

significance of this is the existentialist’s view that the-world-as-it-isfor-human-beings,

the human-world, the humanness of the world,

before metaphysical and scientific speculation, is logically

presupposed by any such speculation. The reason for this is that our

possessing any concepts and categories, some of which must be

involved in all possible talk about the world, logically depends on our

practices and interests as human beings without which concepts and

categories—more generally meanings and significances—would not

arise at all. The significance of the world and its objects arising from

practice and action is presupposed by the distilled categories of a

disinterested intellectual observer or spectator. Being a detached

spectator is not the logically primary way of our being-in-the-world.

That there is “a world”, objects with various significances and

meanings, depends upon and cannot be separated from the

significances and meanings that they have for human beings as a result

of human interests and agency.

The existentialist position requires us to shake off the grip of various

ingrained metaphysical assumptions about the world and ourselves.

One of the most profound of these is the view that we could, logically

speaking, exist as pure autonomous consciousness or thought

regardless of whether any external world existed at all. Another

metaphysical speculation is that reality can be reduced to either mental

or material substance. The existentialist’s contention is that we must be

reminded that such metaphysical speculations use concepts whose

meanings are parasitic on our concrete engagement as human beings

through practices, actions and interests; metaphysical speculations

246 Phenomenology and existentialism

logically depend for their possible intelligible articulation on terms

whose meanings only arise at all out of our not having a disinterested

or detached point of view. There are useful comparisons to be made

here between existentialism and the philosophy of the later

Wittgenstein in which he says the “form of life” is what is given. The

meanings and significances of objects as such-and-such, which are

logically necessary for any “view” of the world—any intelligible

description and theorizing about the world—would not arise as they

do but for specifically human partisan characteristics, concerns, and

activities or for being sufficiently like human beings; and objects with

meanings and significances would not arise at all but for some form of

active engagement with the world.

The general aim of Western thought in metaphysics and science has

been quite other than that of existentialism. The aim of science, for

example, is to evolve what is regarded as a superior “objective”

description of the world abstracted from specific perspectives: to

generate a body of truths about the world whose validity holds across

the contingencies of spatial, temporal or cognitive perspectives and

which mirror the world independently of the practical or instrumental

uses of objects in the world. The most obvious examples of such nonperspectival

truths are those of mathematics and logic such as 2+2=4,

which is true however you look at it, so to speak; such a truth is a

necessary truth. Literally perspectival truths such as “The tower is very

small” (from the hill overlooking it) or “The bath water is hot” (to my

cold right hand) are true only relative to a perspective and would be

false if the conditions determining the perspective changed—if I came

down the hill, or inserted in the water my warm left hand. What

existentialism argues is that the concepts used to describe a world as

such-and-such a sort, a world said to contain certain kinds of objects,

would not arise at all except for some practical mode of relating to the

world, which in our case arises from our humanness. True or false

descriptions of the world depend for their articulation on meanings

which arise only because of practical human projects. The concept of a

“desk” and a world containing desks would not arise if no one ever

wrote anything and did the usual things which lead us to call a certain

object a “desk”; without a certain sort of behaviour the concept “desk”

would never emerge. Existentialism undermines the aspiration of there

being, and our possessing, the one true systematic description of

everything, for existentialism denies that any kind of description

would arise at all if in the cause of a universally valid account, the

attempt were made to describe the world from an utterly detached

spectatorial standpoint. Such a standpoint would be a “view from

nowhere”, a phrase which perhaps only thinly disguises the fact that it

would be no view at all.

All this does not mean that science and abstraction are wrong in

some way, rather it is to argue that our ordinary view of the world, in

Sartre 247

which objects, events, and ourselves have various meanings or

significances, cannot be thought away as quirks of the merely

contingent way we happen to encounter the world in favour of, and

possibly to be replaced by, a supposedly superior system of descriptive

categories that are more universally valid through being detached

from the contingency of our situation as human beings concretely

dealing with the world. For meanings and significances, and hence the

possibility of description whether true or false, would not arise in the

world without our engaged perspectival interests, practices, projects,

and actions. Objects—for example hammers—have the meanings they

have for us because of their function as obstacles to, or instruments in,

human projects. Existentialism regards it as a mistake to propound

either a subjectivist or an objectivist philosophy: both positions are

based on the misconception that reality can be completely separated

from all conceptions; that somehow we can have direct access to reality

apart from all descriptions.

