Philosophy and Philosophers - an Introduction to Western Philosophy - Chapter 4

back to ...

https://sites.google.com/site/philosophygreekancient/philosophy-and-philosophers---an-introduction-to-western-philosophy---chapter-1-2

or ...

CHAPTER FOUR

Rationalism:

Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz

The philosophers of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries are often

separated into rationalists and empiricists. While this distinction

certainly blurs similarities between philosophers of both “schools”,

this retrospective classification has some value at least in bringing out

tendencies of the philosophers grouped under these headings. The

contrast chiefly lies in what is said to be knowable by pure reason

alone. Some factors consistently underlie rationalist philosophy.

Rationalism holds that the human mind has the capacity, logically

speaking, to establish truths about the nature of reality (including

ourselves) by reason alone independently of experience; indeed, if

knowledge of the fundamental structure of the world in the proper

scientific sense is possible, then it must be derived from reason, which

alone has access to the required certain, necessary, universally valid,

timeless truths; the senses inform us only of what is uncertain,

contingent, particular, perspectival and transient. These necessary

truths about the world can be known to be true merely through our

properly understanding the concepts they involve or are deduced from

such truths, and ideally they form a single deductive system. Truths

known a priori by pure understanding, if they do not concern the

world as it appears in perception, instead concern a really existing

intelligible world that underlies the appearance of changing

particulars that we experience; this underlying reality makes

intelligible, and ultimately explains, the appearances. The intellect has

access to concepts, and the terms that express them, whose meaning

does not depend on being referred to some feature of our experience.

Thus there is, according to the rationalists, a reality whose nature is

comprehended by the intellect (reason or understanding) alone and

which stands behind the mere appearance of things; it is this ultimate

reality which delivers the conceptions which bring the explanation of

the way the world is to an end.

74

The rationalists do not disregard the senses, but they share the

characteristic of thinking that knowledge based on experience is

inferior to that derived from reason. The rationalist contention is that

the world has an underlying real structure of natural necessary

connections, which is logically understandable by reason and

deduction alone; this does not inevitably lead to the advocation of an a

priori methodology in science—as if all scientific truths can actually be

discovered just by sitting and thinking—for although in principle or

ideally the world is understandable a priori by the intellect alone, in

fact we as humans have a limited capacity to determine the nature of

the world independently of experience; scientific truths are often in

fact discovered by us through experience. Moreover, the necessary a

priori truths of metaphysics concern not the world of appearances,

which is the subject matter of science, but a reality beyond

appearances.

There is the conviction among the rationalists that everything is in

principle rationally explicable; one can never rest content with features

of the world for which a reason cannot be given as to why they

necessarily are a certain way and not otherwise. The tendency of

empiricism is to admit that there are a priori necessary truths knowable

with certainty independently of experience, but to deny that such

truths can determine anything about what really exists or the real

nature of the world, because in all such cases we are dealing with the

contingent features of the world we experience, and not what is

necessary concerning a supposed world beyond possible experience.

Descartes

The importance of Descartes in Western philosophy can hardly be

overestimated; he shaped the kinds of questions and answers which

were to dominate Western philosophy for many years; and, with some

notable exceptions, this approach has only seriously been questioned

in the twentieth century.

René Descartes (1596–1650) was born in France, in a small village

near Tours that is now called La Haye-Descartes. His constitution as a

child was poor. He was educated at a Jesuit college at La Flèche in

Anjou. Here he encountered scholastic doctrines that his philosophy

was to reject; but he also discovered his love for and great proficiency

at mathematics; and he remained a Catholic all his life. Descartes had

the desire to travel and experience the world of practical affairs, and to

this end he joined, unpaid, the army of the Dutch Prince Maurice of

Orange and later the army of the Duke of Bavaria.

While in Holland he encountered Isaac Beeckman, who encouraged

Descartes to consider questions in mathematics, physics and

philosophy. On 10 November 1619, he spent the night by a large stove

Descartes 75

in Ulm; there he had a vision, and later three dreams, concerning how

he might lay the foundations for a unified science which would

include all human learning. From 1625 he spent two years in Paris,

where he lived the life of a gentleman; he gambled, and was involved

in a duel over a love affair. In 1628 he began writing, in Latin, Rules

for the direction of the mind, which was unfinished and unpublished in

his life time. This states the overall projects that were to preoccupy all

of Descartes’ philosophy: that of founding science on absolute

certainty, free from sceptical doubts, and that of devising a method of

inquiry which, if properly followed, would lead science inexorably to

certain truth.

Descartes spent most of the period from 1628 to 1649 in the

relatively liberal atmosphere of Holland. The death of his five-year-old

illegitimate daughter Francine in 1640 was his life’s great grief. He was

secretive about his whereabouts, and lived in many different houses;

he also had a great desire for solitude, although he was not always

without company. In 1647 Descartes had dinner with the philosophers

Gassendi (1592–1655) and Hobbes (1588–1679), both of whom were

critics of Descartes’ Meditations.

Descartes received criticism of the Meditations from various

theologians, and most fruitfully from Antoine Arnauld (1612–94). All

these criticisms are printed as Objections and Replies; the latter of these

being Descartes’ responses. We are fortunate that as well as producing

his major writings, he engaged in extensive correspondence with many

people about his ideas. Towards the end of his life Descartes developed

a friendship with the exiled Princess Elizabeth, daughter of Elector

Frederick; he replied in letters to her acute questions. He acquired

royal patronage from Queen Christina of Sweden, and was persuaded

in 1649 to go to Stockholm. There he continued his long-standing habit

of rising late, having spent some hours in the morning reading and

writing in bed. In Sweden he led a lonely life, and in 1650, in the

winter, he contracted pneumonia and died. His last words are said to

have been “My soul, we must leave”. Although initially buried in

Sweden, his body was eventually transferred to the church of SaintGermain-des-Prés,

and his skull is to be found in the Musée de

l’Homme, in Paris.

The overall aim of Descartes’ philosophy might be said to be the

attempt to free explanations of the nature of the world from confusions

and conflicts, and set them on a path that would lead to a unified

explanation of things that was true, and, because it was also certain,

free from scepticism. Descartes made a significant contribution to the

revolution of how man viewed his place in the universe, and the

proper way of pursuing truths. His particular contribution to this

revolution in thought is the egocentricity of his approach: the

foundation of truth and knowledge begins by working from what is

most evident to the mind of the individual.

76 Rationalism

In the dedication to the Meditations Descartes seems to have other

aims: proofs of both the immortality of the soul and the existence of

God. It would be wrong to suppose that he was insincere in his

expressed concern for these matters. However, the concern of enduring

importance for modern readers lies in his aim and method in securing

a scientific, in particular mathematical, understanding of the world

that is secure against even exaggerated sceptical doubts. More

generally this involved a search for a method of ridding ourselves of

beliefs not known to be true, and maximizing those which are known

to be true. Descartes presents such a search to us in the Meditations in

the form of a personal odyssey. This is a kind of intellectual record so

that anyone might follow the same procedure at least once in his life,

and by it strip his mind of the accumulated rubbish of uncritically

accepted beliefs. Descartes sets out in the Meditations not merely the

arguments for his philosophy, but also a convincing route we can

follow which will enable us to overcome the psychological resistance

we may have to such a journey. It is the path which should be followed

by the seeker after the ultimate foundations of knowledge; in

particular it involves showing that a mathematical physics of the

world is attainable by creatures with our intellectual capacities and

faculties.

Descartes sets out on an extraordinary procedure of answering the

most extreme scepticism about knowledge and rationality by

embracing that scepticism; he then attempts to show that something

remains that cannot conceivably be doubted even after scepticism has

been applied in its most stringent form, and that what remains is

sufficient to secure the foundations for knowledge. The tool used to

this end is the “method of doubt”.

The final position at which Descartes wishes to arrive is that we can

have objective knowledge of the world; knowledge independent of the

way we happen to be biologically constituted; disinterested knowledge

that aims to divest itself of our perspective, and that tells us how

things really are in the world. Descartes thinks that such an objective

conception must be independent of our contingent sensory faculties,

since we have no guarantee that our senses present to us the world in

its fundamental form; after all, if our senses changed, the world would

appear differently. So the aim is to produce a way of describing the

world based on conceptions which would not change if our senses

changed; a world whose laws we could fraternally share with any

rational beings. To be objective our science must be sense-independent,

and derived from reason or the faculty of understanding. Descartes

sets out to show that when the mind is emptied of all sense-dependent

beliefs, it is not empty of ideas or concepts, and that the ideas that

remain are sufficient to form the basis for science. This involves a belief

that we have innate ideas independent of the senses; we have such

ideas concerning mathematics and geometry. By “ideas” here

Descartes 77

Descartes does not mean images; he means concepts. Descartes

attempts to show that the fundamental explanations of all phenomena

can be derived from a mathematical and geometric conception of

reality independent of sense-experience. Descartes aims to

demonstrate that mathematical geometry can be applied to the

explanation of the world of material things because, contrary to the

appearance of a vast array of natural kinds of things in the world, the

only essential properties of matter are geometric; that is, matter

stripped of all properties other than the ones which geometry deals

with will still be matter, and will be matter if and only if it has those

properties; those properties are extension, shape and motion, of which

extension is primary. The essential properties are those properties

which a thing cannot lack and still be the kind of thing it is.

Descartes in many ways can be seen as opposing the Aristotelian

science; Aristotle takes at face value the division of the world into

what appear to be natural kinds of things. An Aristotelian scientific

explanation of some phenomenon associated with a thing is then

obtained by deducing the phenomenon from an intellectual

examination of the essential nature of that thing given by a real

definition, or from a more general category of which the thing is a

part. The identification of genuine natural kinds, from which

explanations are to be deduced, is very difficult. However, Descartes

does not reject essentialism, which is the view that we eventually reach

a certain category of stuff beyond which we cannot go since we have

reached that which is most ontologically self-sufficient, and from

which we derive explanations of everything else that appears to us in

the world. But instead of a vast array of the natural kinds there appear

to be, Descartes, in the case of the material world, reduces this to one

fundamental kind: matter as extension. It is in terms of this underlying

reality behind appearances that the variety of features making up

appearances are to be explained. The explanation of a vast array of

different phenomena is thus simplified and unified under a more

general conception which reflects the fundamental nature of reality.

The tendency of Descartes’ philosophy, and the revolution of which his

philosophy is a part, is to reopen the gap between how things appear

to us in perception, and how they really are in themselves; moreover,

how things really are, which should form the basis of the explanation

of appearances, has to be comprehended by intellectual contemplation

or thinking, not experience. This marks the distinction between

primary qualities, which are the real qualities things have

independently of perceivers, and secondary qualities, which are in

objects as arrangements of primary qualities (say particles in motion),

but which produce in perceivers quite different ideas, like the

experience of heat and red.

