Philosophy and Philosophers - an Introduction to Western Philosophy - Chapter 6

back to ...

https://sites.google.com/site/philosophygreekancient/philosophy-and-philosophers---an-introduction-to-western-philosophy---chapter-4

or ...

CHAPTER SIX

Transcendental idealism: Kant

The German philosopher Immanuel Kant was born in 1724 into the

midst of the European Enlightenment. The Enlightenment meant

different things in different countries, but certain common features can

be discerned. Kant referred to the Enlightenment as European man’s

coming of age; the assurance with which man had known his place in

the universe was being destroyed for ever. This did not mean the

replacement of one doctrine by another in which man could at least

find a place, no matter how unpleasant it might be; man was cast

adrift in a void, there to be dependent only on his own resources. The

Enlightenment questioned the right of anyone at all to claim a

monopoly of truth; this throws the decision as to what is the truth back

on the individual. The abandonment of authority as the source of truth

leads to a profound search as to the origins and justification of our

beliefs. The eighteenth century is marked by many embarking on this

search full of hope, confident that human reason has the capacity to

provide answers and discover truths. It led many thinkers who were

intelligent and honest in their deliberations to scepticism; an inability

to see how claims to human knowledge can be justified.

Developments in astronomy, with the work of Copernicus in the

sixteenth century, had already begun to undermine the medieval

edifice which gave man his defined place in the universe. The Great

Chain of Being, with God at its summit, stones at its base, and men

and angels in between, was dismembered. The Sun, not the Earth, was

the centre of our planetary system, situated in a universe of

unthinkable immensity and man was denied his privileged place in it.

Newton’s synthesis of the astronomy of Copernicus and Kepler, and

the terrestrial mechanics of Galileo, gave no one a privileged position;

laws of nature are objectively and uniformly true in all places. There

was also no need for a God to maintain the activity of the universe

157

since it was relatively autonomous, like a clock, and perhaps only

required someone to wind it up periodically; but this diminished

God’s influence to a point where He could be dispensed with, even if a

highly religious man such as Newton did not wish to do so. The

religious scientist must now serve God through the humble task of

uncovering the wonderful order bestowed upon the universe by the

Creator at its inception. However, a tension had now emerged in

discoveries that appeared to reveal the magnificent workmanship of

God’s universe, but that at the same time made belief in God optional,

since God’s intervention in the universe, except perhaps at the very

beginning, of which we knew nothing, was not required in explanation

as it had been before.

Out of the Enlightenment we may evolve a criterion separating the

religious from the non-religious, a criterion based on a more

fundamental notion than the existence and authority of God. This can

be based on whether it is thought that the universe has some special

place or concern (negative or positive) for human beings. It is a

universe unresponsive to all human values, one to which human

values are simply not applicable, an amoral universe, that gives rise to

the crisis begun for man in the Enlightenment. Some reject this aspect

of the Enlightenment and continue in acceptance of God, although for

many it can never be quite the same; others embrace the idea of an

entirely amoral universe, and suffer the problems of discovering what,

if anything, can then have value; still others act merely as if the

universe still responds to human values; they live under the shadow

cast by a figure that has already left the scene.

It would be wrong to think of all the most revolutionary intellectual

figures before and during the Enlightenment as free-thinking atheists;

some of the most important figures were Copernicus, Descartes,

Locke, Spinoza, Newton, Leibniz, Berkeley, Kant, and all were

religious men to varying degrees and in different ways, men often

profoundly worried about where their thought seemed inexorably to

be taking them; this sometimes forced them to take rearguard action

against the consequences of their own thoughts. They all contributed

to the complete change in man’s world-view, whether they intended

to or not.

Kant both benefited from, and went beyond, the Enlightenment (die

Aufklärung). After an initial immersion in the rationalist philosophy of

Leibniz, Kant could no longer accept it; under the influence of Hume,

and the German Crusius, Kant says he was woken from his dogmatic

slumbers. Another powerful influence on Kant was Newton. Before

devoting himself to philosophy, Kant had been a scientist; he saw the

effect that a Newtonian view of the universe was going to have on

morality, God, and our freewill. For if Newtonian views were

universally and rigorously applied, they left little place for God, and

undermined morality in fundamental ways: a Newtonian universe was

158 Transcendental idealism

an amoral mechanical system in which objective values seemed to

have no application; man himself was an entity subject to the universal

remorseless laws of nature, whose actions were absolutely determined

by events that had already occurred, and which were thereby always

outside his control; whatever we may feel about the matter, we are not

free to choose, and where there is no freedom there is no responsibility

for action, and thus there can be no moral evaluations. A tree is not

free to choose, despite being alive; so when it falls on someone, the

event is neither moral nor immoral, it is amoral, just something that

happens. Human actions were now in danger of becoming just things

that happen.

Kant tried to respond to all these influences, and reconcile them in a

new synthesis. The empiricism of Hume had, it seemed to many, led to

scepticism about human knowledge, identity and freedom, and Kant

could not accept this. The rationalist view argued that there were

innate principles of the understanding or reason with which man

could a priori comprehend the basic nature of the world, although not

the world of appearances, but a real world that lies behind

appearances which ultimately explains those appearances. Hume

undermined this by showing that these principles either were

analytic—restating what, in disguised form, had already been

assumed—or went beyond being analytic and could not therefore be

justified by reason alone; but Hume found they could not then be

justified by experience either. There was no midway course for

empiricism.

