Philosophy and Philosophers - an Introduction to Western Philosophy - Chapter 3

back to ...

https://sites.google.com/site/philosophygreekancient/philosophy-and-philosophers---an-introduction-to-western-philosophy---chapter-1-1

or ...

CHAPTER THREE

Medieval philosophy:

Augustine, Aquinas, Ockham

In thinking of medieval philosophy, we must consider that we are

covering a vast time of around a thousand years including St

Augustine of Hippo (AD 354–430) and William of Ockham (c.1285–

1349) and extending until at least the time of the Renaissance. What

links the diversity of this period in Western philosophy is the rise to

dominance of Christian beliefs.

It would be wrong to conclude that thinkers in the medieval period

merely slavishly reiterated Christian dogma. There exists a tension in

medieval philosophy between reason and faith (from the Latin fidere,

to trust). The distinction, if there is admitted to be one at all, between

the reason of philosophy and the faith of theology is that between,

respectively, the insights of natural knowledge derived from the

natural cognitive powers of the intellect and senses, and the insights of

supernatural knowledge derived from divine revelation. The

distinction between philosophy and theology in the Middle Ages was

often not clear; generally it can be said that whereas philosophy

embodied rational arguments based on premises derivable from

naturally occurring powers of thought and the logical working out of

those premises (particularly from the philosophers of the ancient

world, especially Aristotle), theological arguments were based on

divine Christian premises derived from God—in particular from the

Bible and the opinions of the Church Fathers as collected in Peter

Lombard (c.1100–60), Four books of sentences. Christian thought insisted

that reason must succumb to the deliverances of faith or religious

belief where the two are irreconcilable.

It is characteristic of the dominant intellectual framework of the

scholars of the universities of the medieval period—called scholasticism—to

try to reconcile the demands of rational philosophy and the

demands of theological faith. The dissolution of scholasticism at the

end of the Middle Ages really amounts to the increasing triumph of

reason over faith; instead of Christian faith being the standard by

52

which rational arguments were to be judged, arguments were

increasingly followed wherever they led. Reason in scholasticism was

often used as a tool for supporting and deepening the understanding

of what was already believed to be true as a matter of religious faith.

After all, it is reasonable to suppose that even if some true beliefs are

accepted as true without sufficient argument, it might still be possible

to provide a rational justification for those true beliefs.

It was also thought that some truths were beyond the reach of

rational demonstration, but that this was not detrimental to these

truths, since their acceptance depended on religious faith. Belief in

truths of faith influenced rational arguments by affecting the premises

considered, and by judging the truth of the conclusions reached. If a

valid argument leads to a conclusion which is false—false, in this case,

according to religious faith—we know that at least one of the premises

must be false. However, the strain of combining reason and faith

eventually led to the separation of philosophy and theology; the

attempt had been made to fit philosophy in as a rational, but limited,

path to religious truth, but in the end it tended to undermine the body

of theological dogma.

The source of medieval theological doctrine was the Bible and the

Church Fathers; the problem presented to medieval thinkers was how

to reconcile beliefs from these sources with the beliefs and logical

arguments derived from Plato and Aristotle, and the attempts of

Arabic and Jewish thinkers from the tenth century to the twelfth

century to combine Plato and Aristotle. This reflects the high opinion

which was held of work from the ancient world; throughout the

medieval period, ancient philosophy was a source of authority which

toward the end of the period was used to oppose new arguments in

philosophy and science. Nearly all medieval philosophical literature

takes the form of either commentaries on previous works (especially

Aristotle), or disputes (quaestio disputata), where a question would be

raised and opposing solutions and objections considered and

eventually reconciled.

During the period from the second century to the fifth century AD,

while the Roman Empire remained intact, Platonism and

Neoplatonism had the upper hand in Christian thought; this is

apparent in the works of St Augustine. The greatest Neoplatonists

were Plotinus (AD 205–270), his disciple Porphyry (AD 233–304), and

later Proclus (c. AD 410–485). St Augustine adopted, but profoundly

modified, Platonism in the service of Christianity, to which he

converted in AD 386 at the age of thirty-two. But with the break-up of

the Roman Empire in the fifth century, Western Europe and the eastern

parts became separated, and from the sixth century to the eleventh

century we enter the Dark Ages.