First, Descartes has to deal with radical scepticism. The method of

doubt seeks to eliminate all beliefs not known to be true which may

78 Rationalism

taint and infect the truth; it does this by rejecting as false all beliefs it is

possible to doubt; that is, it rejects all beliefs whose falsity is possible. In

this way Descartes meets the sceptic head-on. This is done not because

he thinks all those beliefs it is possible to doubt the truth of are false;

rather, it is a way of making certain in one go that no false beliefs slip

through and are mistakenly accepted as true. It is important to note

that Descartes is not suggesting that we adopt such scepticism in our

everyday life; Descartes’ doubt is a method adopted for the pure

project or special purpose of securing the first principles or

foundations of all knowledge, disregarding all practical concerns.

Straight away we can note that we do, after all, find cases of things we

once believed to be true turning out to be false. Even without sceptical

doubt, Descartes’ view that we should make a fresh start makes sense;

we have over our lifetime accumulated uncritically a mass of beliefs

from which we make all sorts of inferences; but any falsity among

these beliefs is likely to infect any inferences we make and conclusions

we draw from those beliefs. If we then arrive at true conclusions, even

in valid inferences, it can only be by a sort of luck.

What remains after this process of sceptical doubt is not a massively

rich axiom from which all that we would wish to claim we can know

can be deduced, but something which, when examined for the reason

for its immunity from doubt, will give us a criterion to distinguish truth

from falsity. That criterion is clarity and distinctness. Descartes does

not wish the criterion to be merely a notion of subjective obviousness,

but he is unable to formulate it in terms of primary truths or logical

truths whose denial implies a contradiction, in the way that Leibniz

does; rather, Descartes explains it as our possessing intellectual

intuition giving us an ability simply to see that certain propositions or

beliefs, once fully understood, must be true. After this we can begin to

reinstate many of those beliefs we previously supposed false. In this

search we take time off from practical concerns and constraints, and

apply the criterion single-mindedly.

Descartes embarks on his method of doubt by disposing of the

range of beliefs in three classes: first, we abandon sense-based beliefs

by accepting that the senses may deceive us; second, we abandon the

belief that we can have knowledge of real “simple natures”; third, we

abandon the belief that God exists. A belief in the existence of God is

simply dropped, both because Descartes has no wish to assume one of

the things he sets out to prove, and because if the existence of a

beneficent God were granted the radical scepticism Descartes

envisions would not be plausible. Descartes also wishes to show that

there are degrees of doubt involved in these classes of beliefs, and to

indicate the order of trustworthiness in which we should reinstate

them; he also wishes to make the method of doubt psychologically

convincing. To these ends he suggests two hypotheses: the “dream

hypothesis” and the “evil demon hypothesis”.

Descartes 79

The first of these—the dream hypothesis—points to those occasions

on which I thought I was awake when in fact I was dreaming. Our

sleeping dreams may also be phenomenally or qualitatively

indistinguishable from our waking states: I may be convinced I am

awake and seeing real things when I am in fact asleep. This suffices to

undermine the trust we may have in the senses as representing to us

something real. This doubt extends to the existence of my own body,

which brings us to the second class of beliefs: the existence of “simple

natures”. When we dream we dream about something, and that

something must conform to the most simple and universal categories

such as extension, shape, duration, number, movement. Even if what

we dream of does not exist exactly as we dream about it, it is still

possible, and less doubtful, that simple and universal natures exist; for

example, objects with extension. Thus an object of a specific shape

might not exist because we might dream about an imaginary unreal

object of that shape; but that is not the same as showing there are no

objects with shape: shape as such does not exist. Even dreaming

involves objects considered under the simplest categories and concepts

which are surely real. Horses, and bodies of particular shapes, may not

exist, but it is less doubtful that there exists a world of extended

material things at all. Moreover, the greater security of mathematics

and geometry derives from its dealing with simple natures (such as

number and shape) and their necessary relations regardless of whether

those general things exist or not. Geometrical proofs done in a dream

would still be valid since their validity is independent of whether

geometric objects exist. The evil demon, however, who has the active

power to deceive us has the ability to lead us to believe falsely that

there exist in the world even the most general sorts of things

characterized by simple natures. The evil demon finally makes it

conceivable that no external world exists corresponding to our idea of

a world of extended substance; the evil demon could cause our idea of

an extended world although that world does not exist. It is not always

clear if simple mathematical and geometric truths can be doubted

under the influence of the evil demon. It must be remembered that it is

not within the power even of the demon to alter logical truths and to

make 2+2=4 false and 2+2=5 true; however, the demon can make us

believe that 2+2=5. Descartes thinks it is within God’s power to alter

such logical truths. Even if we accept that beliefs in basic mathematical

and geometric truths survive the demon, we have not established that

anything exists corresponding to the simple natures; doubt as to their

existence is conceivable, so their existence is therefore not free from

scepticism. We have at best a pure mathematics and geometry which

has not been shown to apply to anything existing, for the simple

natures are what it would deal with.

What remains that cannot be doubted is cogito ergo sum: I think,

therefore I am. For however the demon may twist and turn in his

80 Rationalism

attempt to trap and deceive us, and lead us to accept doubtful and

false beliefs, there is one belief I cannot doubt: that whenever I think, I

exist. This belief is somehow self-verifying; the mark of truth is

intrinsic to it and does not depend on accepting any other truth. Even

if the content of that thinking is itself an act of doubting, this too could

not take place unless I existed. The cogito is the necessary condition for

all reasoning—even all deception. Each time I entertain the cogito it is

certainly true.

What is more, I am essentially a thing that thinks, for, although I can

doubt that I have a body and still exist, I cannot cease to think and still

exist. Descartes believes that he is essentially a thinking thing: he is

necessarily immaterial (incorporeal) if he exists at all, and only

contingently embodied. The question of whether he is entitled to this

conclusion is much disputed; but one obvious objection has been that

it does not follow from the premise “I necessarily exist whenever I

think” that “I am necessarily only a thing that thinks”. We might

accept that “I think” entails “I exist” without agreeing that “I exist”

entails “I think”; I may still exist in some other way when I do not

think. Therefore I may not be essentially only a thinking thing. There is

indeed some doubt as to how much weight Descartes puts on this

argument. Whatever we think of this, Descartes is committed to the

view that he is essentially a thinking thing, and that thought is his only

essential property. Descartes of course presents more than one

argument for this view.

By essence Descartes means some property, or set of properties, f,

such that if f is an essential property of X, then X cannot be an X

without possessing property f; if f is the essence of X, then X cannot be

what it is or the sort of thing it is without f. Thus, f is a necessary and

sufficient condition for X to be what it is independently of the fact that

it is. In a case where there is only one essential property, as with mind

and matter, that property is alone both necessary and sufficient.

Descartes thinks we can know—that is, have clear and distinct

conceptions of—what mind and matter are before we know whether

any exists or not. For Descartes, as for other rationalists, only God has

existence as part of His necessary and sufficient conditions for what

He is: God. In this way Descartes draws the distinction, criticized by

Spinoza, between true substance, God, and the finite or created

substances mind and matter.

As it stands, the cogito is merely a subjectively certain truth; it is

time-bound; its certainty is restricted to those times when it is

actually being entertained. Descartes obviously wishes to move

beyond the perpetual reiteration of this one truth. What makes the

cogito a certain truth is that it is clearly and distinctly perceived.

Descartes makes use of an analogy with sense-perceptions: an idea is

clear in so far as we attend to features of which we are forcefully and

immediately aware, and an idea is distinct when we attend only to

Descartes 81

those features which are clear, and thus do not make inferences

beyond that of which we are immediately aware. This turns out to be

awareness of the essential nature of the objects of one’s awareness;

and awareness of an object’s essence means that the object of

awareness could not be confused with anything else. The thinking

behind clear and distinct ideas is that there must be a “natural light”

of reason that allows a direct grasp or intuition of some truths with

certainty, independently of the acceptance of any other truths. They

are grasped by anyone who can reason and can understand at all. If

some truths are not immediately manifestly true on intrinsic grounds

alone, following our full understanding of them, without any further

(“external”) justification, then all reasoning would be impossible,

since it could never get started. Those propositions which we can

clearly and distinctly conceive, or intuit, can be known to be true

because we can see they must be true merely from completely

understanding them. Such truths can be seen as analytic: they can be

known to be true merely from understanding the meaning of the

terms they involve.

One problem with the cogito is that in it Descartes does seem to go

beyond what he is immediately aware of; what he is aware of is

particular acts of thinking; but this falls short of establishing a durable

“I” or self as a mental substance on which the thinking depends.

Descartes’ plan is then to move from the two features of the cogito,

thinking and existence, to prove the existence of God. Having

established the existence of God, Descartes relies on our

understanding of the nature of God as an all powerful, perfect and

benevolent being to say that, as deception is an imperfection, God

would not deceive us in that which we most clearly and distinctly

conceive: that is, truths that are knowable through the understanding

alone. If I do not go beyond judging as true that which I clearly and

distinctly perceive, then I will always judge truly, and I will not

entertain falsehoods.

What I clearly and distinctly understand about things is the

essential properties of those things; those properties without which

those things cannot be the kind of things they are; those properties

which, if I think about those things at all, cannot be separated from,

and so must be part of, my conception of those things. These are the

defining properties of substances, on which all the other apparent

qualities of things rely. There are three substances according to

Descartes: matter, whose essential property is extension; mind, whose

essential property is thought; and God, whose essential properties are

perfection, omnipotence, benevolence, infiniteness, and existence.

Only God contains existence as part of His essence; that is, among the

necessary and sufficient conditions for being God is existence. But the

created substances of matter and mind are distinguished by relying on

nothing else apart from God for their existence. The same cannot be

82 Rationalism

said for colour, for example, which relies on there being an extended

physical object which is coloured.

If we examine the essential properties of mind and matter, we

discover that it is the intellect, independently of the senses, which

gives us our understanding of them. If we conceive of mind and

matter, and we imagine away all those properties which seem

unnecessary to their being either mind or matter, we find that we are

left with the essential properties; thought in the case of mind, and

extension in the case of matter. Without these properties neither could

have any other properties at all; the essential properties are what all

other properties depend on. All the other properties can change, but

without extension and thought, matter and minds respectively would

not be what they are. These essential natures remain constant to give

identity to matter and minds through the changes they appear to

undergo according to our senses, and even when all the sensory

qualities have changed; the intellect reveals the underlying reality

upon which sensory appearances are a kind of clothing. If the senses

are eliminated by sceptical doubt, it is by the sense-independent

conception of the understanding that the essential properties or

intelligible properties remain known to us. The essential properties

these substances have are what remains constant through change, and

makes sense of the continued identity of a thing over time through

accidental change. If essential properties change, we do not say that X

has acquired property g and lost property f, we say, rather, that X has

ceased to be X; it ceases to be the same substance if it loses its essence.

What makes a material thing (for example, a piece of wax) a piece of

matter through its various appearances is not sensible qualities

(something we perceive by sense), for these can all alter; the

conception of a material thing revealing its essence, by which we

identify it as the same material thing through its various appearances,

is therefore given through inspection by the intellect.