Many of these points are brought out by examining the reaction of

Sartre to the phenomenology of Husserl. In Being and nothingness

Sartre requires a phenomenology that is existential. It is important to

note in this matter the significant influence on Sartre of Heidegger’s

monumental work Being and time (1927). The seeds of Sartre’s

existential phenomenology are found in his short work The

transcendence of the ego. Husserl’s philosophy of pure phenomenology

derives much of its inspiration from Descartes. Husserl contends that

consciousness is essentially intentional; that is, consciousness is

defined and uniquely distinguished by its “aboutness”; if we are

conscious at all we are always conscious of something with such-andsuch

a significance or meaning. With this point Sartre agrees

completely. But the meanings to which Husserl’s phenomenology

aspires are the pure, essential, or defining features of the objects of

which we are aware. In Husserl’s account, to get at the pure essences

of objects of consciousness it is necessary first to think away all those

characteristics which are unnecessary for the thing of which we are

aware to be just what it is. The immediate result of this “bracketing”

is the suspension of judgement concerning the existence or nonexistence

of that of which we are conscious. The aim is to seek the

features something must have from any “point of view” if it is to

remain that kind of thing. The thought here is again the Cartesian

one that what is true of an object from any point of view

whatsoever—and so is non-perspectivally true and not true merely

from a certain perspective—describes how things really are in

themselves with the contingencies of what is added by our point of

view, in its most general sense, subtracted. This gives the possibility

of a transcendental perspective on the world and a science of

essences. Husserl supposes that the bracketing process suspends

judgement not only on the existence of the physical world but also on

248 Phenomenology and existentialism

the contingent individual empirical ego; what remains is what

Husserl calls the transcendental ego, which is the common essence of

consciousness or consciousness as such. The picture that remains is

one of a transcendental or pure spectatorial ego which intuits pure

essences or meanings that are present or immanent in consciousness

and experience, which are devoid of any contingent assumptions

about the existence of the world or individual selves or the practical

use we make of objects in specifically human projects.

The two notions of the transcendental perspective and the

transcendental ego are interrelated and fall together as the chief targets

of Sartre’s attack on Husserl. Sartre’s position is that there is no such

transcendental pure disinterested perspective and no transcendental

ego. The transcendental ego betrays the doctrine of the essential

intentionality of consciousness for it posits a pure consciousness of

objects which are themselves modes of consciousness, disengaged

from concrete acts of awareness of particular intentional objects in the

world. Sartre rejects the subjectivization of the doctrine of

intentionality. His view is that there is no transcendental perspective

and no pure or transcendental consciousness detached from the world,

for consciousness makes sense only in relation to an awareness of

objects in the world which are not modes of consciousness. A

disinterested, passive and pure view of the world is impossible, in

Sartre’s view, because without particular intentional acts arising from

our existence as beings-in-the-world engaged with what concretely

concerns human beings, consciousness would not arise at all, since the

being of consciousness is defined by its “aboutness” of something

other than consciousness itself: something that is not-consciousness.

Consciousness is not a thing at all, not even a transcendental thing

“outside” the world. If all actual intentional acts, directed to something

other than consciousness—in sum, all awarenesses of—are removed,

then consciousness simply evaporates; so there can be no disinterested

transcendental ego “outside” the world.