Kant set out to show that these views could be reconciled; he tried

to show why the true nature of the relationship between experience

and the world is such that we can know things about the world of

appearances a priori—truths knowable independently of the evidence

of experience—although we can have no a priori knowledge of a real

world beyond appearances. Kant wants to show that we can know

certain truths a priori which are not trivial logical truths known

merely because of their formal structure. We can know the truth “If p

then q, p, therefore q” a priori precisely because we can substitute

uniformly any propositions we like for p and q; but for that same

reason such logical deductions can, independently of experience, tell

us nothing about the world. Our ability to know them a priori derives

precisely from the fact that they commit us to nothing about the

actual world. Kant thinks he can show how we can know universal

necessary truths a priori about the world as it appears, although not

the world as it is in itself.

Kant draws an analogy between his own revolution in philosophy

and that of the Copernican revolution in astronomy, but only in the

following respect: Copernicus had dared to suggest that some of the

motions of the heavenly bodies were only apparent and were as a

result of the motion of the observer. Similarly Kant suggests that

Kant 159

some of the properties we ascribe to external objects are a result of

constructive mental processes to which appearances have to conform.

The philosophy propounded by Kant also attempts to be universally

valid in covering all self-conscious rational beings. Kant proposes

that our experience involves elements partly contributed by us, and

partly by the world; this does not mean our conception of the world

is merely subjective in being true only from a particular point of

view, or that it is absolutely objective, since the conception of the

world cannot be separated completely from ways that we experience

the world.

Kant

Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) was born in the Prussian town of

Königsberg, into a pietist Lutheran family; there he became Professor

of Logic and Metaphysics in 1770, at the age of forty-six.

Kant is frequently seen as almost a caricature of the popular

conception of a philosopher; outwardly his life was the very model of

the fastidious, studious, self-contained philosophical speculator. There

is no doubt that like many original people he was capable of great acts

of self-discipline. Yet he was not an unsociable man, or an

unentertaining lecturer; he was fond of female company, although he

never married. He never ventured many miles from Königsberg. His

life is therefore depicted as being, on the whole, dull and uneventful.

This may well be true; we should temper this somewhat patronizing

conclusion by reflecting that many of us do not have lives a great deal

more exciting. Near the end of his life, when he had already been

withdrawn from society for some time, Kant’s intellectual powers

crumbled; he failed to recognize friends, and he was virtually blind;

yet those closest to him still had glimpses of his good nature and will

power, and of the great philosopher behind the shell of the man that

remained.

A discussion of Kant’s epistemology and metaphysics naturally

centres upon the Critique of pure reason, his most complete thinking on

these subjects. An additional work on the same subjects is the

Prolegomena. Kant published many other works on science, aesthetics,

and on ethics.

Kant, to some extent, saw himself as solving the errors committed

by Hume and Leibniz. Hume’s philosophy has been interpreted by

some as collapsing into scepticism; central claims for human

knowledge, which are logically presupposed by natural science, are

found to be unjustifiable on the basis of his empiricist philosophy

whereby all such claims must be rationally justified either by pure

reason a priori or by the evidence of experience a posteriori. Neither is

found to provide such rational justification, although nature takes

160 Transcendental idealism

care that we nevertheless hold the required fundamental beliefs. Not

only did our common-sense beliefs about the world become

unsupportable, but the most powerful intellectual achievement of the

day, Newtonian mechanics, was also undermined. Newtonian

mechanics seemed to give a complete unifying explanation of the

workings of the universe; it was revolutionary in regarding the

universe not as operating under special laws for different regions, but

as being unified throughout under one objective set of laws. Kant saw

this as supremely worth defending against Hume’s scepticism.

Knowledge for Kant, as for Leibniz, had to be necessary and

universally valid. Hume undermined this, leaving us with knowledge

of the world, in so far as we could have any at all, which was

subjective, particular and contingent. The most important basic beliefs

about the world could not be justified by reason, but if we examined

closely what we actually experienced—the information provided by

experience—they could not be justified by experience either. The most

important basic beliefs in question were: the belief that the world

operates by necessary causal laws, so we can make inference beyond

what we presently perceive to unobserved cases; the belief that there

exist independent continuously existing objects; and the belief that

there is a continuous self. In short, empiricism, with its adherence to

the view that experience must be the sole source of evidence about the

world, led to scepticism when it was found that experience in itself, if

carefully examined, was not sufficient to justify some of our most

basic beliefs about the world.