The thinker who has reached the intuitive certainty of his own

existence and the essential nature of that existence has still to get

beyond this. Descartes distinguishes between levels of reality, or being,

by degree of ontological dependence; the more independently a thing

exists, the more formal (actual) reality it has. Descartes distinguishes

between objective and formal reality. An idea has a certain degree of

formal reality as an entity in itself; but it also has an objective reality—

its content, what the idea is about—which may differ from its formal

reality as an idea. The cause of an idea must have at least as much

formal reality as the idea has objective reality; that is, the actual cause of

an idea must have as much reality as the content of the idea. One idea

we have is the idea of God. In the case of the idea of God we have an

idea with infinite objective reality since the object of that idea has

infinite formal reality. An idea with such a content (such an object)

could not be caused by something merely finite, with less formal

Descartes 83

reality than the content, like ourselves, but must have as its cause

something of equal or greater actual or formal reality; so only God can

be the cause of our idea of God. This is a cosmological argument for

God’s existence. The notion of levels of reality can be summarized in

the following diagram; the arrows show the direction of decreasing

formal (actual) reality.

The other argument Descartes uses to prove God’s existence is the

ontological argument. God contains, by definition, all perfections, and

one of these perfections is existence itself. Therefore God exists. One

problem here is involved in suggesting that existence is a predicate

rather than a term confirming that predicates are actualized. Another

problem is that, although it may be part of God’s definition that if He

exists, then He exists necessarily, it may still be questioned whether

anything actually satisfies that definition.

A serious problem for Descartes’ arguments which aim to escape

the exaggerated doubt is the charge of circularity: the Cartesian

Circle. If we are dependent on the existence of God to free us from

scepticism, it is important to see how far this dependence extends. If

the dependence extends to God being our only guarantee of the truth

of even that which we most clearly and distinctly perceive, then it is

impossible to see how there can be any rational proof of God’s

existence; in that case the truth of any of the premises and the

reliability of any of the inferential steps in the proof would logically

depend on the outcome of the proof: God’s existence. We cannot,

without circularity, prove God’s existence by means of propositions

and arguments whose truth and validity depend on assuming God’s

existence. It is not clear what Descartes’ final view is on this. One

suggestion has been that God’s role is not to guarantee clear and

distinct ideas themselves as we intuit them—since they are in that

case as certain as they could ever be—but to obviate the necessity of

our running constantly through proofs to reassure ourselves. The

central problem then with the proofs of the existence of God is not

their circularity but their questionable validity and the dubiousness

of their premises.

Descartes, however, thinks he has proved the existence of God.

Having done this he can begin to reinstate some of the things cast

84 Rationalism

aside by the method of doubt by invoking the nature of God. In the

case of the material world, what we clearly and distinctly perceive

about it is that it is extended; and this is something grasped by the

intellect, not the senses; it follows from our merely properly

understanding the concept of matter. God would not deceive us about

what we most clearly and distinctly perceive. Those ideas that we

most clearly and distinctly conceive are innate; and once God’s

existence is proved, the truth of those ideas we identify as innate by

subtracting the sense-derived ideas is also guaranteed by their being

directly planted in us by God. This then gives us a pure physics of the

world, but it is one that is hypothetical: we have a clear and distinct

idea of what matter is as being essentially extended, but the question

remains as to whether such matter actually exists. God is required

again in order to demonstrate the possibility of an applied physics.

The ideas I receive when I perceive a material world, which I suppose

are caused by external bodies, could indeed have as their cause

external bodies, but their cause might also be myself, or derive

directly from God. These ideas come to me unbidden so I cannot be

their cause, and I have a strong belief that they derive from material

bodies; if the source of the ideas was other than what I strongly

believe it to be, God would be allowing me to be deceived; but God is

no deceiver; therefore bodies exist. This argument aims to prove the

existence of the material world. This establishes the possibility of

applied physics within what I clearly and distinctly perceive about

bodies. If we judge as true only that which we clearly and distinctly

perceive, God guarantees that those judgements correspond to actual

states of affairs in the world.

All that has been established in Descartes’ argument has been

established by pure reason alone independently of information

derived from the senses; the senses have been denied any role by the

sceptical doubt. Truths must be tested by reason, not by the unreliable

senses.

If God is no deceiver, why does he let us make mistakes at all?

Letting us make mistakes is not the same as actively deceiving us.

Descartes is clear that such mistakes as we make are our responsibility,

not God’s. The mind is made up of two chief faculties: intellect and

will. We make mistakes when we allow the will to push beyond what

is clearly and distinctly perceived by the intellect. God gives us the

possibility of avoiding error: we merely have to stick within what we

clearly and distinctly perceive: propositions we can know to be true

purely by fully understanding them.

If this is the case, it tends to undermine Descartes’ proof of the

existence of the material world. His argument depends on the notion

that God cannot be a deceiver and would be deceiving us if he allowed

us to believe strongly that material objects were the cause of our

perceptions of material objects when they are not the cause. But God

Descartes 85

could only be accused of deception if in those circumstances He either

implanted the belief in us, or such a belief was a clear and distinct one.

Descartes does not attempt to demonstrate the former, and the latter is

obviously not the case. So it is perfectly possible that God is not a

deceiver and that material objects do not exist as the cause of our

perceptions of material objects. Descartes has already admitted that

God lets us make our own mistakes in judgement and these are likely

to occur when we make judgements beyond what we clearly and

distinctly perceive to be the case.

Descartes gives a dualistic conception of reality; there are two basic

substances in the world, mind and matter. These two give at least the

appearance of interaction: things in the world act on my sensory

organs and result in perceptions; I will my arm to move, and it moves.

But the problem arises for Descartes of how a non-spatial (unextended)

substance, which cannot thereby be in motion, can cause the motion of

extended substance, or how motions in our bodies can cause changes

in consciousness. Mind and matter have no properties in common, and

it is difficult to see how their interaction can be rendered intelligible.

They are created substances dependent on God for their existence, but

apart from that the explanation of their states should be independent

of any causes “external” to their own type of substance. Descartes’

motivation for dualism derives from his belief in both the immortality

of the soul and the possibility of free will. The immortality of the soul

is maintained by the soul being an independent substance which

might survive the dissolution of the body. Free will is maintained by

making the soul independent of the deterministic mechanical laws

which govern matter; then our behaviour is not governed by

mechanical compulsion, but can be acts done out of choice in

knowledge of good and evil.

It is important to summarize some of Descartes’ achievements. They

are mainly seen in his attempt to gain a more objective point of view of

the world, and this requires a conception of the world which is nonsense-based;

an objective conception is non-species specific, and

independent of the way we happen, contingently, to be biologically

constituted. Some of our view of how the world is is contributed by

our natures; and to get a view of how the world really is (how it is in

itself), it is necessary to strip away as much as possible of the elements

in our conception contributed by the particularities of our perceptual

apparatus and perspective. Certainly the sense organs we happen to

have could alter to give us a different view of the world, but the world

would not thereby be different. The objective conception of the world

is a conception which is universally valid, revealing the world as it is

in itself, a conception devoid of features that depend, as apparent

features of the world, on the contingent peculiarities of our point of

view, such as those derived from our particular sensory apparatus.

Reason provides a conception, as a source of disinterested universally

86 Rationalism

valid concepts and truths, independent of our, or indeed any, point of

view. Take an extreme example: the truth 2+2=4 would presumably be

a truth for Martians no matter what sensory apparatus they had—they

might see X-rays but not light-rays. The idea is that our view of the

world could be objective and universally valid in the same way. We

cannot perhaps attain this ultimately objective point of view—a God’seye,

or no-eye view—but it is something at which we can aim; only

God sees things as they are in themselves independent of any point of

view; for God there is no appearance/reality distinction, for His view

is non-perspectival.

We can obtain objective knowledge of the physical world, according

to Descartes, by concentrating exclusively on conceiving it to have

only mathematical and geometric properties. Descartes needs to start

from the point of disinterested pure consciousness, which is outside

nature; using only the resources of reason or intellect that are found

within the incorporeal consciousness, Descartes hopes to build a

unified and universal conception of nature which would be common

to all beings capable of reasoning at all.

Spinoza

Benedict (Baruch) de Spinoza (1632–77) was the son of a Jewish

merchant who fled to the Netherlands from persecution in Portugal.

The Jews who entered Amsterdam met a close-knit and strict Jewish

community to which they had to accommodate themselves by

manifesting doctrinal purity. Spinoza was taught at a school run by a

rabbi, and he became familiar with Hebrew sacred books and Jewish

theology. But in 1656 he was excommunicated from the Amsterdam

synagogue for being unable to assent to important aspects of Judaic

orthodoxy; the root of this lay in Spinoza’s increasingly critical attitude

towards the Bible. His life as an outcast from the Jewish community

necessitated that he become financially independent; so Spinoza came

to make his living as a lens grinder. Although towards the end of his

life he was offered a professorship at the University of Heidelberg, he

declined it as a threat to his intellectual freedom—he thus never held

an academic post.

The advocacy of toleration, particularly the opposition to religious

fanaticism, was a mark of Spinoza’s outlook, surrounded as he was

by violent schisms of every sort. Spinoza was held in great affection

by his friends—friendship between those who in common seek truth

being something, in the Aristotelian tradition, he valued highly.

Something of Spinoza’s inner strength and personal bravery is

indicated by two incidents toward the end of his life. In 1670, while

living in The Hague, Spinoza received a small annuity from Jan de

Witt, Grand Pensionary of the Netherlands and an enlightened

Spinoza 87

advocate of religious freedom. De Witt was accused of treachery in

1671 when England joined forces with France against the

Netherlands; an angry mob seized de Witt and his brother and beat

them to death. In an uncharacteristic display of recklessness, Spinoza

was prepared to confront the mob and denounce their barbarism, but

he was dissuaded from this course of action. Later, in 1677, following

his appointment to a peace mission to France, Spinoza too came

under suspicion as a spy; his house in The Hague was besieged by an

enraged mob; again Spinoza was prepared to try and face down the

crowd despite the possibility that he might be killed in the same

manner as de Witt.

However, these are incidents untypical of Spinoza’s life, most of

which was spent in independence and simplicity; he was stoical in

outlook, and dedicated to intellectual and scholarly pursuits.

Fortunately he was able to discuss his philosophical views with

tolerant Protestant friends. He was uncomplaining, and cautious;

suspicious of violent emotions (which is not to say he was unfamiliar

with them), knowing well their destructive power; but he did not

thereby lack either charm or warmth. He smoked a pipe, and liked to

drink beer. He was unmarried, thinking that such emotional

attachment would disrupt his scholarly study; although it seems that

he had been disappointed in love early in life. The consumption from

which he had suffered for many years, aggravated perhaps by the glass

dust he breathed in his work as a lens grinder, claimed his life in 1677.

Spinoza’s interests wandered freely across mathematics and the

various sciences. Among Spinoza’s modest library there was the Bible,

books of Euclidean geometry, works on optics, and astronomy. This

apparently likable man was vilified both during and after his life,

variously as heretic and atheist.

Spinoza’s correspondence aids our understanding of his

philosophy: that with Henry Oldenburg, who became secretary of the

new Royal Society in London, but most important that with the

scientist Tschirnhaus. In 1676 Spinoza was visited by Leibniz; he

overcame Spinoza’s initial wariness to the extent that Spinoza

allowed him access to the unpublished Ethics. Spinoza also became

acquainted with Christiaan Huygens who originated the modern

theories of optics, and corresponded with Robert Boyle, the founder

of chemistry.