Phenomenology becomes existential when it is realized that

consciousness and the world are logically interlinked: that is, no sense

can be given to consciousness in the form of a transcendental ego if it

is separated from its intentional awareness of objects which are not

themselves modes of consciousness. The converse is also true: that no

sense can be given to “the world” if separated from the sense of what

the world is that arises from an actual engagement of human beings

with the world in pursuit of their human concerns. One of the

consequences of this view is the collapse of the mind-body dualism

which supposes we could still make sense of consciousness if all the

world was destroyed, and still make sense of “the world” devoid of

the sense that arises from consciousness engaged in the embodied

pursuit of human interests, purposes and aims. The world for us is a

world of significances and meanings which it would not have without

Sartre 249

us. There are no pure meanings or essences of things waiting to be

discovered by a disinterested pure consciousness; that there are

recognizable separate things with certain significances only arises from

our practical contact with the world in pursuit of various human

purposes and interests. No sense can be given to what a hammer is—

what is meant by a “hammer”—independently of a network of other

objects and what embodied humans do. The significance of an object

such as a hammer would not arise as it does if no one ever made

anything; a hammer emerges as an object of the kind it is because of the

sorts of things human beings do. In the case of a being which was

merely spectatorial or contemplative, totally detached from the world,

the meanings and significances of objects, whereby a particular object

is a such-and-such, would not arise at all. Consciousness consists

strictly of intentional acts—we are conscious as an awareness of objects

as such-and-such a sort—but such intentional or meant objects would

not arise if we were purely passive spectators. Human beings exist as

active beings-in-the-world, not as pure egos; we are consciousnesses

“thrown” into the world, and have to cope with it, and it is only as

coping agents that the vast and intricate network of meanings and

significances of objects we encounter arises. Any abstract theorizing

about the world is logically dependent on our initial natural active

engagement with the world. Phenomenology becomes existential in

not dealing with the structure of a supposed realm of abstract pure

essences which remain after we put ourselves in the transcendental

position separated from practical involvement with the world: instead

existential phenomenology examines the structure of the meanings

and significances the world has as it appears to us everyday in life as a

lived-world. We are embedded in the world: the-world-as-it-is-forhuman-beings.

The world does not cease to exist with our ceasing to exist; but in so

far as the world is a system of meanings and significances it is a

human world because significances and meanings are a product of our

human activities and interests. In this sense when a man dies a world

dies with him.

We find the same existentialist points in Heidegger’s Being and time.

Again there is the emphasis on our “thrownness” into the world of

significances-for-human-beings. The significance the world has as an

instrument, through our active concrete engagement with the world in

pursuit of human purposes and interests, is the world as “ready-tohand”

(zuhanden), which is logically presupposed by the passive

detached description of the world “present-at-hand” (vorhanden) which

is found in natural science.

In this way existentialism undermines the picture of man alienated

or estranged from the world. The world is not primarily a place from

which we stand apart, which is not amenable to human values and

significances. The world is first a place which has human

250 Phenomenology and existentialism

significance—it is our world—and there is no reason to denigrate the

world as a network of significant objects for human beings in order to

replace it by a detached view of the world “as it really is” rendered

alien and devoid of human significance. Human reality is a Dasein

(being-there): that is, we always exist as beings-in-the-world, not

detached from it. As Heidegger points out, we are “cast” or “thrown”

(geworfen) into the world to which the primary relation of our Dasein is

one of “concern” or “care” (Sorge) where some objects are more

important than others; the world is not neutral or flat with all

significances being on the same level. The significance that things have

is inextricably linked to the kind of being we are; we do not relate to

the world as disembodied disinterested consciousnesses but as

embodied agents.

In Sartre’s novel Nausea we find him beginning to deal with the

issues outlined above. In Nausea Sartre’s protagonist Roquentin is a

disappointed rationalist. We can begin by distinguishing between the

notions of existence and essence: the existence of a thing refers to the

fact that it is, the essence of a thing refers to what it is. Particular,

actually existing, things like trees are always inadequately captured or

explained in rational systems of concepts designed to render the world

ordered and intelligible. Sartre seems to have in mind here a stringent

notion of explanation which involves relations of deduction or

entailment between concepts. We find such relationships in a field

such as geometry: all the properties of a triangle follow necessarily

from its initial definition, that is, from its essence or “whatness”;

nothing about a triangle as such is “superfluous”; everything about it

is explained as a necessity that follows from what it is; there is nothing

about a triangle that is left over from what is entailed by its essence. In

other words, all the properties of a triangle follow from its essence, so

nothing is left unexplained. However, neither the existence of objects

in the world, nor the nature of their existence in their full particularity

can be explained by any conceptual system of essences. The “thatness”

of an object—that it exists—and the features in virtue of which it exists

as that particular object are not explained by being deducible from any

system of universal concepts. Only in the realm of essences which do

not exist do we have full explanations for why things are as they are,

for in the realm of essences the properties a thing has are all and only

those logically entailed by its essence: its “whatness”.