Kant was convinced both that, contrary to Leibniz, knowledge of

the world had always to be concerned with the world of our

experience, not a reality beyond appearances, and that, contrary to

Hume, the senses were not alone as a means of justifying our

knowledge of such a world. The way out of this is to deny that

sensation and experience are one and the same. Kant’s basic idea is a

distinction between form and content; the form of our experience is

knowable a priori, the content is given a posteriori, and only in

combination can these provide knowledge of the world. We could not

have knowledge of a world other than the experienced one; but

sensation alone could not support our claims to knowledge. Sensation

is always particular, changing and subjective, and our knowledge

claims are general, universal, unchanging and objective. Leibniz was

impressed by the power of mathematics; maintaining a distrust of the

senses as a source of knowledge that led back to Plato, Leibniz sought

a metaphysics that describes the fundamental or underlying nature of

the world beyond appearances, which was independent of the

evidence of experience, based on a few basic principles; the world of

appearances is explained ultimately through the reality that lies

behind it; it is this reality which is the metaphysical foundation for all

other knowledge of the world. This is not to say Leibniz thought that

Kant 161

humans could deduce all scientific laws from a priori metaphysical

principles; such a priori principles are too general and the a priori

principles and reason describe not appearances but the reality

underlying those appearances. Metaphysics seeks to describe what the

world must fundamentally be like if it is fully rationally explicable.

Kant thought Newtonian mechanics explained not a reality behind

appearances, but those appearances themselves; the question was how

this was possible in the light of Hume’s attack on our ability to justify

through examining our sensations the kind of necessary universal laws

Newton proposed, and the application of such laws to experience. It

could not be achieved through Leibniz’s philosophy, for Hume had

also shown that the machinations of pure reason alone could not

generate any new knowledge concerning what is actual; a pure logical

argument unpacks only items that are already contained in its

premises. The finite ability of the human mind may give us the

impression that something new is arising; but it is already there; for

God there would be no point in doing mathematics, or logic, or

playing chess; He would already know all the consequences.

There were other intellectual structures that Kant thought it

necessary to defend: Euclidean geometry, absolute space, continuous

infinite time, the applicability of mathematics in explaining the

world. Underlying Newtonian mechanics especially are the concepts

of causality and substance. Each area of human inquiry has its limits;

one Newtonian limit consisted in not questioning the existence of

matter, but instead concentrating on how all posited matter behaves.

But without the establishment in reality of a general concept of an

independent, self-subsisting stuff, Newtonian mechanics is left

entirely hypothetical: if the world is a certain way then these are the

laws of its behaviour. In addition the justification of general laws as

such had to be attempted: universal causality, which allows us to go

beyond seeing that this follows that to saying that this always causes

that, and so make inferences to cases we have not observed. Hume

thought that rational justification for our beliefs could lie only in

either reason or experience; but neither reason nor experience could

justify our belief in an external world of bodies, substance, causality,

or the self of personal identity; we could only show how they in fact

arise as natural beliefs in response to the experiences we have. It is

just these general concepts or categories that Kant aims to show we

are justified in applying necessarily and objectively to the world we

experience, although that application could not be justified, or

refuted, by experience.

It must be emphasized that Kant thought that in some areas of

human inquiry some final answers had been generated. The world did

obey Newton’s laws, Aristotle’s logic said all there was to say about

logic; space was Euclidean and three-dimensional, time was classical

and stretched like an infinite straight line towards the future and back

162 Transcendental idealism

into the past; causality did apply universally. All these things have

been questioned by modern thinking; Einstein questioned Newtonian

space, time, and motion; quantum mechanics questioned universal

causality; modern logic generated a richer array of theorems, making

Aristotelean logic a small fragment of it. Kant was not narrow-minded,

but Newton’s world-view in particular was so powerful and allencompassing

in its unified explanations of a vastly diverse range of

phenomena that to be overwhelmed by its finality was

understandable. Nor must we let Kant’s adherence to these particular

theories detract from his important and revolutionary views.

Kant’s Critique is, roughly, divided into two parts: the Analytic and

the Dialectic; the Analytic includes the Aesthetic. The word “aesthetic”

derives from a Greek word aesthesis relating to perception by the

senses. The special Kantian sense of “Aesthetic” concerns the a priori

form or order necessarily imposed by our capacity to receive

representations—our sensibility—on the material supplied by the

senses. The form or order is a priori and necessary, and Kant discovers

it by subtraction of both the material of sensation and the concepts

contributed by the faculty of understanding. These pure forms of

sensible intuition or of experiences turn out to be space and time. The

Analytic is largely positive; in it are determined the a priori principles

of the understanding; we are also shown the proper use of

metaphysics in providing the basis for our objective knowledge. The

Dialectic is largely negative. We are shown the misuse of metaphysics

in using concepts to go beyond what we can possibly experience, to a

world of illusion and contradiction; we are also shown why we are

prone to be tempted to this kind of speculation. The Aesthetic and

Analytic give us a metaphysics of experience; they display what must

be the basic features of experience and reasoning. The Dialectic shows

how we err when we attempt to extend our knowledge beyond that

which it is possible for us to experience.

We now turn to examining some well-used terms in Kant’s

Critique. These divide into three pairs: a priori/a posteriori, analytic/

synthetic, necessary/contingent. First we distinguish a priori

statements, which once understood can logically be known to be true

prior to, and independently of, the evidence of experience, from a

posteriori statements, which once understood can logically be known

to be true only by the evidence of experience. Analytic statements are

true in virtue of the meanings of the terms in the statements and are

known to be true merely by understanding the meanings of the terms

contained in the statements; synthetic statements cannot be known

just by examining the meaning of the terms in the statements.