There are probably three main influences on Spinoza’s philosophical

views: scholastic Aristotelianism transmitted through the early Jewish

thinker Maimonides (1135–1204); Cartesian philosophy; and the works

of Hobbes. Spinoza came to reject, or modify massively, all of these

influences.

To gain full understanding of Spinoza, it is the Ethics on which one

must concentrate. The Ethics is a work of stupendous ambition.

Spinoza aims to connect how the world necessarily really is at its

88 Rationalism

deepest level with the practical concern of how we should live our

lives and attain a blessed peace (acquiescentia) of mind. This project has

a good deal to do with ways of controlling, but not eliminating, the

emotions; emotional states and reactions are inextricably linked to

beliefs; if we see that certain of the beliefs we hold are false, we can

thereby change the emotions connected with those beliefs. This

suggests that through a form of cognitive therapy there can be some

control over emotions.

The Ethics is set out in a form which follows the methods of

geometric proof: using axioms, definitions, and postulates, from which

propositions are inferred by deductive reasoning. It uses a highly

abstract and technical language, much of which derives from the

medieval scholastic tradition—although its views are quite opposed to

scholastic metaphysics. Spinoza aims to start from first principles

which he thinks self-evidently true, and then logically deduce what

consequences follow; thus the propositions that follow are proved and

necessarily true. The definitions are not merely stipulative (arbitrarily

laying down how a word will be used); they are meant to be true of the

objects to which they refer; they are “real definitions” which can be

true or false because they aim to give the necessary and sufficient

conditions for their reference being what it is; that is, such definitions

give a thing’s essential features. Nevertheless, the definitions often

depart greatly from common usage. The axioms are both self-evident

and primitive: they are obviously true, and not derivable from

anything simpler.

The heart of Spinoza’s philosophy is the nature of substance. Certain

aspects of the world seem to be dependent on other aspects for their

nature and existence; if anything in the world is ultimately real in

being fully independent—and we are not to embark on an infinite

regress—we must reach something that does not depend for its nature

and existence on anything else. The rationalist contention is that by

chasing down the ladder of dependence, our intellect or reason will

reveal what satisfies the conditions for ultimately independent being

which is fully self-explanatory and explains everything else, so

nothing whatsoever is left unexplained. The universe as a whole must

have no superfluous features in its nature or existence that are

inexplicable in being not deducible from its total concept. Spinoza is

dissatisfied with Descartes’ analysis of substance; Descartes’ notion of

the “created substances” mind and matter is for Spinoza a mistake

because they are not fully self-explanatory. There are, for Spinoza, two

main conditions which must be satisfied for something to be regarded

as a substance:

(a) Whether that thing is self-subsistent or self-caused (causa sui):

that which has the most independent sort of nature and existence

and does not owe its nature and existence to anything else.

Spinoza 89

(b) Whether that thing can be totally conceived—understood or

explained—through itself alone, without involving any

conception of another thing outside it.

And there is a third point to be borne in mind which ultimately derives

from Aristotle:

(c) A substance is that which is a subject (ultimately: always a subject)

and not a predicate (ultimately: never a predicate). It is the subject

of predication, and not predicated of anything; it is what remains

the same through changes in predication.

So substance is that which is self-caused, self-explanatory, and the

ultimate subject of all predication. This amounts to saying that true

substance must be such that all of its features are deducible from its

essence.

Spinoza is committed to some form of the ontological argument:

God, and only God, exists necessarily, since God’s essence involves

existence; it would therefore be a contradiction to suppose God did not

exist. So God exists and, moreover, only God can fulfil the conditions

for substance, therefore there can be only one substance. It is a mistake

to regard mind and matter as substances: they are not fully selfsubsistent,

but are dependent modes or manifestations of God. Only

God includes existence among the necessary and sufficient conditions

defining His nature. A true substance must be that which contains

within itself, as part of its essence, the complete explanation of its

nature and existence.

This complete causal autonomy and explanatory autonomy amount

to the same thing. If we have a clear and distinct conception of things,

which we derive from self-evident truths intuited by the intellect, then

the consequent logical deductive links between the concepts will

correspond to causal links between things. In this way, the underlying

structure of the world is seen to be one reflected in necessary

deductive links. This conflates (in a way unsatisfactory to empiricists

such as Hume) causal connections with logical necessity so that: if A

causes B, then B is logically deducible from A.

It is vital to understand that Spinoza thinks that the intellect can

ideally attain a system of concepts which represents the underlying

nature of the world as a whole; and that a complete explanation of the

world would be constituted by laying out all the deductive logical

interrelations between these concepts.

Spinoza’s concept of God is not one of a transcendent God who

stands outside the world; Spinoza writes of “God or Nature” (Deus sive

Natura); God is to be identified with the totality of the universe.

Spinoza’s view of God is sometimes regarded as pantheistic. The

totality of the universe includes more than that which is material. God

is infinite and unlimited; unless one contradicts this, there can be

90 Rationalism

nothing which is not “in” God; that is, there is nothing which is not

dependent on God both ontologically and for its explanation. There

can only be a single substance; there cannot be a plurality of

substances. Substance in Spinoza has upon it the extremely restricting

definition that it must be completely self-caused (causa sui) and must

be entirely self-explanatory; and this eliminates the traditional

distinction with respect to true substance between having necessary and

contingent properties; that is, necessary properties given by an essence

or definition, and accidental or contingent properties, derived from the

conception of another thing that is an external cause; to be a true

substance all its states must follow necessarily or deductively from its

essence or definition, otherwise it would not be completely

independent in being its own complete explanation. Spinoza identifies

true substance with God or the totality of nature because only that can

satisfy the conditions of a true substance by being fully the cause and

explanation of itself; it satisfies these conditions simply because, by

being the totality of what there is, there is nothing else that is required

to be, or could be, its cause or involved in its explanation.

To suggest that there could be two or more substances would be to

suppose the following.

(i) To suppose something—assuming that everything has to be

rationally explicable—outside the plurality of putative substances

which explains the plurality; but then this contradicts the

definition that true substance must be entirely self-explanatory.

(ii) To suppose that a substance could be limited; but limitation

entails that part of the explanation, and thus of the cause, for the

substance being as it is does not lie within it, but depends on

another thing outside it explaining its limitation; but then

something limited like that could not be a true substance because

true substance is by definition fully self-explanatory.

There are two alternatives here in talking of a plurality of substances:

there could be two or more substances with different attributes or

essences, or two or more substances with the same attribute or

essence.

(a) The possibility of there being two substances with different

attributes is ruled out by the definition of God as having all

attributes; God, as it were, uses up all possible attributes, so if

there is a substance other than God, it must have the same

attributes as God.

(b) So if there is more than one substance, then those substances

must have the same attributes.

Spinoza therefore aims to show that there cannot be two or more

substances with the same attributes—the same essence. If they differ in

attributes, then we have two substances with different attributes,

Spinoza 91

which is not what we are looking for. If two things differ only in mode,

and modes are modes of substance and not themselves substances,

then a difference merely in modes does not mark a difference in

substance; since we are by hypothesis dealing with a difference only in

mode, and not in attribute, the modes must be modes of the same

substance; two things that differ only in mode are therefore essentially

the same, and are not therefore different substances.

Moreover, we would have no reason to regard “two things” with the

same attributes—differing merely numerically—as two; for there is no

sense in which they could be distinguished, since all their features are

dependent upon their attributes, or essence, which are here posited to

be the same; a difference in modes would involve a difference in

attributes in the case of true substance, since all its features must

depend only on itself; this means there cannot be two true substances

differing only in mode and not in attribute as well.

There cannot be a difference in substance apart from a difference in

attributes, so there cannot be two substances with the same attributes.

But there cannot be two substances with different attributes either,

because of the definition of God as a being of infinite attributes. So

there cannot be more than one substance.

Hence, true substance is utterly causa sui, cause of itself, and for this

to hold true, there can be only one substance. This unique unlimited

substance must have infinite attributes—that is, all possible

attributes—each of which is infinite in its kind. True substance is God

or Nature, and is theoretically conceivable in an infinity of ways, of

which our intellect truly grasps just two: we conceive the world under

the attribute of thought or under the attribute of extension; these are

what the intellect perceives of substance as constituting its essence.

Thus Descartes’ two “created substances”, mind and matter, are

properly seen as attributes of the one substance, not themselves two

substances.

The notion of something being the cause of itself (causa sui) may

seem incomprehensible. For A to cause itself to exist would seem to

involve A existing before A exists. But the notion of causation involved

here is that of logical deduction; the existence and nature of A is

caused by A in the same sense as the theorems of a geometry follow

from the axioms; and here the sense of following from is entirely nontemporal;

it does involves not succession in time, but rather a nontemporal

logical relation.

The notion of two attributes is partly understood as two

perspectives on the same thing—analogous to two sides of the same

coin—but here the “perspectives” are intellectual, not spatial, points of

view. There are two systems of concepts which represent or express the

order of the same thing in two ways, such that each way of talking is

irreducible to the other; explanations in both systems or schemes take

place by logical deduction using the concepts within that system only;

92 Rationalism

the two systems of concepts, within each of which there are logical

links, are irreducible one to the other; they are incommensurable. They

are two completely autonomous ways of looking at the same thing.

All that we observe in the world as particular things are either

modes of the attribute of extension (physical things) or modes of the

attribute of thought (ideas, which make up minds); all things are thus

a determinate expression of the essence of God. Infinite modes are

those features that are common to all modes that fall under a certain

attribute: motion and rest in the case of physical particles, and ideas in

the case of thoughts. Finite modes are the more particular features of

the world. Thus an infinite mode under the attribute of extension

would be described by a law of nature that applied to all physical

things, whereas a finite mode such as the red of this book is a

particular feature of the book and is not a feature common to all

physical things. The explanation of the existence and nature of

particular modes derives either from the essence of that mode,

something that lies within it “in so far as it is in itself”, or something

external to that mode, something that lies outside it. God or nature as a

totality is the only thing which has within it the complete explanation

of its existence and nature; all other things are modes which are

determinate cases of God expressed under the attribute of either

thought or extension, and to varying degrees their explanation lies

outside such modes; but in any case the full explanation must

ultimately be traced back to the nature or essence of God.

This begins to move us from metaphysics to epistemology. Spinoza

thinks that the logical order of ideas (their logical relations) is the same

as the connection of things (their causal relations). The perfect, or fully

“adequate”, understanding of the world would be attained if we could

see how everything was deducible from the essence of God. We would

then see how everything in the world follows by logical necessity from

God’s eternally fixed nature. This is more than determinism: it is

necessitarianism. One might have a variety of sets of axioms from

which different theorems could be deduced, which would constitute

their explanation or proof. But these proofs are conditional or

hypothetical in that they depend on the acceptance of the axioms: if

one accepts the axioms, then the theorems follow by logical necessity,

so that to accept the axioms (premises) and deny the theorems

(conclusions) would imply a logical contradiction. In the completely

adequate science of the world (falling under the attributes of extension

and thought) there is only one possible axiom set: the essence of God.