The relations between different essences also produce necessary

connections. But there are no such necessary connections between

objects in the world, for the objects in both their individual existence

and nature transcend and are not exhausted by universal concepts

purporting to reveal their essence. In so far as objects in the world are

brought under universal concepts, necessary relations can exist

between them; but no existing particular object can, just in virtue of its

existence and particularity, ever be fully explained or described by

Sartre 251

universal concepts; so the causal relations we aim to describe as

existing between existing particular objects are contingent and have no

logical necessity. Essences are necessarily inadequate in fully

describing all that can be said about particular objects in the world, for

they cannot capture their particularity and their “thatness”. There is a

logically necessary connection between X being what it is, a triangle,

and X having internal angles equal to 180 degrees; but no such

necessary, deductive connection exists between events in the world.

There is no logical entailment between putting the kettle on the heat

and the kettle boiling, no matter how often we have observed the

conjunction of those events in the past; the one event cannot be

deduced from the other. In this sense Sartre expresses a position in

Nausea that is very close to that of Hume. By its very universality a

concept considers and explains an object—gives a reason for why an

object is as it is—only in so far as it falls into some general class not in

its concrete particularity. We may consider an object, for example, in so

far as it falls into the class of trees; but that does not explain the

existence of, or all the features of, that thing over there we have called

a “tree”. Its existence—its “thatness”—does not follow from its

description as a tree, nor do most of its features peculiar to that

individual tree—its roughness, its colour, its hardness—these are all left

out of the concept of “treeness”. They are contingent, unexplained,

excessive, accidental; they are “absurd” in being without sufficient

explanation or reason; there is no sufficient reason as to why they are

one way rather than another.

In Nausea Sartre mentions other things besides geometry that have

the characteristic of complete intelligibility, such as music and stories;

there is a sufficient reason for their being one way rather than another,

for these have a complete internal logic that can be distinguished from

any manifest individual existence. One can smash or damage a record

of Beethoven’s Fifth Symphony, but not smash or damage the Fifth

Symphony itself, for it consists, as a symphony, of abstract relations

between idealized non-actual musical events. Nothing is superfluous

about a work of art: it is what it is.

One way of looking at Nausea is to think of it as the realization of

the Humean nightmare or the collapse of all the supposedly necessary

Kantian concepts: we are reminded in the book of the brute

contingency of relations between objects and events in the world by

the depiction of a world in which the causal order we take for granted

does actually break down. In the extreme case our ability to bring

objects under any intelligible categories also breaks down. That

particular root over there has features not exhausted by its description

as a kind of pump. There is a central scene in Nausea in a park when

the root of a tree manifests itself as a bare individual unclassified

“thatness”—its pure existence is manifest devoid of its identification as

a neatly pigeon-holed sort of thing. The world is experienced as failing

252 Phenomenology and existentialism

to behave according to our ordering conceptualization of it, in virtue of

which we render what happens intelligible and explicable; that and the

rationally inexplicable excess both of the particular features of things

and existence itself generally induces the disorientating “nausea” of

which Sartre speaks. The picture we have of the world is that this

object, because it is of a specific kind, will do such-and-such; but in

Nausea Sartre depicts a world in which individual objects cease to act

according to their kind, because as individual objects they are not

exhausted by essences.

There is something else of importance that emerges in Nausea: that

we are free. We are free, and in Sartre’s sense “absurd”, in that, even

more than physical objects such as trees, we are not determined by an

essence; indeed we have no essence. Our existence (“thatness”)

precedes our essence (“whatness”): we first are, and it is then through

what we do that we give ourselves any “whatness” or defining identity.