Generally speaking, although it is this that Kant will question,

necessary statements (those that must always be true or must always

be false) are a priori analytic, and contingent statements (those that

may be true or may be false) are a posteriori synthetic. Thus, “All

Kant 163

bachelors are unmarried” is a priori analytic; we can know it to be

true without consulting our experience, nor could any experience

refute it, for the meaning of “bachelor” includes “unmarried”; if

someone was suggested to us as an example of a bachelor who was

married, we would respond by explaining how we define “bachelor”,

not by seeking empirical evidence. Analytic truths are those truths

whose denial is contradictory; the predicate “unmarried” is

contained in the concept of the subject term “bachelor”. However,

“All bachelors admire Kant” may be true, or it may be false; the way

we find out is by empirically investigating bachelors; it certainly is

not part of the definition of the term “bachelor” that an admiration

or otherwise for Kant should come into it, and so it cannot be known

to be true a priori.

Hume thought that the only necessary propositions were analytic

ones (mathematics, for example); but the price we pay for our only

pieces of necessary truth is that they are quite empty; they tell us

nothing about the world. They simply unravel linguistic definitions.

Logical truths such as “not-(p and not-p)” are known to be true a priori

precisely because they exhibit a universally valid form which is devoid

and independent of content; any proposition could be substituted for

p, therefore the whole expression can tell us nothing about the actual

contingent world. Logic alone can tell us only what is necessary,

impossible or possible, not what is actual and contingent: that which

is, but might have been otherwise. Hume argues that all our

knowledge of the world must come from the senses; but all we can

generate from that source is contingent particular statements which

cannot support general necessary statements, such as the reality of

universal causation, the truth of universal laws, the real existence of an

independent constant external world. If we observe A followed by B,

we note that we perceive no necessary connection between A and B,

which is an essential part of the belief that A causes B, that would

justify saying B must always follow A; but this is the form of universal

laws of nature and the basis of any inferences from the observed to the

unobserved.

The disagreement between empiricists such as Hume and

rationalists such as Leibniz centres on whence our knowledge of the

world derives, on what knowledge of truths about the world logically

depends, and on the emptiness of analytic propositions. In general, the

issue is that of the informativeness of truths knowable independently

of the evidence of experience: whether such truths can tell us anything

about reality. The rationalists see analytic truths and deductive

reasoning as an a priori source of knowledge, admittedly not of the

ephemeral world just as we experience it, but of the reality behind

those experiences. Leibniz has a problem maintaining any a posteriori

synthetic truths at all, since he thinks all truths concerning underlying

reality must ultimately be analyzable into the subject-predicate form

164 Transcendental idealism

and be analytic. Unlike the rationalists, the empiricists see analytic

truths as empty or trivial statements, which can tell us nothing about

the actual contingent nature of the world.

Kant found himself agreeing and disagreeing with both parties. He

agrees with the empiricists, and disagrees with the rationalists, that a

priori analytic truths are empty, and that our knowledge must be of the

world we can experience; but he also thinks that we can know

necessary and universal a priori truths that tell us something about the

real or actual world of experience. Kant agrees with the rationalists

that not all a priori knowledge is empty, but disagrees that this

knowledge can be of a world behind appearances. The answer for Kant

is the existence of propositions that are synthetic a priori and in some

way necessary; these truths, knowable prior to the evidence of

experience, are irrefutable by any experience, and yet they go beyond

the mere meaning of the terms used in expressing them and determine

a priori certain truths concerning the world as experienced. The

necessity and universality of the truth of synthetic a priori judgements

cannot derive from their being analytic and their denial implying a

logical contradiction; they must be necessary and universal truths for

some other reason. Kant’s positive project, his transcendental

philosophy, is to show how it can be possible to know truths a priori

which are necessarily true of the world as it appears, but which are not

necessary by merely being analytic. Such a synthetic a priori truth is

that every event has a cause.

The term “transcendental” does a lot of work in Kant’s philosophy.

Generally whatever is transcendental is not derived from, or justifiable

or refutable by, experience, yet is applicable to, or is a condition for, all

experience. Transcendental knowledge is knowledge not of objects, but

knowledge of the necessary a priori conditions of our cognition of

objects. Kant uses the term to denote the a priori factors in our

knowledge.

Kant analyzes experience and understanding in order to justify

objective knowledge. Intuitions consist of sensations which are

necessarily subject to the forms of space and time; sensations are a

posteriori and space and time are supplied a priori by our sensibility or

capacity to receive representations; but sensation is not separable from

those a priori conditions. Space is the form of outer sense, of objects in

the external world, whereas time is the form of both outer and inner

sense—our inner experience necessarily only involves succession in

time. Space and time are the a priori forms of our sensibility as a whole.

These pure forms of our intuitions are analogous to filters on a camera:

the only images formed are ones that have passed through or been

subject to the filters. The pure forms of intuition are not empirical: they

are not derived from experience, rather they are the necessary form of

all experience. Nor are space and time concepts, for there can be no

object (like a table) corresponding to space and time in general. Kant

Kant 165

further holds that the pure intuition of space is presupposed by

geometry, and that of time is presupposed by arithmetic.

In addition to this, knowledge, as opposed to the mere having of

experiences, involves the use of the basic concepts or categories of the

faculty of the understanding. The knowledge that what we see is a

table involves having and applying the concept of a table by a

judgement of the understanding, not just seeing something in space

and time. Furthermore our understanding necessarily operates with

certain basic concepts or categories. Knowledge is possible through the

conjunction of actual intuitions with the necessary categories of the

faculty of understanding. The senses alone are literally thoughtless; the

understanding alone is contentless.