So the world is not explained in conditional truths deduced from a set

of basic truths which we might reject in favour of some alternative set;

the world follows unconditionally from God’s nature, which it would

be absurd to suppose could be different from what it is. God is perfect,

so any change in God would produce imperfection in God; God cannot

be other than what He is. On similar grounds Spinoza opposes final

Spinoza 93

cause or purposive or teleological explanations. God’s nature stands

immutably and eternally the same; it stands outside time. So this

world not only follows in every detail, when properly understood,

with logical necessity from God’s nature, this world is also the only

logically possible world. Not only is each link in the series deductively

connected with other links, the series itself is the only logically

possible series—the series itself as a whole is logically necessary.

Presumably this means any other series, and hence world, would

produce within it a logical contradiction.

The notion of a completely perfect conception of the world derives

from Spinoza’s doctrine of “adequate ideas”. The world, and features

of it, are always viewable under its two expressions of thought and

extension; these two worlds run in irreducible parallel; they are

isomorphic. From this metaphysics it follows that for every idea there

is a corresponding physical correlate, an ideatum. This does not mean

there cannot be false ideas, since truth involves more than mere

correspondence of an idea to some ideatum; the idea must also be an

adequate idea; this involves more than the external correspondence to

the object the idea purports to be an idea of; it must also represent the

true nature of the object represented. It is clear that Spinoza is using

the term “true” in a way different from common usage. For an idea to

be true in Spinoza’s sense it must not only correspond to the facts, but

must also be known to be true and one must know the nature of the

object to which the idea corresponds; only then is an idea said to be

adequate and true. Thus falsity is a privation of knowledge; although

an idea that failed to correspond to the facts would also be false. To

have an adequate idea of X involves understanding X, that is, knowing

the causes of X being as it is; this involves explaining X by deducing it

from other adequate ideas. Ultimately the chain of adequate ideas is

traced back to axiomatic necessary truths and concepts called

“common notions”. An inadequate idea is like a conclusion without

premises. An idea is more or less adequate in so far as it fits into a

more or less general system of explanation; the system will be more

general and powerful to the extent that features of the world can be

unified and deduced from it by deductive reasoning. An idea becomes

more adequate—thus adequacy is a matter of degree—by fitting as a

deducible conception within an ever wider, and more inclusive,

unifying, explanatory system. Complete adequacy would involve

fitting in the idea or conception deductively with the system

describing the order of the totality of things; ultimately this is the ideal

system contemplated by God. The completely adequate system of

ideas will ultimately be deducible from universally acceptable

“common notions” that are seen as evident by intuitive reason: these

are the axiomatic necessary truths and basic concepts of Spinoza’s

science and metaphysics that comprehend or constitute the logically

necessary and essential features of the universe.

94 Rationalism

An adequate idea gives an intrinsic mark of truth, as distinct from

the extrinsic mark whereby an idea merely corresponds to its object; a

completely adequate idea does not merely correspond to its ideatum; it

presents to us the true nature of, or understanding of, its ideatum. A

false idea is one that is inadequate; we know it corresponds to an

ideatum, but it will misrepresent, and fail to explain, the nature of that

ideatum, by failing to place the idea in the deductive system of

explanation which is constituted by a coherent system of ideas that

represents the true order of things. To have an adequate or true idea of

X is to understand X, which is to explain X, which is to know the

causes of X. The criterion of truth is given by features of ideas or

propositions themselves and the logical relation of proof between

them, and not by a mere comparison of ideas and the world; the

determination of what is true and what we know about the world is

available to us within the circle of ideas themselves in the form of

intuitions of reason giving “common notions” and necessary logical

deductions from these notions. At the level of completely adequate

ideas there turns out to be an exact agreement between ideas and

reality.

We can use a spatial perspectival example to understand the notion

of the completely adequate science. What I now see is in a way true

only from my perspective, my point of view; if I moved, or if I were

different biologically, what I see would be different—my view is in

this way particular. The aim of an adequate understanding is to see

things from no point of view; that is, to subtract all those features

which make my point of view mine or a mere point of view. The

intellect already provides us with such radically non-perspectival

truths: 2+2=4, for example. This is true from all points of view; its

truth is unconditional in not depending on any qualifying reference to

a perspective. Such is the nature of fully adequate ideas of the world;

these are found in rationally universally valid “common notions” and

deductions from them.

This rules out sense-perception as a means of attaining adequate

ideas of the world; we are to aim for an intellectual conception of the

world freed from the mixing of things in the world with their effect

upon us in terms of bodily processes. When we observe the sun, the

ideatum of the idea we have we confusedly think is the sun itself,

whereas the ideatum is really, in the sense of its physical correlate, that

bodily process corresponding to the perception of the sun, which is a

result of the effect of the sun on us. This is not a great problem

provided we come to understand the nature of our perceptions

themselves; in isolation the ideas of perception are not false, but may

become so—hence they are inadequate or untrue—when placed within

a wider explanatory context. A true, and thus adequate, idea, of the

sun as it is in itself will be approached by its deduction from other

ideas as part of a general science of physical things, the concepts of

Spinoza 95

which are grasped by the intellect, and this will replace the “false”,

inadequate, idea of sense-perception. The completely adequate system

of ideas places each idea in a totality of ideas such that the deductive

relation of the ideas represents the true order of causes in the world.

This is the world as understood by the intellect of God, who is

identical with the world.

Ultimately Spinoza’s completely adequate view of the world is sub

specie aeternitatis—the view from eternity, from outside time, from no

point of view. This is opposed to sub specie durationis—the view of

things as happening in time. God has such an eternal, non-temporal

view of the world; it should be our aim to participate in such a view.

We already have such non-temporal universal truths in mathematics

and geometry; it is senseless to apply time or duration to the truth

2+2=4; it is more than always true, its truth lies outside time altogether,

in eternity; the concept of duration has no application here at all.

Spinoza thinks that a true, hence completely adequate, explanation of

the world can be attained only through a view which is similarly sub

specie aeternitatis; the view outside time is the final step in ridding a

conception of all perspectives; one would then have the eternal,

necessary, a priori deductive explanation for everything. Some of these

truths we can grasp; but our finite minds enable us to grasp only a

small fraction of them.

There are three levels or kinds of knowledge. The first kind of

knowledge is sense-experience, the second kind of knowledge is

deductive reasoning, the third kind of knowledge is immediate

intuition of reason.

Sense-perceptions can be useful in giving us limited knowledge of

particular facts and in the forming of inductive generalizations. Our

finite minds cannot trace the infinity of causes that would give us fully

adequate ideas of the objects of sense-perception. Our finite minds

cannot cope with the infinite complexity of deducing truths concerning

finite modes (“A red book is on my desk”) all the way back to the

essence of God. Knowledge of the third kind, intuitions of reason, is

the highest form of understanding. There we not only have ideas

giving logical explanations by being related deductively to premises,

as in the second kind of knowledge, we also simply grasp the proof

complete in one intellectual act by seeing the rule in the instance. In

the case of sense-perceptions, we are presented with one inadequate,

fragmentary, logically unconnected idea after another (which is

correlated with inadequately understood states of the body) with no

real possibility of the order of presentation reflecting the true order of

causes. Sense-perception is not needed and cannot give knowledge of

the essence of things; in so far as we do not distinguish a thing from its

essence, we can deduce its nature from its definition.

Sense-perception can give knowledge that but not knowledge why,

which involves deducing the necessity of that perceived to be the case.

96 Rationalism

Nevertheless, sense-perception presents a low-level sort of knowledge

since it can satisfy what seem to be Spinoza’s three conditions for

knowledge that p:

(a) p corresponds to what is the case

(b) there is no reason to doubt that p (that is not to say p cannot be

doubted)

(c) there is a good reason to assert that p is the case (it is not a

guess).

Sense-experience as the ground for the assertion of either particular

facts or inductive generalizations seems to satisfy these conditions.

Knowledge in its highest senses of the second and third kind, which

involve deductive proof or logical necessity, clearly satisfies the above

conditions for knowledge, but to a higher degree.

The third kind of knowledge is the kind of understanding God has

of things in their totality derived from “common notions”. God’s view

of the world sub specie aeternitatis telescopes down the process of

deductive reasoning involved in comprehension of the totality of the

world to one intellectual “point”. Time is thus ultimately unreal from a

God’s-eye point of view. The ultimate explanation of the world lies

within the world; the world is fully explicable as a self-contained

system.

The general metaphysical conclusions are reflected in the Spinozian

response to the mind-body problem: ontological monism (a single

substance) is combined with a conceptual dualism (double-aspect). A

human being is viewed as mind or as body—these are two aspects of

the same thing; indeed, the ideatum of the mind is the human body.

This does not mean one is always conscious of one’s body; it alerts us

to a dual use of “idea of” in Spinoza. First, there is that derived from

ideas being expressions in thought of that which is expressed under

the attribute of extension; second there is the sense in which I have an

idea about some object. In the case of an idea of a table there is the first

meaning of the “idea of” the table, in the sense of the idea being an

expression in thought of some state of my body affected by the table

(that which may be involved in seeing the table); there is the second,

different, meaning of “idea of” in the sense of my idea being about the

table—its content or object is the table. In this second sense ideas are

said to be active and to exhibit intentionality: they point beyond

themselves to an intended object.

There can be no causal relation between mind and body; mind

concepts and body concepts are incommensurable so that logical

deductions, and hence causal laws, which included talk from both

ways of conceptualizing substance would be senseless. The relation

between the two systems of concepts is like that between two

autonomous languages which can say or express the same things each

in its different way. There is some relation between mind and body: it

Spinoza 97

is the correlation between determinate states of two attributes of one

substance. The complexity of thought of which a mind is capable is

therefore directly matched by the complexity of the body; a human

being is capable of complex thought processes, and this has its

correlate in the complexity of the human body. This means that

although every physical mode (ideatum) under the aspect of extension

has its corresponding idea, most things lack the necessary complexity

to be capable of conscious thought. Spinoza is not committed to stones

or chairs thinking; but the difference between them and us is only one

of great degree.

A human being is one kind of finite mode of the one infinite

substance. What gives meaning to the notion of any finite mode

having limited individuality is our conatus (striving, endeavour or

power): the endeavour to maintain its integrity or persist in being

against the effects of external causes. The nature or essence of a finite

mode is that without which it would cease to exist as what it is even

as a qualified individual, and would collapse under external causes.

In so far as the states of a thing are deducible from its nature or

essence, that is the conatus or power of that thing in self-preservation.

This will vary in degree and kind. The greater the conatus, the more

self-dependent it is and the more that through its essence, it expresses

power of self-preservation, power which is ultimately derived from

and expresses the power of the only truly independent individual,

God. Higher level finite modes such as organisms obviously exhibit

conatus: they try to persist in being what they are—a man, a dog—

with some degree of individuality. The greater our conatus the more

we realize our essence as rational beings; but this seems to produce a

conflict with our individuality, for we then have a view from which

we appreciate our connectedness with the whole of nature. No finite

mode can be ultimately self-explanatory of course, but the degree of

independence is determined by the balance between the derived

“active” (internal) explanation of its states and the “passive”

(external) explanation of its states.