During the Dark Ages nearly all serious intellectual activity ceased

in Western Europe, although it continued in the eastern provinces

Augustine, Aquinas, Ockham 53

conquered by the Arabs. From the fifth century onwards little of Plato

was known directly in Western Europe, and the full corpus of his

works did not re-emerge until the end of the Middle Ages; apart from

in the work of John Scotus Erigena (c.810–c.877) Neoplatonism as such

was also not rediscovered until the late twelfth and thirteenth

centuries, but its influence seeped in from around the fifth century

from the Arabs and the works of Pseudo-Dionysius, who was falsely

thought to be the Athenian converted by St Paul. Only the works of

Aristotle on logic remained known throughout the Middle Ages,

thanks largely to translations and commentaries by the Roman

philosopher Boethius (c. AD 480–524); but in the latter part of the

twelfth century other works of Aristotle were rediscovered, revealing

the ambitious system of metaphysics, science, and ethics.

In contrast to the period before the lacuna of the Dark Ages, after

that period it was Aristotelian philosophy, rather than Platonic

philosophy, which dominated Western European thinking. It was

during the period from the twelfth century to the fourteenth century

that the tensions between reason and faith intensified, and this gave

way to the progressive weakening, from the fourteenth century, of the

scholastic attempts to harmonize the two. The spread of new ideas

continued, aided by the invention of printing in the fifteenth century.

Intellectual changes were matched by the disintegration of the

medieval social order; the increased disrespect for ecclesiastical

authority and the rise of the rival power of the nation state

undermined the unity of Christendom. The door was open for the

Protestant Reformation of the sixteenth century and the greater

importance of the conscience of the individual and direct

understanding of Christianity. Philosophy became increasingly

autonomous after the fourteenth century, and the gap between

philosophy and theology was never again closed. By the end of the

medieval period both Christianity and Aristotelianism, as the

authoritative storehouses of correct opinions, were being replaced by a

different vision of intellectual and moral advancement in the light of

new philosophical and scientific ideas.

Given such a long period as the Middle Ages, it is unsurprising that

it is possible here to make only a small selection of its thinkers. Apart

from the thinkers discussed, among other important figures are

Abelard (1079–1142), St Anselm (1033–1109), St Bonaventure (1221–74)

and Duns Scotus (c.1266–1308). Augustine, Aquinas and Ockham are

chosen here as representative of different important aspects of the

period; they might be said to embody respectively medieval

philosophy’s inception, its consolidation, and the beginning of its

dissolution. Their views on the place of reason and faith can roughly

be summarized as follows: for Augustine there is no fundamental

distinction because reason depends on divine help to grasp eternal

truths; for Aquinas there is a distinction on the basis of the natural and

54 Medieval philosophy

the divine but the two are complementary and to a degree

overlapping; for Ockham reason and faith are distinct and have no

overlap.

Augustine

Augustine (AD 354–430) was born in Thagaste and died in Hippo, both

places in North Africa. Intellectually he straddles the gap between the

philosophers of ancient Greece and those of medieval Christian

Europe; he lived through the decline of the Roman Empire, which led

to the Dark Ages. The eventual historical outcome in the eleventh

century was the increased dominance of Christianity. Augustine’s

mother, Monica, was a Christian, but initially he did not accept the

faith and adopted Manichaeanism, which embodied some elements of

Christianity among elements from other religions. At the age of

seventeen he became a student of the University of Carthage where he

became a teacher of rhetoric and, while there, lived a life of

extravagant pleasure—including sexual pleasure—which was to

contrast starkly with his later monkish life. In AD 383 he moved to

teach in Rome; following financial problems, he accepted a teaching

post in Milan, where he greatly augmented his knowledge of ancient

Greek philosophy, in particular Neoplatonism. In Milan he was

impressed by the teachings of Ambrose, Bishop of Milan.

Augustine converted to Christianity in AD 386, and was baptized

the following year. He was then determined to enter the Church and

renounced worldly pleasures. Initially Augustine found no difficulty in

reconciling the dominant intellectual position of his day,

Neoplatonism, with the demands of Christian scripture; later he began

to see greater problems in reconciling their basic concepts. He soon

founded his own monastic community in Thagaste; but this lasted only

a couple of years through his being forced into the Catholic priesthood.