A summary of the nature of intuitions, and the relation between

them and concepts of the understanding producing knowledge, can be

given in the following diagram.

There is a sharp distinction between the intellectual and sensory

elements in human knowledge. The mind is active in understanding

nature, not a passive receptacle waiting to be filled by experiences.

Transcendental philosophy does not give us particular scientific

knowledge of the world we experience; but the transcendental

deduction shows how we can know the necessary a priori elements

166 Transcendental idealism

presupposed by such scientific knowledge of the world as experienced.

For example, we cannot know a priori that A is the cause of B—that is a

matter for scientific empirical investigation; but it can be known a

priori that B has some cause—that much can be proved by

transcendental philosophy.

Kant was well aware of the distinction, said to be confused in the

work of some earlier philosophers, between the origin (quid facti) of

something, and its justification (quid juris). The revealing of the origin

or genesis of a truth or belief has to be distinguished from whether the

truth or belief can be known a priori or a posteriori. The origin concerns

facts about psychology; the question of whether a proposition is a

priori or a posteriori concerns what logical type the proposition is.

Propositions that can be shown to follow deductively from certain

logically necessary premises can be known independently of the

evidence of experience, since their denial would imply a logical

contradiction; but some truths can be known only by consulting the

evidence of experience, even if the belief in the truth happens to be

psychologically innate. I may have been born with the belief, which is

true, that “There are lions in Africa”; but the conditions for the belief

being true depend on facts about Africa; knowledge of those facts,

and hence knowledge of the truth of the proposition describing those

facts, can be justified only by experience of Africa; it could not be

proved a priori by deductive reasoning or a priori by merely

understanding the meaning of the terms in the proposition that

expresses the belief. To show that something is psychologically a priori

does not show it to be a priori valid or true, still less that its truth is

knowable a priori.

Kant was not engaged in speculative empirical psychology. If Kant

can justify the necessity of the application of the forms of space and

time, and the categories, to the world, he will have achieved a great

deal. In the first case we have, for example, justified, and explained,

applied mathematics; in the second we have justified concepts

essential to science, for example, substance, causality, plurality, unity

and the like.

Running through Kant’s philosophy is a distinction between form

and content. The form of experience is knowable a priori; the content or

filling is given to us and is knowable a posteriori; but the two elements

are not simply separable. The form of our intuitions is space and time,

the forms of our understanding or thought are the categories. In actual

intuitions, sensations and space and time are not separable; in actual

knowledge, intuitions and categories are not separable. This idea is

essential to understanding Kant’s transcendental idealism: his notion

of objectivity is designed to counter empirical idealism, which is the

position that our knowledge is only subjectively valid concerning the

content of our own minds.

The “schemata”, which are kinds of restricting frameworks, are

Kant 167

required to give rules for applying the categories, for the concepts of

the understanding in their pure form are never met in intuitions; we

must take the pure concepts and form schematisms by which

particular intuitions can be identified as falling under pure concepts. If

we take the example of the category of substance as that which is

always a subject of predication and is never predicated of another

subject, the schema of substance is that which is permanent in time

while other things change. The schema of necessity is the existence of

an object at all times. The schema of causality is the succession of real

things according to a rule. Time is presupposed a priori in our

experiencing things existing simultaneously or successively; and it is

indeed temporal existence that is the primary condition to which

schemata of the a priori imagination must conform. It is the schema

which ensures that the categories are applied only to objects of

possible experience; the understanding is effectively limited to

experience (intuitions of our sensibility) by requiring that the

application of the pure concepts is through schemata which involve

the a priori pure form of inner intuition (time) and outer intuition

(space); that is, the categories are limited to objects in time and space.

Thus the categories become more than pure or formal logical truths,

but come to have objects to which they apply; they come to tell us

something a priori about the objects of possible experience, that is,

possible intuitions. Through the methodological adoption of the

mechanism of schemata, reason does not attempt to describe a world

beyond or behind all possible experience; in this case it is not a world

which is as a matter of fact out of reach of all experience from which

we exclude ourselves, but rather a world which is necessarily out of

reach of all possible experience. What is denied is “transcendent”

knowledge: knowledge of things-in-themselves or, in Kant’s

terminology, noumena beyond the conditions for all experiences. For

example, it can be said to be possible to experience atoms, although in

fact they are too small to see (at least with the naked eye); whereas it is

impossible that we should experience timelessness or eternity, since all

experiences are in time as they involve succession; nor is it possible to

conceive of a spaceless world.

We can see the categories as the highest point of a hierarchy of

classificatory and ordering concepts. We use the concept “tree”, which

falls under the concept “plant”, which is an “object”, which is

subsumed under “substance”, something that is separable and can

remain the same while undergoing certain sorts of changes. We can

conceive of a world as experienced to which the lower and more

particular concepts do not apply—a world without trees, in which the

concept “tree” is not applied in our judgements—but we cannot

conceive of a world to which the concepts of something that can

endure through change, universal causality, plurality and unity do not

apply. The same applies to the other twelve in the table of categories.