We do not have a predetermined essence or nature that assigns to us a

place in the world and a given character: we are forced to be free and

make ourselves through our actions. We cannot pass the responsibility

for what we are to any objective standards that lie outside ourselves:

we must take responsibility for our choices, which determine what we

are. Awareness of the responsibility arising out of the truth that there is

no pre-existing self which is the “real I”, and that the self is identifiable

only through what we do following an initial, ultimately groundless,

choice, gives rise to Angst. The passing of responsibility for what we

do to something other than ourselves is what Sartre calls “inauthentic”

or living in “bad faith” (mauvaise foi); the abdication of our

responsibility for what we are and do Sartre sees as a kind of selfdeception;

it is as if really we know we are responsible for what we are

through what we choose to do, but we often fail to face that

uncomfortable truth. Freedom is not something we can avoid, but is an

inseparable part of being human. For example, by not killing ourselves

we choose to live. We cannot, of course, divorce ourselves from the

situations in which choices are made, but there is always some room

for free choice—even if it only consists of dissent and saying “no”.

Living with consciousness of the truth of my freedom is to live with

“authenticity”.

A person is never simply identifiable with any label applied to him

which aims to define his essence. Thus a waiter is a waiter in the

predicative sense of “is”, but that is not what he is in the identity sense

of “is”; being a waiter is not his essence—“person X=waiter” is false—

so what a person does is not logically determined by an essence.

Indeed, there is nothing that I am in the identity sense of “is”. What I

am is constantly remade through my actions: only in death is there the

possibility of final judgements being passed upon what kind of man I

am which I can no longer confute. The most blatantly “inauthentic”

life would be one in which I negate my own freedom altogether by

Sartre 253

regarding my self as being as fixed as an object; this may be because

that is how others regard me. An act of “bad faith” involves my simply

giving up any attempt to determine and take reponsibility for my

future because I regard a label I have given myself as binding on, and

sufficient to determine, what I will do; but such facts about me are

never sufficient to determine my actions, for I can always try to revolt

against the facts of my situation.

Nothing about the existentialist belief that we are free implies that

we should act wildly or capriciously, as is sometimes suggested, for to

choose to act wildly or capriciously is only one of the choices we can

make. What is important is that whatever choice we make is accepted

as our choice; we must take responsibility for it and its consequences. It

is in this way that our lives are said by the existentialist to be

“authentic”. Existentialism does not argue, as is again sometimes

suggested, that the aim should be to return to some inner “real self”,

for there is no sense to self other than the sum of what one does; rather

than there being a persistent self existing over time independently of

what one does, the self is constantly remade through action. The

notion of a self independent of actions would indeed be another route

to “bad faith”, for it suggests that I can do one thing but be another in

some inner sanctum of the “real self”. I cannot betray my friend, but

refuse to accept the kind of person that makes me, by saying that in my

“inner self” I was loyal to him, for the self—what I am—is constructed

out of the choices I make.

The attempt fully to rationalize the existing world of particular

concrete things in a system of abstract universal concepts or

“whatnesses” fails. Although any language which can function

descriptively cannot do without some degree of abstraction, we can

maximize the concrete and particular and not regard it as an inferior

view of the world to be “reduced” to something more universalizable.

The attempt to impose such a universally valid intelligible structure in

fact falsifies the world: it falsifies the uniqueness and particularity of

our experiences of, and our encounters with, the world. Even if we

merely say x and y are both red, we ignore the differences—perhaps

the shade of red—that make x and y distinct concrete particulars, and

so distort reality in the attempt to fit x and y into a scheme of

descriptive categories. The uniqueness and particularity of our

experiences are not to be rejected as worthless in favour of

considering the experiences as merely examples of certain general

classes or types.

The connected but distinct nature of consciousness and the world is

reflected in the ontology described in Sartre’s Being and nothingness.

The fundamental kinds of being there are underpin the notion that

consciousness cannot be an autonomous, isolated, “inner” realm

unrelated to the awareness of an existent objective world that is not a

part of consciousness, and the world has significance primarily as it

254 Phenomenology and existentialism

figures in human projects and actions. Sartre identifies two basic

categories or sorts of being.