Augustine eventually became Bishop of Hippo in AD 396. He never

left North Africa for the last thirty-nine years of his life. In AD 410,

Rome was sacked by the Goths; in 429 the Vandals crossed to North

Africa from Spain and laid siege to Hippo; Augustine died in 430, aged

seventy-five, a short time before Hippo fell.

The character of Augustine’s thought is distinctly religious, rather

than purely philosophical; the discussion of certain philosophical

problems is not that of the disinterested academic, but has the

overriding purpose of identifying the path to the attainment of

blessedness or beatitude. This does not mean that what is true is

crudely identified with whatever makes one happy; it is rather the

other way around: knowledge of truths will make one happy. It is

assumed that the wise man and the happy man are one, and

knowledge of truths is part of the attainment of wisdom. The question

Augustine 55

of whether we can know truths is generally assumed to be answered

positively; the chief question is how we can attain that knowledge. The

overall religious purpose is twofold: first, to show how we can become

closer to God; secondly, to emphasize the importance of God by

showing how everything is closely dependent on God.

A problem of particular concern to Augustine is how we come to

know the universal necessary eternal truths described by Plato and the

Neoplatonists. First, however, Augustine sets about demolishing the

sceptic who asserts that no knowledge at all is possible. He points to a

range of things we clearly know to be true, which the sceptic cannot

possibly deny. He is not aiming to use these known truths as the

axiomatic foundation of the rest of knowledge, rather, if any of the

examples are admitted as known truths, then knowledge is possible,

and the absolute sceptic refuted.

(a) We know the law of non-contradiction, whereby if something

is true, it cannot also be the case at the same time that the

opposite is true.

(b) I know that I exist. “If I err, I exist” (“Si fallor, sum”). This

anticipates Descartes’ cogito; but it is not used in the same way;

Augustine is not concerned to use it to prove the existence of the

external world.

(c) Appearances cannot in themselves be false; I know infallibly

what my subjective experiences are, how things appear to me: my

“seemings”. I can know infallibly what seems to be the case; it is

my judgement, which goes beyond what seems to be the case,

which introduces the possibility of falsehoods.

(d) We clearly, even from the sceptic’s point of view, have the

capacity to doubt; so we know at least one truth: there is

doubting.

(e) We obviously know with certainty mathematical and geometrical

truths.

(f) We do not just know abstract principles, we also know real

existences. We know that we exist, that we are alive, and that we

understand these facts. Augustine points out that even if our

experience is really a dream, we nevertheless still know we were

alive. We are also conscious that we will certain things.

These bulwarks against scepticism are in one way or another derived

from introspection independently of the errors of the senses.

Augustine does not dismiss the senses as wholly deceptive. From the

fact that we can sometimes err in our sense-based judgements (for

example if we judge that a stick which appears bent in the water really

is bent), and can on any particular occasion err, it does not follow that

the senses cannot ever support true beliefs. That the senses deliver

truths less certain than those of mathematics does not mean the senses

do not deliver truths at all. However, Augustine supports the Platonic

56 Medieval philosophy

view that the lack of certainty and the relativity of judgement (the same

thing can appear different to different people) that beset the senses

make the objects of sense not suitable objects for true knowledge or

knowledge proper. The true objects of knowledge—the truths we can

know with greatest certainty—are truths that are universal, necessary,

and eternal; this is the highest form of knowledge, and sensory

knowledge the lowest. This means that these eternal truths have to be

found within the mind independently of sensory experience.

The problem arises of how eternal truths and our knowledge of

eternal truths are to be accounted for. The sensible world does not

provide us with the required immutable concepts and truths; the

human mind or soul, although immortal, is also temporal and

mutable. Augustine agrees with Plato that, just as transient truths are

accounted for by the mutable objects of the sensible world, so

universal necessary eternal truths are accounted for by their being

truths about eternal and immutable real objects. Moreover, these

eternal objects, and the truths concerning the relations of the concepts

of these objects, are independent of the human mind; they are truths

that we discover, which we cannot alter, and which are thereby

objective and common to all capable of reasoning. Such objects—

immaterial impersonal essences—referred to by Plato as Forms, are

identified by Augustine as ideas in the eternal, immutable mind of

God—they are the content of the divine mind. Such divine ideas

provide both truly objective fixed concepts and necessary truths by

being the objects of necessary judgements. Augustine, like Plato, has

no facility to account for the necessity of some truths which does not

involve realism, requiring there to be eternal objects to which those

truths correspond; he is unable to account for such necessary truths

merely on the basis of the logical relations between concepts, but

thinks that such truths require eternal objects which the eternal truths

are true of eternally.