168 Transcendental idealism

I

Quantity

Unity

Plurality

Totality

II III

Quality Relation

Reality Substance and accident

Negation Cause and effect

Limitation Reciprocity

IV

Modality

Possibility and impossibility

Existence and non-existence

Necessity and contingency

These are the categories with which we must think if we think about

the world at all, and they must therefore be presupposed in, apply to,

any way the world can appear to us and be involved in all judgement

and knowledge.

In the metaphysical deduction of categories, Kant tries to

demonstrate how the categories arise from general logic—from

different kinds of logical judgements. However, Kant’s exposition is

unusually terse. The judgement “Some S is P” (“Some cows are black’)

involves concepts; it involves the concept of plurality, since it involves

two terms, it involves the concept of reality, since it states something is.

Perhaps of greater importance to the modern reader is the

transcendental deduction, for here we have an argument that attempts

to justify the application of categories as such; that there are concepts

we necessarily have to apply to experience, whatever these concepts

specifically turn out to be. The sense of “deduction” in the

transcendental deduction is more akin to a defence in law than an

argument in formal logic.

The transcendental deduction runs as follows. The aim of the

transcendental deduction is to show not only that there are categories

or concepts we necessarily apply to our experience, but also that that

experience must be such that in applying the categories we can be said

to be making objective judgements, or judgements about objects. The

absolutely minimum condition for experiences which are something to

me is that the experiences are subject to a synthesis such that they are

all part of one consciousness. To say that experiences are thus united is

equivalent to the condition of apperception, that is, the experiences are

possible objects of self-consciousness; it must be possible for the “I

think” to accompany all my representations. The “I” here is not

empirical self-consciousness; sometimes I reflect, and sometimes I do

Kant 169

not; it is the transcendental unity of apperception: the unity given by

the mere possibility of my being self-conscious of whatever

experiences I have. For this apperception to make sense it is necessary

that I am aware of something which is not-self, objects which have a

unity and independence of their own, distinct from my self; if they

were not thus independent, I would not be engaged in an act of selfconsciousness

at all. The items on which I reflect in self-consciousness,

that is, the items of my consciousness, are not-self and are therefore

objects; they have objectivity. Now to reflect at all is to apply concepts;

to say, for example, “x now”, “there are more xs than ys”, “x is

different from y”, “x again”, “y has got bigger”; in reflection concepts

must be applied, so what presents itself could not be a totally

disordered stream of sensation, each item utterly unrelated to any

other. In the final step, having shown we necessarily apply concepts,

Kant, due to his faith in his metaphysical deduction, thinks he has

shown that it must be just those concepts or categories deduced in the

metaphysical deduction that we apply.

To sum up: consciousness is a uniting of intuitions, the condition

for this is possible self-consciousness; the condition for selfconsciousness

is awareness of objects, or objective experiences

(experiences under categories); the objects of conciousness on which

we reflect in self-consciousness are therefore subject to concepts (are

objects having order intrinsic to them); and if we must apply concepts,

the categories revealed in the metaphysical deduction must be the

concepts we apply.

Kant equivocates about the nature of objects, items of which we

can claim to be able to make judgements independent of the

particular state of the subject. Whether the objectivity granted by the

categories as the necessary universally valid conditions for all

experience is enough to give us everything we expect of an object,

and an objective world, is open to dispute. But the transcendental

deduction attempts to justify the application of the categories by all

rational consciousnesses, not just the human mind. There cannot be

forms of understanding quite different from our own. Kant does

allow that there could be forms of sensible intuition other than our

own human forms.

Hume correctly thought we could not derive an abiding self from

the flux of perceptions open to introspection; but Kant argues that the

ability to introspect at all assumes a self or subject which has the

experience, for we say, “This is my experience”; it must be possible for

the “I think” to accompany all my representations. But I can think only

according to the categories; so there can be no experience such that it is

not subject in my judgement to the categories, since then there would

be experiences of mine which could not be accompanied by “I think”,

which is impossible. The awareness of self derives from the awareness

of our power to unite representations in one consciousness.

170 Transcendental idealism

This creates for Kant the possibility of objective knowledge of the

world; knowledge must include experience, and we necessarily have

to apply the categories which give the form of that experience.

Whereas Kant’s argument may have justified the application of

necessary conditions for experience—some set of categories or other—

it is not clear that he has justified the application of all and only those

categories he lists in particular; that would follow only if we accepted

the metaphysical deduction.

This has led some to update the categories but maintain their

necessity; it has led still others to update them but to abandon their

necessity. The second of these positions seems to abandon the point of

Kant’s transcendental idealism, for then the categories are neither

universal (for they apply only to human cognition) nor necessary (not

transcendentally necessary but psychological facts). On the other hand,

the first position has great difficulty generating categories which at

once can be shown to apply necessarily to any comprehensible world,

while at the same time avoiding the triviality of being entirely vacuous

and non-specific.

Interpretations of Kant’s transcendental idealism vary. One view

asserts that we have obtained objective knowledge because the

categories have been demonstrated to have universal inter subjectivity.