A result of this is that no thing can be the cause of its own

destruction; the destruction of a thing is always through an external

cause. This is because the conatus of a thing is its essence, and its

essence revealed in a definition affirms what it is; thus in so far as a

thing is considered only in itself, in virtue of its essence, it cannot be

destroyed as that thing. This seems to make suicide impossible. But

Spinoza can answer that suicide is a case of being overwhelmed by

external causes. However, cases of rationally defensible self-sacrifice

complicate matters; the answer relates to Spinoza’s conception of

freedom as acting in accordance with universal rational principles.

Freedom does not consist in our being able to do otherwise than we

do; it is not contrasted with necessity; it is understood in opposition to

constraint. Everything that exists is necessary either by reason of its

98 Rationalism

essence or by reason of an external cause (another finite mode);

everything that does not exist is impossible either by reason of its

essence containing a contradiction, or for want of an external (efficient)

cause. The external chain of causation is ultimately necessary by

deriving from God’s essence; the impression we have of contingency is

merely the consequence of ignorance of causes. We are free in so far as

the explanation of what we do derives from our conative disposition to

behave in certain ways, as our essential natures meet each situation.

The exact nature of the conatus will vary between organisms. There is

nothing that is good or bad in itself; things are good or bad only in

relation to some conative disposition; things are good or bad for

someone or some kind of thing. Everything is free “in so far as it is in

itself’: that is, in so far as the explanation for what it does is derived

from its essence, which determines what it is. In this sense God is

absolutely free; not because what follows from His nature could be any

different from what it is—not because He could have “acted”

otherwise—but because God is totally self-determined, and thus totally

unconstrained. We are in a state of bondage in so far as we are the

slaves of external determinations and circumstances. This does not

mean we should live without emotion, but we should, in order to be

free, have active emotions following from reasoning; we should control

our passive emotions which are derived from external causes. In so far

as a man is externally caused, he acts under the influence of

inadequate ideas, failing to see how events must follow by logical

necessity from one another. The free man acts under the dictates of

reason, by the active causal determination of an internal logic; the

principles of reason are universal, thus in so far as we act because of

reason we make ourselves free in virtue of acting from causes

independent of particular circumstances.

This returns us to adequate ideas and their metaphysical connection

with Spinoza’s search for human happiness, contentment and

freedom. To understand this we have to remember that Spinoza

conflates logical and causal necessity. In so far as we entertain

adequate ideas, our ideas follow one another by their internal logic, a

logic that is independent of external causes. The explanation for the

occurrence of one idea, in so far as it is adequate, will be found in its

logical deduction from previous ideas; this gives a logical and causal

integrity, a self-sufficient, self-contained system based on universal

rational principles independent of external explanations and hence

external causes. There will be some bodily equivalent to this mental

aspect of human beings and in this sense we are free. What human

conatus ultimately seeks to preserve is this power of self-determination

itself. It reaches its highest degree when ideas are sub specie aeternitatis

because such ideas are absolutely necessary and universally true.

We are free when we act according to reason because the dictates of

reason are necessary, universal, categorical and thus independent of

Spinoza 99

context or particular situation. We act independently of contingent

particular external causes and circumstances if we act by reason: we

are then free.

Passive human emotions are controlled by reason to the highest

degree under the third kind of knowledge; for then the truth I grasp is

not an abstract deduction, but is intuited irresistibly in the particular

case; thereby it becomes not a truth I merely rationally accept, but one

that has force or power to effect changes in my emotional states. The

inference has force as well as validity. But since Spinoza is a strict

determinist, it is difficult to see what someone can do to bring about

the attitudes Spinoza thinks desirable; either one will be determined to

have them or one will not.

Our aim should be the attainment of a view of the world that is

detached and eternal. By striving for the completely adequate view

which is sub specie aeternitatis, of which only God is fully capable, one

comes to see the strict logical necessity of all that happens; all follows

from God’s immutable nature by logical necessity. We can thus

reconcile ourselves to the necessity of things. It no more makes sense

to hate a man who hits us than it makes sense to hate a tree that falls

on us; although in both cases this does not preclude our trying to do

anything about it, like getting out of the way—but we understand the

necessity of what happens through reason.

Although there seems nothing we can do to bring about human

happiness and peace of mind, they nevertheless consist in having a

certain attitude toward the world. The wise man engages in a life of

philosophical contemplation studying the rational and eternal: a life

of relative independence from the buffeting vicissitudes and

unreliability of particular circumstance, one which gives enduring

pleasure and grants peace of mind; the troubled mind is alleviated

when one views the world and events in one’s life sub specie

aeternitatis. The rational understanding that God is the ultimate

eternal cause of all things is what Spinoza calls the “intellectual love

of God”. To the extent that we entertain conceptions or ideas sub specie

aeternitatis, we free ourselves from the bondage of time, since such

conceptions are absolutely necessary and have no temporal reference;

and it is in this that our ultimate happiness lies; to the extent that we

do this, we participate in God’s eternal vision and the eternal

existence which is God’s existence.

Leibniz

Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716) was the son of a Professor of

Moral Philosophy at the University of Leipzig. Leibniz’s early

education, with a Lutheran religious background, would have

involved the study of Latin, Greek, theology, and Aristotelian logic.

100 Rationalism

He graduated from the University of Leipzig in 1663, and gained his

doctorate in 1666 from the University of Altdorf near Nuremberg. He

began his employment with the Baron of Boineburg who was first

minister to the Elector and Archbishop of Mainz, but in 1667,

following the death of Boineburg, he moved into the service of the

Duke of Brunswick in Hanover. One of his major duties was that of

librarian. Between 1672 and 1676, Leibniz was on a diplomatic

mission in Paris, which was at that time the centre of European

intellectual activity. There he met important thinkers such as

Malebranche, Arnauld (with whom Leibniz corresponded

extensively), and the physicist Huygens. Huygens, recognizing the

talent of Leibniz, set about improving Leibniz’s mathematical

knowledge. In Paris Leibniz would have been fully apprised of

Cartesian philosophy. In 1673 Leibniz visited London, where he met

the chemist Boyle and the Secretary of the Royal Society, Oldenburg;

on this visit he also became acquainted with the materialism of

Hobbes. In 1676 Leibniz went to Amsterdam in the hope that he

would find, in the work of Spinoza, answers to some of the problems

he perceived in Cartesian philosophy. He spent a month there; some

of the time was spent reading Spinoza’s Ethics, some in discussion

with the ailing Spinoza.

There were many influences on Leibniz’s philosophy; apart from

those already mentioned, he was impressed by Plato’s Phaedo and

Theaetetus and well acquainted with scholastic philosophy (derived

from Aristotle)—for example the notion of substantial forms.

Leibniz was a stupendous polymath, active in almost every

imaginable area of inquiry, from geology and mining engineering to

philosophy, mathematics and logic. He was indeed a mathematician of

genius, and discovered independently, and simultaneously with

Newton, the infinitesimal calculus. His fertility of mind left an array of

unfinished projects. Leibniz was a man capable of bouts of intense

intellectual activity; he is said to have spent several days at a time

sitting working at his desk—even sleeping in his chair. He suffered

from intellectual isolation in Hanover, where he spent most of his time.

During Leibniz’s lifetime there were few academic journals, and letters

were the chief means of exchanging ideas. Leibniz’s correspondence is

massive involving over 1,000 correspondents; in any single year he

frequently wrote to more than 150 people. He hoped that one day all

reasoning in various fields of inquiry could be united in one system, a

universal calculus of all reasoning, which would eliminate fruitless

disputes; answers to disagreements could be settled simply by

calculation.

Leibniz never married; he proposed, but the woman hesitated long

enough for him to think better of it. He was of medium height, with

sharply intelligent eyes; he had broad shoulders, but stooped and had

weak lungs. The last years of his life were ones of loneliness and

Leibniz 101

neglect. No member of the House of Brunswick bothered to attend his

funeral.

The philosophy of Leibniz is not like a building based on

unshakable foundations, it is more like a platform kept in balance by

constant adjustments to the weight put upon various fundamental

logical principles. These basic principles in Leibniz’s philosophy are

logically interconnected; and for this reason it has no definitive

starting place.

In Leibniz’s philosophy there is an intimate connection between

metaphysics and the fundamental nature of logic. This is a view which

has ancestors and heirs: it suggests that conclusions in and about the

basic structures of logic lay bare the basic structures of the world.

Certain important truths derived from logic are seen by Leibniz as

having consequences for any attempt to explain the fundamental nature

of the world which is studied in metaphysics. Probably the best

approach to Leibniz is to state what the basic truths of his thinking are,

and then proceed to see how he uses them to solve certain

philosophical problems. There are five major basic principles in the

philosophy of Leibniz.

(1) The predicate-in-subject principle: the nature of the proposition

This “inesse principle” holds that, in all true propositions that

which is predicated of a subject is contained within the concept of

the subject. All propositions are ultimately reducible to the

subject-predicate form. This gives a theory of truth in which in all

and only true propositions the predicates are contained in the

concept of the subject; all analytic propositions are true and all

true propositions are analytic.

(2) The principle of non-contradiction

This asserts that propositions p and not-p cannot both be true,

and that any proposition that implies a contradiction is

necessarily false; and any proposition whose denial implies a

contradiction is necessarily true.

(3) The identity of indiscernibles

This says that there cannot be two entities which have all their

properties in common. Entities which are identical in their lists of

qualities are the same entity; they are indiscernible.

(4) The principle of sufficient reason

There must be a sufficient reason (complete explanation) why

everything in the world is just so and not otherwise, even if we

cannot know what that reason is. There are to be admitted no

inexplicable truths about the world.

(5) The principle of perfection

Those propositions which describe the most perfect world—the

best of all possible worlds—are true. This amounts to saying that

God creates the most perfect world He can and it involves the

102 Rationalism

notion that the most perfect world is “simplest in hypotheses and

richest in phenomena”; God maximizes both plenitude or variety

of phenomena and order or simplicity of explanatory hypotheses.

Leibniz makes a fundamental distinction in his logic between “truths

of reason” (necessary or eternal truths) and “truths of fact” (contingent

truths). Truths of reason are those truths which, by a finite analysis,

show that their denial produces a contradiction, that is, an assertion of

(p and not-p). To assert a necessary truth is, on analysis, to assert an

identity. The analysis is a process of definitional substitution: for

example, 1+1 being substituted by definition for 2. Thus, to assert

2+2=4 is ultimately to assert 1+1+1+1=1+1+1+1; to deny 2+2=4 would

obviously produce the contradiction that 1+1+1+1¹1+1+1+1. To allow

that (p and not-p) could be true would be to threaten the possibility of

all meaningful talk, since we would fail to make the most basic

distinction required for any such talk, that between assertion and

denial. The assertion that p, and its denial, not-p, cannot

simultaneously be true. Truths of fact do not, if denied, entail a

contradiction; to deny “Alan is wearing a green shirt” does not seem to

involve any contradiction. Truths of reason are necessary truths in that

they could not be otherwise; they must be true; in any possible world

these truths must hold. Truths of fact are contingent, they could have

been otherwise; they might not have been true; there could be possible

worlds in which these truths do not hold. Leibniz accepts that truths of

reason can be known independently of any sense-experience, a priori;

whereas truths of fact can be known only through examining the

world, a posteriori.