Such necessary truths are available to us in the areas of mathematics

and geometry, but they are also possible in moral and aesthetic

judgements. The divine ideas provide perfect objects for the concepts

of number and geometrical forms; they also provide objective

standards for moral judgements concerning good and evil, and

aesthetic judgements concerning what is, or is not, beautiful. We do

not find perfect unity in our experience (we always find things with

parts which are thereby both one and many); we do not find absolute

goodness or evil or perfect beauty in our experience. We do not find

these things in themselves exemplified in the sensible world; but nor

are they mere constructions of the human mind. Rather, the divine

ideas in God’s mind are the absolute eternal standards by which all

else is judged, and which are assumed in our judgements.

The problem remains of how such eternal truths are accessible to the

non-eternal human mind. We have certainly been granted reason by

Augustine 57

which we are able to form true or false judgements not derivable from

sense-experience. But reason alone is not enough to account for our

knowledge of eternal truths. The human mind, in seeking eternal

truths, is seeking something beyond, and superior to, the mutable and

temporal mind, and to know such truths we need help. Such help

emanates from God in the form of “divine illumination”; and as an

illuminator God is present in us as He is present in all things. All

knowledge in Augustine is seen as a form of seeing. Just as the senses

see independent objects when they are illuminated by the sun, so

reason or intellect “sees” eternal truths when illuminated by the divine

light. This does not mean that in apprehending eternal truths we have

direct access to God’s nature—that is possible only after death, if at all.

We do not intellectually see God or the mind of God when we know

eternal truths. It is unclear whether the illumination implants the

concepts constituting necessary truths in our minds, or whether it

simply enables us to recognize which judgements are eternal and

necessary—it could indeed function in both ways. Perhaps the best

interpretation is to say that God does not directly infuse our minds

with the absolute concepts which constitute eternal truths, rather such

concepts are latent in the mind as copies of the archetypes in God’s

mind; divine illumination enables us to see intellectually which are the

eternal and necessary truths that are latent in our souls, and so to

recognize them as eternal and necessary. The latent concepts, and the

eternal truths connecting them, are in memoria; in this way ideas can be

in the mind without the mind being aware of those ideas. This accords

with our use of “memory” only in that it refers to ideas that can be in

the mind without our being always aware of them; it refers in

Augustine, most importantly, to the a priori content of minds, which is

not literally a remembrance of things past. Nevertheless the theory is

close to Plato’s account of our possessing a priori knowledge through

reminiscence.

Eternal truths are, of course, independent of and irrefutable by

sense-experience. So the true objects of knowledge are objective eternal

objects which depend on there being ontologically appropriate eternal

objects in the divine mind. Knowledge of eternal truths is granted by a

combination of natural human reason and supernatural divine

illumination. To benefit from such illumination we have to turn

towards God. This precludes the possibility of making a distinction

between natural reason and divine faith, for both are always needed

and mixed in the search for knowledge. This again emphasizes the

dependence of all things on God, in this case our capacity to know

eternal necessary truths.

The immateriality of the soul and its superiority to the body mean

that Augustine has great difficulty accounting for perceptions through

the corporeal organs. The superior nature of the soul’s mode of

existence involves the view that it cannot be affected by the inferior

58 Medieval philosophy

corporeal organs. At first he suggests that the mind uses the sense

organs as a tool. Later he tries to account for our awareness of changes

in our corporeal senses by the mind attending to or noticing such

changes; but it is difficult to see how, in this case, some causal

influence of the corporeal sense organs on the mind can be avoided.

Augustine uses the existence of eternal truths as proof of the

existence of God. Leibniz in the seventeenth century presents a

similar argument. The argument starts by getting one to admit that

there are eternal truths—immutable necessary truths, forced on

human beings. The only way to account for there being such

necessary inescapable truths is their objective existence as truths in an

eternal mind. We serve and are closer to God in so far as we

contemplate eternal ideas in the mind of God. This, however, is not

all that is required; we also need a spiritual purification—goodness—

in order to approach God.