(a) être-en-soi: being-in-itself. Things or non-human being.

(b) être-pour-soi: being-for-itself. Conscious or self-aware being.

However, he identifies an additional important category of being:

(c) être-pour-autrui: being-for-others. Being, especially of persons,

which arises from relations to others.

Together these are Sartre’s complete irreducible, uneliminable list of

sorts of being or ontological categories; these are what we are

committed to saying there must be, whatever else there may be, given

the nature or structure of consciousness.

Being-in-itself is the kind of being that inanimate, inert, non-human

objects have. In contrast being-for-itself is the kind of being that

consciousness has. The two are brought together as being-in- theworld.

Consciousness, the for-itself, arises only through its intentional

awareness of something other than itself; that is, it is awareness of the

in-itself, of not-consciousness, and that it is not the in-itself of which it

is aware. Sartre is anxious to maintain that consciousness is not any

kind of thing; consciousness is a negativity, a lack, or a no-thing-ness.

Consciousness is not-a-thing which arises as a negation of objects of

awareness. The primary nature of consciousness is its intentionality: it

depends for its existence on things other than itself of which it is

aware. Consciousness comes into being as an awareness of not being—

as a separateness from—the objects of which it is conscious. We are

conscious of an object X, and the being of consciousness is a negation

through a simultaneous awareness of not-being-X. Consciousness is

not an absolute nothingness, but is the awareness of itself as not

being—as not being absorbed into—whatever objects are objects of

consciousness. If I am aware of a table, the being of consciousness

consists in my self-awareness of not- being-a-table. In our awareness of

objects of consciousness we are at the same time pre-reflectively aware

of our being aware. Awareness of our own awareness or consciousness

cannot be a relation of subject and object or we would embark on an

infinite regress of awarenesses, and awareness of ourselves as aware

would never arise at all. To be conscious of X at all is to be conscious

that we are not-X, because the being of consciousness in our

consciousness of X is the consciousness of not-being-X. The logical

dependence of the existence of consciousness on something other than

itself ensures that it does not exist as an in-itself. Consciousness is not

some thing that can be separated from the world as a pure ego; rather,

consciousness and ego arise only in acts of awareness of objects and

awareness of the separateness from those objects. Consciousness arises

as a self-awareness of being not-the-objects-of-awareness; in this way

consciousness is a kind of nothingness or negation. Consciousness is

Sartre 255

not what it is and is what it is not, since it has yet unfulfilled potential

as to what it can be.

Sartre’s concept of the nature of consciousness ties in with his

concept of freedom. It is the nature of consciousness, the for-itself, that

it is not an object or thing. That our being is as not-a-thing frees us from

the causal nexus that determines the realm of the in-itself. There is no

fixed ego or self in the Cartesian sense and consciousness is not to be

identified with ego. The ego or self is our view of the sum of free

intentional choices consciousness has made in the past, so that what

the ego is can change in the future through its as yet unfulfilled or

potential free choices. We create our own essence—what we are—

through our choices and are therefore totally responsible for what we

are. We are our freedom; our “whatness” is our choice. “Bad faith”

arises when we treat the predicative “is” as to what we are—we are a

waiter, a soldier, a coward, a liar, a Frenchman—as if it were the “is” of

identity defining an essence, and abdicate our responsibility as to what

we do by virtue of an explanation following from our supposedly fixed

essential nature which, we might argue, is imposed upon us. The

overarching exemplification of “bad faith” is thus to see ourselves as an

object, as fixed: as a being-in-itself. Similarly it is “bad faith” to live as

though values and attitudes were derived from the world and not

derived from us. To overcome the Angst involved in our awareness of

our freedom we tend to retreat to the pretence that we have no choice

by adopting roles, characters, values and attitudes, as if they were

imposed upon us. I do not choose the condition or situation that is

forced on me from the outside, which is my “facticity”, but I am always

free in what I make of it. We try to fill our nothingness with actions to

define what we are, but what we are is always, unto death, incomplete,

since future choices characterizing the kind of persons we are always

remain open to us. Our incom-pleteness as a for-itself means we can be

free because we have the power, unlike the in-itself which is just what

it is, to be not what we are and to be what we are not.