Another view suggests that Kant has to show that there is a world of

objects existing independent of us in some further sense than the

world we experience and know, necessarily conforming to the

categories which are not thereby merely arbitrary and subjective. But

this destroys Kant’s position by asking him to accomplish the

impossible. We cannot possibly know that objects in themselves,

distinct from how they are experienced or appear to us, are organized

according to the categories, but we can know that objects as they

appear or the world-as-experienced must be organized according to

the categories, since the way objects appear partly depends on

ourselves and we must apply the categories in thinking about what we

experience. The world, or nature, just is the sum of possible

experiences; the world of phenomena. Noumena, or things-inthemselves

(Dinge-an-sich), are not objects of experience; they stand

proxy for a world beyond appearances that is unknowable; this realm

is nothing to do with the world as studied by science. Noumenon is

not, it must be emphasized, the atomic world, or anything where our

lack of actual experience of it is purely a matter of accidental

contingent fact. The atomic world exists straightforwardly (or so it

seemed in Kant’s day) in space and time, even if the laws governing its

behaviour are discovered indirectly by its effects; our inability to

observe atoms directly is an empirical, not a transcendental, limit to

our experience. The appearance/reality distinction is not between

phenomena/ noumena, but between the variant/invariant features of

our experience. To suggest that we can still look around the edge of all

Kant 171

our experiences, dropping our form of cognition, to a world untainted

by that form, to see if the categories actually apply, is to attempt what

Kant denies is possible, and to abandon precisely the ground from

whence the objectivity of the categories arises. The categories which

we bring to experience cannot be abandoned, for they are present

whenever we have an intelligence capable of self-conscious thought.

Kant says his position supports empirical realism and refutes

idealism. Whatever we may think of Kant’s arguments, he cannot be

defending empirical realism in the form of knowledge of objects

devoid of our form of understanding; to think otherwise is to miss the

point. If we tried to apply Kant’s views to objects totally independent

of our, and all intelligent, modes of understanding, Kant could never

have hoped to justify the necessary application of categories; there

would always be an unbridgeable gap between the way we think and

what we think about; we would never be able to show the categories

applied to reality in this sense, rather than merely indicating how we

have to think about the world. If any conception of reality is

inseparable from mind, then there is a possibility of explaining why

our basic intellectual structures—causality, substance, plurality, and

the like—must actually apply. The point is that as far as we are

concerned, transcendental idealism delivers all that a bald empirical

realism supposes to be the case; these two positions are in that sense

equivalent and indistinguishable. A logically or transcendentally

inescapable perspective is equivalent to an objective view. Universal

objectively valid knowledge, invariant with, and not requiring

qualifying reference to, the state of the subject, is squared with the

argument that there cannot be a perspectiveless world-view of thingsin-themselves

through the establishment of the categories and forms of

intuition as transcendentally necessary and objective for all possible

appearances in being invariant with the experiencing subject. There is

then no perspectiveless position from which the rational perspective

itself can be checked; if the perspective is thereby universal it is also

necessary and objective and independent of the individual subjective

perspective.

This is not the only interpretation of Kant’s position, and Kant

himself was not entirely consistent or clear; he plainly felt uneasy

about it. Kant sometimes speaks as if noumena are the unknowable

causes of our experiences.

Kant attacks in the Dialectic the possibility of knowledge

transcending experience and its a priori form or conditions to attempt

to gain knowledge of unconditioned noumena, a perspectiveless view

of things-in-themselves. Kant is setting the necessary presupposition of

all human knowledge and so marking the bounds of legitimate

inquiry. The Dialectic is the logic of illusion. That is not to say that we

cannot think beyond the bounds of possible experience; we can form

concepts—for example of substance—to think about that which exists

172 Transcendental idealism

beyond our possible intuitions, and so outside space and time; but

knowledge is not possible.

Noumena are unknowable; we can speak of noumena only

negatively: we can say what they are not as compared to phenomena

that we can experience, since we can say that none of our concepts can

be positively applied to characterize noumenon. It is indeed unclear if

we can legitimately talk of either noumenon in the singular or

noumena in the plural, since the first involves the category of unity

and the second that of plurality. Whatever is the case, noumenon, or

the thing-in-itself, is reality in the sense of being independent of all

conceptual determinations which apply necessarily to the world as

experienced; and, since all knowledge involves applying concepts,

things-in-themselves are unknowable.

Illusory metaphysics which aims at knowledge has three main

subjects: God, and proofs for the existence of God; freedom, which

connects with cosmology; immortality, which connects with the soul.

Metaphysical speculation which aims at knowledge of truths

concerning these subjects has been endless, fruitless and contradictory.

In contrast to physical science, disputes seem undecidable. As Kant

says, it has involved “deluding the adventurous seafarer ever anew

with empty hopes, and engaging him in enterprises which he can

never abandon and yet is unable to carry to completion”. Kant wants

to show why this is so, and put an end to it. This is the overall aim of

Kant’s “critical philosophy”.

Kant sets about this demonstration in the Antinomies. The strategy

is, after taking some matter about which we illegitimately aim to know,

to present a pair of equally logically compelling arguments from which

are derived a thesis and antithesis which are mutually exclusive and

collectively exhaustive alternatives. The conclusions cannot both be

true, but we have no way of knowing which is true and which false.