Leibniz argues that although the meanings of the terms of a

language may to some degree be a matter of arbitrary definition, this

does not mean that either the contingent or the necessary truths

expressed in a language are dependent on contingent facts about

language; the only thing that is contingent is the particular form the

expression of such truths takes, not the logical status of the truths

themselves as either necessary or contingent. This distinction between

the truth expressed and the form of expression of a truth is particularly

important in the case of necessary truths, which he sees as eternal and

objective.

At first sight Leibniz’s philosophy can seem obviously false; some of

the basic principles listed above, far from being universal truths, seem

plainly false when applied to the world. For example, surely it is

possible (probable even) to have two identical objects? Surely it is far

from obvious that all truths are true in virtue of the predicates being

contained in the concept of their subject? It becomes clear, however,

that what Leibniz is applying the basic principles to is the underlying

structure of reality; this reality is a metaphysical reality that stands

behind the world as it appears; it is grasped by the intellect by an

Leibniz 103

inexorable logic as the way the world is and must (necessarily) be at its

most fundamental level if the most basic truths of reason are to hold. If

we accept Leibniz’s basic principles, then he argues that the nature of

reality is not how it appears to be, but really quite different. This is to

characterize substance, or the really real.

The examination of this underlying structure can begin by

considering substance. In Cartesian philosophy there are two “created

substances”: mind and matter. In Spinoza there is just a single

substance: “God or Nature”. What the Cartesian view seems to leave

out is an account of the individual, or identity. As we look around us it

seems obvious that some things are separate individuals capable of

remaining the same individual kind of thing while undergoing change,

whereas other things are merely “heaps” or collections of qualities

with no intrinsic unity. Compare a pile of pebbles, which is not a kind

of thing, with a crab found on a beach. Scholastic philosophy, derived

from Aristotle, had sought to take account of this through the notion of

“substantial forms”. Thus, the soul is the substantial form of the body,

for whatever may befall someone, so long as that person exists the soul

remains the same soul; without some such notion we cannot make

sense of someone being young and that same someone being old; any

change would, strictly speaking, produce a new entity, not the same

entity with a new property. The notion of individuals here aims to do

justice to the distinction we make between things which have an

intrinsic organic unity as kinds of thing, such as men and dogs have,

and things which are mere heaps of stuff, such as a pile of pebbles. But

in pursuing things that are true unities or true individuals, Leibniz

moves a long way beyond the Aristotelian commonsense substantial

forms which are natural kinds such as man or horse.

In the case of physical things the identification of real unities (things

that remain the same kind through change) is relatively unimportant; it

is possible to say that all physical things are portions of a single

extended substance. In the case of the person as mind, individuality

becomes of pressing concern; identity in this case is of vital

importance. Spinoza challenges the Cartesians to provide a principle

of individuating minds; if the only essential attribute of mind is

thought, it is difficult to see how there can be a plurality of distinct

mental substances or minds differentiated by essence. Spinoza’s

conclusion is to deny any sense of individuality as substances to either

physical things or minds; they have a limited individuality at the level

of modes, but are all modifications (modes) of the one substance,

without any ultimate substantial independent unity of their own.

Leibniz sides with the Cartesians in agreeing to a plurality of

substantial individuals, but makes the claim all-encompassing; for

anything in the world to be real, there must be at some deep level true

unities or individuals: completely autonomous entities.

This brings us to what Leibniz calls the “labyrinth of the

104 Rationalism

composition of the continuum”, which leads him to his conception of

substance, and thus to the ultimate nature of reality. Leibniz has the

same general conditions for substance as were found in Descartes and

Spinoza: that in considering the nature of the world and our

explanations of that world, we must, if we are not to enter into an

infinite regress, reach something which is (a) ontologically

independent or autonomous, and (b) self-explanatory. Substance is the

permanent stuff which stands behind appearances which are

secondary or derivative. Things appear to change in the world; the

explanation of these changes comes to an end at something that

remains the same, otherwise the explanation would go on for ever.

What is fully real is completely independent and self-explanatory; the

fully real is the ultimate logically unchanging constituent of change

and plurality. The explanation for anything, if we are not to regress

infinitely by always having to look to another thing for an explanation

outside that which we are explaining, must end in something that is

fully causally autonomous and fully the explanation for its own states.

Spinoza says that within true substance must lie the full explanation

of not only its nature but also its existence; and he contends that there

can only be one substance, and that is the totality of reality. Leibniz

demands not that a true substance should contain within itself the

reason for its own existence, but only that it should contain the reason

for its entire nature, that is, all its states.

In Leibniz’s view, in giving a rational account of the world, we must

give an account of what it is that is the ultimate constituent of reality;

that which does not alter through natural change, but is, rather, the

constituent of that change and, to avoid a regress of ontological

dependence, is not itself subject to natural alteration. Leibniz is

searching for that which, with respect to all natural means of change,

cannot be destroyed and is without parts, and so is indivisible; the

aggregation and dissolution of aggregates of such entities constitute all

perceived change and plurality. Leibniz identifies this true substance

as a monad (a word which derives from Greek meaning “unit alone”).

Ultimately we must reach such really independent substantial unities,

and each one is a unique kind, not merely a collection of parts; they do

not change by natural means, but exist or do not exist all at once. They

are perfectly determinate. Such entities are the only way to ensure that

we have identified genuine substance; something not ontologically or

rationally dependent on any further constituent elements because its

existence is all or nothing; each is a unique kind that either exists

complete, or ceases to exist completely; as a unique kind, if it changed

in any detail, it would cease to exist altogether. The ultimate

constituents of reality are an infinity of unique individual kinds called

monads.

The “labyrinth of the continuum” problem involves considering the

ultimate nature of the world, in particular the nature of matter. If the

Leibniz 105

world is a continuous whole, then its parts would seem to be unreal

arbitrary divisions; if, on the other hand, the parts are real, then the

world is not a continuum, but a collection of unrelated discontinuous

parts. The aim is to reconcile real wholes which are continuous with

real parts that are indivisible. We can consider this as the relation of

wholes to parts, and present it as a dilemma: extended whole things

are either finitely or infinitely divisible. If extended wholes are finitely

divisible, we reach atoms, which are real parts in being indivisible; but

then the whole that they make up becomes unreal because it is

discontinuous, a mere arbitrary heap of atoms between which there is

no intrinsic connection. The suggestion that there are, in addition,

forces between the atoms runs counter to atoms being the ultimate

constituents of reality in terms of which all else is explained and

constituted. Nor can the coherence of atoms be explained through an

interlocking system of hooks and eyes; anything capable of having

hooks and eyes would itself be capable of having parts in need of some

internal principle of cohesion. If extended wholes are infinitely

divisible, as the Cartesians thought, then the parts are unreal because

we have an infinite regress of divisibility; and this gives us a whole

with unreal parts. Leibniz argues, against physical atomism, that

anything extended must be divisible in principle. The solution in this

search for a substance which reconciles the real continuity of the world

with the real indivisibility of parts is to exclude extension from among

the qualities ascribed to substances: the most basic entities of the

world. Anything that can be divided would cease to exist as one thing,

and thus would be subject to external causes, and could not be a true

substance.

Ultimate substances are monads which have no extension; they are

purely qualitative (intensive), and have no quantitative (extensive)

properties; they are independent in all respects except for their

existence, for which they depend on God, and they are simple in being

without parts; they can be destroyed only by total annihilation (or

miracle), not natural change, for natural change is the constantly

changing aggregation of monads. This notion of substance is derived

by analogy from the non-spatial “I” or “soul”, for it is this that remains

the same through all the changes in our lives, so that we retain our

identity. Monads are the unchanging constituents of all natural change,

in that anything that happens in a monad is a product of its own

indwelling nature. There is an infinity of monads, each of which is a

unique individual kind in virtue of being identified by a unique

infinite list of predicates giving all its properties.

Leibniz conjoins the contingency of existence with the principle of

sufficient reason to give a proof of the existence of God. For every fact

or truth there must be a sufficient reason. Granted that something

exists, there must be a reason why something exists rather than

nothing; this reason cannot lie within the series of existing finite

106 Rationalism

things, for we would never among existing things find something

whose existence did not itself require further explanation. We must

find such a reason outside the world in a logically or metaphysically

necessary being—a being whose existence is not contingent—which is

the sufficient reason for its own existence. Another way of putting this

is to say that although the state of A is explained sufficiently by

reference to state B, so that we can explain this or that state from

within contingent events within the world, we cannot from within the

world of things with states explain why there are things with states at

all, why there are any states whatsoever. This argument relies on the

principle of sufficient reason having unlimited application; we might

instead be prepared to argue that “Why is there something rather than

nothing?” or “Why should there be anything at all?” is a question

which does not have an answer; it is a brute fact beyond which we

cannot go.

The world as it appears to us as matter in space and time is a set of

“well-founded phenomena” (phenomena bene fundata); the world as it

appears is our misperception of qualitative changes in the world of

monads; the world of appearances is secondary, and derived from the

underlying reality of an infinity of self-subsistent, self-explanatory

monads which are without parts. This solves the problem of

reconciling the continuity of the whole with the indivisible (simple)

reality of the parts: the whole is a plenum or continuum in virtue of

the adjacent monads differing infinitesimally from each other, and the

parts are real in that monads, being unextended, are indivisible.

Given the conception of true substance as monads, we can now

begin to apply to the world the basic principles of Leibniz’s

philosophy listed above. Monads, as true substances, must—except for

their dependence on God for their existence—be independent of all

other things, and must be completely self-explanatory; monads can be

both these things by all that is true of them being true analytically.

Each monad is its own complete concept in that it contains within its

essence the list of all the predicates, past, present and future, which are

true of that individual monad, apart from its existence. God is the only

substance that exists in conjunction with all possible worlds, for unlike

all other substances, that God exists is analytically part of His complete

concept or essence. Although the existence of all monads except God is

contingent, Leibniz sees no sense in the distinction between accidental

and essential properties of substantial individuals; all properties are

equally essential in being deducible from the complete concept of the

monad; and substantial individuals are individuated only through

considering their whole being or complete concept.

Leibniz thinks that Spinoza confuses determinism and extreme

necessitarianism. While, according to the principle of sufficient reason,

everything in the world must be fully determined—there must be

something which is sufficiently the reason for the way it is —this does

Leibniz 107

not mean that this or any other deterministic world is the only possible

deterministic world. That would involve confusing necessary and

contingent truths. Leibniz makes the distinction, and derives it from

the idea that all propositions are ultimately reducible to the subjectpredicate

form; a true proposition is such that the predicate is

contained in the concept of the subject.

Necessary truths (truths of reason), such as 2+2=4, are those whose

denial, in itself, implies a contradiction; they are unconditionally true

in all possible worlds; they have an absolute or metaphysical necessity.