With respect to being-for-others, Sartre first rejects the dualistic

presuppositions of the “problem of other minds”. The problem is said

to arise from the problematic inference from the bodily behaviour of

others to the hypothesis that they are conscious like ourselves. Sartre’s

dissolution of the problem denies that the bifurcation of other people

into body and mind in our experience is possible in the first place. We

immediately recognize important modes of our being—such as shame

and guilt—which are a result of existing in relation to other people and

depend on there being other people aware of us. In perceiving others

we immediately perceive them as persons, and this is a primitive

feature of our experience. There is no inference to “other minds” to

justify because such an inference does not occur at all.

Many of the most fundamental meanings of the human world, the

world-as-it-is-for-us, involve an intersubjectivity that depends on the

256 Phenomenology and existentialism

existence of other persons. The meanings that the world has for us

depend on the recognition of there being others. My experience of the

world as a public world, and of myself, in various important ways

depends on my acceptance of the existence of others. To deny the

existence of others would, among other things, be to abandon some of

the most fundamental ways in which the world and myself have

significance for me.

One of the basic ways in which I relate to others is through my

consciousness of being looked at by another person, which Sartre calls

“The Look” (Le Regard). My relation with others is a struggle not to be

fixed by The Look as an object for the other. The struggle is to maintain

my freedom when The Look of others fixes me as an identifiable

object. To preserve my freedom I may attempt to turn others into

objects for me and so attempt to destroy others as a source of The

Look. Thus each person is apparently a threat to the other’s freedom.

At the same time, however, my reflective (as opposed to pre-reflective)

self-consciousness arises only from my awareness of how others see

me. That I am ashamed of myself, for example, is necessarily

connected to my seeing myself as being seen by others doing

disreputable things. My self-consciousness derives from my taking

another’s view of my behaviour.

The mutual recognition of freedom is constantly compromised as

people fix others as objects. To fix another as someone who loves me,

for example, involves the paradox that, on the one hand, we wish the

love of the other to be unconditionally given, while on the other

hand, if it is to have its value as the love of another, it must be given

freely.

The ethical implications of Sartre’s philosophy are complex, but

central is existential freedom. Existentialism does not imply that one

should simply do what one likes and there are no moral considerations

guiding us; rather, it implies that what moral considerations we choose

to guide us are our responsibility. But that does not mean that what is

morally good or bad is itself dependent on mere individual subjective

appraisal or whim. Existentialism does not entail accepting that there

are no reasons or justifications for actions independently of subjective

predilections. If this were the case, then no moral dilemmas would

ever arise in my free choices; that such dilemmas do arise is clearly

something existentialism accepts and through which freedom to

choose is given its importance.

Since the notion of freedom and living an “authentic” life in the

awareness of that freedom are central to existentialist philosophy in

general, and values in particular, it is important to see whether any

fairly specific moral “directives” emerge from the notion of

“authenticity”. One point that emerges is that the notion of an

“authentic” life—one lived in awareness of freedom—is increased in

proportion as we are not aware of ourselves fixed as objects by others.

Sartre 257

But the strategy of evading the fixity ensuing from The Look of others

by in turn objectifying others is in the end self-defeating. For as I

regard others as objects, so I come to regard myself as an object like

them, which is the paradigm of “bad faith” or “inauthenticity”. This

seems to imply a moral directive on action concerning the treatment of

others whereby both we ourselves and others can collaborate in

maximizing the awareness of the freedom of our lives—their

“authenticity”—by increasing the extent to which we refuse to fix each

other as objects. We thereby move in the opposite direction from the

downward spiral of mutual objectification by trying not to start the

fixing of each other as objects in the first place. Whether actual human

relations with others can allow, or easily allow, such reciprocal support

of freedom, and if so what such relations would be like, are further

problems.

258 Phenomenology and existentialism

continued to ...

https://sites.google.com/site/philosophygreekancient/philosophy-and-philosophers---an-introduction-to-western-philosophy---chapter-10