The proof of the thesis and antithesis is by reductio ad absurdum:

showing that denying an assertion leads to an impossibility, thus

demonstrating the truth of the assertion. Kant presents four

Antinomies: first, the finitude or infinitude in space and time of the

universe; secondly, the finite or infinite divisibility of substance;

thirdly, whether there is freedom or no freedom; fourthly, whether

there exists an absolutely necessary being or not. These matters are

undecidable by human reason, since we are presented with equally

convincing conclusions which are mutually contradictory. However, to

agree that the Antinomies show this, we would have to accept the

arguments for each thesis and antithesis in each Antinomy as equally

valid; unfortunately their quality is variable.

Hegel (1770–1831) was to suggest that the opposing conclusions of

Kant’s Antinomies indicate not the limits of human reason, but the

need for a synthesis which somehow encompasses the conflicting

conclusions as to the nature of reality.

Kant 173

Arguments for the existence of God are classified in three ways:

physico-theological, cosmological, ontological. The physico-theological

is basically the argument from design, whereby, if an orderly clock

needs a clockmaker, the world surely needs a worldmaker. Hume had

attacked this argument on the grounds that if the clock/world analogy

was weak, then the world might not need a maker; if the analogy was

strong, then the worldmaker was no better than a clockmaker, and

need not be a God at all. The cosmological argument harks back to the

ancient unmoved-mover argument of a first cause required to start the

universe off; this is already implicitly undermined in the Antinomies.

The most significant attack is upon the ontological argument. Here

God’s existence is said to be deducible from the concept of God; God is

perfection, it is more perfect to exist than not to exist, therefore the

perfect being must exist. Kant’s refutation of this proof rests on

arguing that “existence” is not a descriptive predicate adding anything

to the meaning or concept of a subject, so that to say something exists

does not therefore attribute an additional property to a subject at all;

rather it merely says that there is something to which the concept of

the subject applies. We do not add an additional property, after we

have listed all the attributes of Kant, by saying Kant exists; rather it is

to say that all the properties of Kant—shortness, thin body,

philosopher, etc.—actually have an instance.

Kant was concerned that he had, in a sense, done his job of

providing necessary metaphysical foundations too well; especially

with reference to the universally valid application of causality to

phenomena, it seemed as if there was no place left for human freedom.

Kant replies through an analysis of the self. Although the world of

phenomena may be determined by the causal laws of physics and

transcendental concepts, the noumenal world beyond experience is

not. Kant’s answer is to posit a noumenal-self, or transcendental-self,

which is “outside” the phenomenal world; man viewed as noumenon

can therefore act freely according to the moral law. The transcendentalself

is the only transcendental object we have access to; here our

perspective and a perspectiveless view become one and the same; the

distinction between appearance and reality can be eliminated. This

explanation of freedom leaves too many questions in obscurity to be

satisfactory; moreover, because the moral law governs the operation of

the noumenal-self, it fails to explain how we could ever act wrongly. If

it is maintained that the operation of the noumenal-self originates

totally spontaneously, then it amounts to nothing more than a

reassertion of belief in freewill. In any event Kant’s call upon the

transcendental world should, on his own account, be illegitimate, as

this world is unknowable, and its causal interaction with the

phenomenal world impossible, since the concept of causality cannot

apply to it.

Kant does leave some positive function to the ideas of

174 Transcendental idealism

unconditioned reason; they can be regulative of our inquiries, even if

concrete knowledge of truths cannot directly be derived from them. If

we treat the ideas of unconditioned reason as unobtainable aims, they

may act as injunctions. For example, the idea of determining if the

world has a beginning in time is not something we can settle by pure

reason, nor could any empirical inquiry determine the answer; but the

question of the universe’s temporal origin requires us to keep

searching for ever greater understanding of the universe’s origin.

We can summarize the philosophy of Kant in the following way.

Kant starts from the problem of justifying the objectivity and necessity

of the form of intuitions and the concepts we apply to the world. Their

necessity and objectivity seem unjustifiable by the raw sensations of

experience alone or because their rejection would involve logical

contradiction. The world for us can be nothing but the sum total of

possible appearances, and the form given to those appearances—

applied to the raw sensations—is the product of our minds;

appearances, but not things-in-themselves, have to conform to the

form given to them by our understanding; these forms are objective

and necessary because they are that to which all appearances must

conform if there are awareness and judgements concerning those

appearances; these forms are universally valid for all rational beings.

Thus they are objective because they apply to all worlds conceivable to

us, and to rational beings in general, and so are independent of the

subjective contributions of any individual minds. The world as

noumenon is the world considered as other than how it can ever

appear to us; such a world beyond all possible appearances is

unknowable; it is a world in which the a priori form produced by our

intellect is not valid, since it is the world as it is independent of all

appearances, beyond possible experience. The function of philosophy

is not to provide us with knowledge of the nature of reality as a whole

or in itself—how the world might be beyond how it can possibly

appear to us—but with knowledge of the a priori form or structure of

those appearances themselves. Nor can philosophy lay down a priori

the scientific laws of nature; but it can justify the presuppositions that

the scientific empirical inquiry into the laws of nature involves.

Philosophy studies the only thing it can: the necessary and universal a

priori form of the world as it appears to us; the a priori forms are

necessary and objective because they are how any rational minds must

think; the forms are therefore applicable to any conceivable world, that

is, to all that is a possible appearance to us.

Kant 175

continued to ...

https://sites.google.com/site/philosophygreekancient/philosophy-and-philosophers---an-introduction-to-western-philosophy---chapter-4-2