Contingent truths (truths of fact) are those whose denial does not in

itself imply a logical contradiction; they are, however, conditionally or

hypothetically necessary when they are logically implied by some

other true proposition from which it would therefore be a

contradiction to deny they follow. Contingent truths (such as “Caesar

crossed the Rubicon”) are conditionally necessary truths, given that the

individual monadic substance (Caesar), of whom the truths are

predicated (crossed the Rubicon), exists. A proposition is conditionally

necessary (contingent) if its denial is not a contradiction in itself, but

there is some other proposition from which it logically follows. A

proposition is unconditionally necessary if, by finite analysis, its denial

is a contradiction in itself.

Unconditionally necessary truths (truths of reason) hold across all

possible worlds, and cannot determine which of the infinity of possible

worlds is actual. The principle of non-contradiction is sufficient to

account for metaphysically necessary truths, although Leibniz also

thinks such truths are eternal objective truths in being in the mind of

God. But in the case of contingent truths a further reason is needed to

account for why certain truths are actualized and not others. Truths are

contingent because God was not ultimately logically compelled by the

principle of non-contradiction to actualize those truths. The further

sufficient reason for contingent truths—what among the non-necessary

possibilities God actualizes—is found in the principle of perfection.

God creates the best, or most perfect, of possible worlds from a choice

of infinite possible worlds; the actual world is the one that maximizes

copossibles. All possible truths strive to be actual truths in that they

will be actual truths if their being true does not contradict the

actualization of some other possible truth. The principle of perfection

is the general test for truths of fact: the actual world is the one that

maximizes both plentiful variety (diversity) and order (simplest laws).

Existence is taken to be a perfection by Leibniz. All truths ultimately

refer to truths about the underlying monads, so all truths are

eventually analytic in that the predicates are contained in their subject;

but in the case of contingent truths this analysis is infinite, because to

show analyticity is equivalent to showing how that truth fits into the

most perfect world.

The principle of perfection gives us a criterion of truth for choosing

108 Rationalism

scientific laws: we should choose the law that explains the greatest

variety of phenomena with the greatest unifying simplicity.

Being true substances, monads are their own complete explanation,

except for the explanation of their existence; thus everything that is

true of them is true analytically; they are fully independent; so there

can be no causal interaction between them. Nevertheless, things in

nature appear to interact. This appearance is accounted for by

Leibniz’s notion of pre-established harmony. Leibniz denies causal

relations involving necessary connections between phenomena or

between the monads; he replaces these with pre-established harmony

and causal laws with functional relationships; in science we are simply

concerned with the determinate way one phenomenon varies in

relation to another. It is these functional relations that constitute laws

of nature, not some mysterious further notion of necessary connection.

Just as the existence of any monad is always contingent, and there is

an infinity of possible worlds, so there is an infinity of possible laws or

orders of nature. The only true causes, apart from God, in the sense of

producing deductive explanations, are the states of the monads

derived from within each monad itself.

Each monad is completely self-contained, but in a more or less

confused way every monad mirrors the entire universe. The mirroring

of the universe gives each monad a unique point of view; these

constitute active states of the monads which are “perceptions”; the

tendency to change between these perceptions is termed

“apperception”. The spontaneity of changing states of the monads

reflects Leibniz’s concern for dynamics; that an essential property of

substance must be force or activity, contrary to the inert extended

matter of Descartes. The monads have “no windows” through which

anything can come in or go out; monads are substances and there can

be no interaction between substances. God’s initial choice of what set

of monads to create arranges things so that the subsequent states of the

monads are perfectly coordinated or harmonized in accordance with

certain laws. This is analogous to two clocks being set at the same time:

they always strike correctly together at twelve o’clock and at all other

times on the hour even though they do not interact. God, in choosing

this world, arranges a perfect coordination of all its monadic elements.

Each monad has within it an active force whereby its states unfold.

This harmonious coordination of the monads involves a mirroring by

each monad of the states of all the other monads, which means that a

change in any one monad would entail a completely different

universe, for adjustments would have to be made in the systematic

arrangement everywhere else. The universe is a plenum; the plenum of

space corresponds to the infinitesimal qualitative differences between

monads which are perfectly compacted.

The world as it appears to us in space and time is a set of “wellfounded

phenomena” rather than a mere illusion; that is, the world of

Leibniz 109

appearances is systematically underpinned by states of the monads.

Appearances are correlated with something that is ultimately real.

Great distances in space are correlated with great qualitative

differences between monads, small distances with the reverse. Time is

correlated with our perceiving the unfolding of the states of the

monads. All apparent relations are reducible to truths about individual

monads. So we can say that the relation of A being heavier than B is

reducible to a truth about A weighing five tonnes and a truth about B

weighing one tonne.

We can now see why the identity of indiscernibles applies

universally, as Leibniz suggests. Leibniz’s principles apply to the

ultimate nature of the world, not to things as they merely appear. It

may be suggested that we could have two substances with identical

sets of true predicates, but at different places in space. But space, as

well as time, is itself something derived from truths predicated of the

monads. Once we see that all true predicates describing all states

whatsoever are contained within the ultimate monadic elements in the

universe, we see that there could not be two substances with identical

lists of predicates; there would be nothing left in virtue of which they

could be distinguished.

Leibniz’s view of the world can be summarized as follows. All

reality is made up of an infinity of soul-like monads; these are true

substances; they are ontologically independent of everything except

God, as they depend on Him for their existence, and no two monads

are alike. They are independent in the sense that all that is true of them

is deducible from their full concept or essential nature. Logically

necessary truths are true of all possible worlds in virtue of the

principle of non-contradiction alone. Only God is such that a denial of

His existence would be a contradiction; the existence of all other things

is contingent. Each monad when it comes into existence goes from

being an unactualized possibility to being an actualized possibility. But

given that God chooses to create particular monads (basic substantial

individuals), everything proceeds from the complete conception of

those individuals with necessity. Thus some truths are contingent

because, although given the creation of individual A all that happens

to A follows with necessity, it is only hypothetical necessity, since the

creation of A was not itself necessary.

The monads actualized are the reality that underlies appearances

which are systematically related to those monads so that the

appearances are well-founded phenomena. We explain the appearance

of causation and causal laws between phenomena, which all derive

from monads, by there being an analogue of strict rules governing the

non-causal coordination of the states of the monads.

God cannot choose what is impossible, and any universe must

include what is necessary; but among contingent truths—those truths

that are neither necessary nor impossible—God chooses from among

110 Rationalism

the possible, pure essences that are not actualized. There must,

however, be a sufficient reason for what God chooses if the universe is

to be fully rationally explicable; the reason why God chooses to

actualize some contingent possibilities rather than others cannot be

found in the principle of non-contradiction, since their nonactualization

would not imply a contradiction; the sufficient reason is

derived from the goodness of God, which means that, from an infinity

of possible worlds, He chooses the best of all possible worlds; a world

of maximum plenitude or variety tempered with greatest order or

simplicity of explanation.

It should not be supposed from Leibniz’s talk of soul-like monads

inhabiting everything that everything is thereby conscious.

Nevertheless, the distinction between different levels of monads is a

matter of degree and is dependent on their level of activity and the

clarity of their perceptions. It is in virtue of these factors being at a

high level in our case that we have the capacity for reason.

We are monads. The human body is a collection of monads which is

dominated by the powerful monad of the human mind: the “I” in us.

Leibniz’s doctrine of pre-established harmony solves the Cartesian

mind-body interaction problem; there is now no mystery concerning

interaction for it is only an appearance, but one that is well-founded

in the coordination of the monads. The appearance of mind-body

interaction is the coordination of the mind-monad and the bodymonads,

and this is just a special case of monad harmonization. There

is no more difficulty in explaining this than there is the coordination

between any other monads in the universe; God so arranges things

from their inception. The monads that correspond to the telephone

ringing are perfectly harmonized with the monad which is myself

having the experience of the telephone ringing, without the

experience of the ringing being caused by the ringing itself. The

intimate nature of the relation between the mind/self-monad and its

body-monads, is accounted for by the special characteristics of my

perceptions in relation to my body-monads. I am a structured

aggregate of monads, structured by the degree of activity and clarity

of perception of the monads. The dominant monad is that which has

the greatest degree of activity and clarity. Leibniz distinguishes three

levels of monads: self-conscious monads; conscious monads;

unconscious or bare monads.

A remaining question concerns human freedom. The notion of

human freedom in the sense of choosing otherwise at a particular

moment seems irreconcilable with all truths concerning substantial

individuals, such as particular people, being analytic truths.

Although the predicates true of an existing individual are only

hypothetically necessary, since they depend upon God’s original

decree to create that individual of which the predicates are true, this

does not seem sufficient for freedom. It makes all that I do contingent

Leibniz 111

in the sense that there is no logical contradiction in supposing that

the specific individual that is me might not have been created at all to

do what I do. But, given God’s decision to actualize the possible pure

essence A1

, and thereby create monad A1

in particular, then its states,

(a, b, c…) follow necessarily or deductively from the complete

concept of A1

. The existence of monad A1

is itself contingent—it is not

contradictory to deny that A1

was brought into being or actualized—

so any particular state of A1

, say c, is contingent in that “not-A1

c” is

not a logical contradiction. There are possible worlds in which A1

c

might not be true because A1

might not have been actualized—

brought into existence—at all, but instead A2

. But we do not say that

people are free if it is a mere logical possibility that what they do

might not have been done because they may not have existed at all.

When God decides to create an individual monad A, this means

creating the complete concept from which all truths predicated of the

subject A follow deductively from analysis of—are contained in—the

concept of that subject; thus to change any of these truths would be

to change the complete concept and thereby destroy that individual

as that particular individual and create another individual. It seems

that I could only be free by controlling my complete concept; but only

God has this control at the inception of that monad. All that is true

of—happens to—an individual in total defines that individual. That

Leibniz died in 1716 is a truth that follows necessarily, given the

initial creation of that particular individual, that Leibniz had to die in

1716; if this had not happened, we must be talking of a different

individual.

A worrying question remains for Leibniz, connected with the

problem of freedom. Does the inesse (predicate-in-subject) principle

apply to God? Does whatever God does follow deductively from His

complete concept, including His decrees as to which world to create?

If this is so, then the distinction between necessary and contingent

truths is in danger of collapsing, because God’s decree to create the

most perfect world itself follows deductively from God’s complete

concept; and then what follows could not be otherwise unless God

ceased to be God, destroying His own complete concept. It would

then be a logical contradiction to suppose God could have chosen

otherwise. This threatens a return to Spinoza’s extreme

necessitarianism.

Leibniz is a rationalist in the sense that he thinks reason can grasp

the true nature of reality that lies behind appearances; he is also a

rationalist in the sense that it ought in principle to be possible to deduce

all the states of the world from an analysis of the complete concepts of

actualized monadic substances. This a priori analysis is also infinite,

and not completable by human beings, and moreover refers to an

intelligible reality that lies behind appearances and accounts for those

appearances, not to the appearances themselves. However, Leibniz’s

112 Rationalism

metaphysics provides only a framework of principles which are vastly

too general to allow the deduction of specific scientific laws; and in

this sense Leibniz is an empiricist; we can discover specific scientific

laws concerning the connection and order of appearances only from

observation and experimentation.

Leibniz 113

continued to ...

https://sites.google.com/site/philosophygreekancient/philosophy-and-philosophers---an-introduction-to-western-philosophy---chapter-4