Aquinas

Thomas Aquinas (1225–74) was born of a noble family at Roccasecca,

Italy. From the age of five he began studying at the Benedictine abbey

of Monte Cassino. In 1239 he went on to the University of Naples,

where he studied the seven liberal arts of grammar, logic, rhetoric,

arithmetic, geometry, music, and astronomy; while at Naples he

entered the Dominican Order. His entry into this Order, with its

emphasis on poverty and evangelism, was opposed by his family to

such an extent that he felt the need to escape to Paris; but while on

the road to Paris, he was abducted by his elder brother and locked up

in the family castle at Monte San Giovanni. He was later held

prisoner in Roccasecca for over a year. His family was unable either

to strip him literally of his Dominican robes, or to persuade him to

renounce the Order. While he was imprisoned his brothers sent him a

seductress; but he drove her from the room with a burning brand,

and the event merely reinforced his commitment to chastity.

Eventually his family relented and he returned to the Dominican

Order, first at the University of Paris in 1248, then at Cologne under

Albert the Great. During this time he became deeply versed in the

works of Aristotle.

He returned to Paris in 1252 for advanced study, and he lectured

there in theology until 1259. The next ten years of his life were spent at

various Dominican monasteries near Rome; in 1268 he returned to

teach again at the University of Paris. In 1272 he went to teach at the

University of Naples; but ill-health forced him to stop work. In 1273 he

had a mystical vision which caused him to regard his intellectual work

as worthless—he consequently ceased work on the massive Summa

theologiae. In 1274 he was journeying to Lyon for a meeting of the

Aquinas 59

church council, but had to rest at Fossanova, not far from his place of

birth, owing to illness; there he died in 1274.

Aquinas’ character seems to have been one of imperturbability, and

there is no doubting his sharpness of intellect. After his death the

teaching of Aquinas and Thomism formed the official doctrine of the

Dominicans, and this was adopted by some other Orders, but it was in

general relatively neglected by the Catholic Church. However, in the

nineteenth century Aquinas was commended by Pope Pius IX as the

premier figure of Catholic philosophy and theology.

Aquinas’ thought owes a great deal to Aristotle, and he attempts to

reconcile the central tenets of Aristotelian philosophy with Christian

dogma; these attempts deal with issues like the nature of God, our

means to salvation, and our understanding of the nature of creation.

Aquinas’ thought begins with the presupposition that the universe is,

at least partly, intelligible to finite human intellects: the structures and

laws of the universe can be understood.

Aquinas hatches a compromise between the conclusions derived

from our natural cognitive faculties (the senses and reason of secular

philosophy), and conclusions derived from divine revelation (the faith

of divine theology). One could dismiss one or the other as worthless,

or say that each one ultimately depends on the other, as Augustine

does; Aquinas however maintains the distinction, and says that they

are two generally autonomous ways of looking at the same object,

namely God. Whereas our natural cognition works “from below” to

know God through His effects as the creator of the world, divine

revelation—supernatural cognition—works “from above” to know

God as cause. Thus faith (fides) and scientific knowledge (scientia) are

sharply distinguished not by object, but by method. Both are cognitive

processes involving the assent of the intellect to truths; but whereas

faith requires the addition of the will in order to believe truths with

certainty, scientific knowledge requires no such application of will

since the intellect either intuitively “sees” truths immediately, or

argues validly to establish truths from intuitively known premises.

Within theology we can make a distinction between supernatural

and natural theology: respectively, truths revealed about God and

other elements of Christian doctrine which depend on divine

revelation (grace, which derives from the Latin gratia, meaning

favour), and those that can be known through natural powers of

cognition. There is also an overlap of truths: some truths are both

revealed and known through being provable by natural cognition. In

this sense natural theology is part of supernatural theology. So the

totality of truths grasped by the human mind has three parts.

(A) That which is believed only in virtue of divine illumination or

revelation.

(B) That which is believed by divine revelation and is known by

being provable by natural cognition.

60 Medieval philosophy

(C) That which is known by natural cognition.

Ideally a conflict will never arise between the deliverances of the

revelations of faith, and the proofs of natural reason; but in the latter

we are fallible, and a conclusion derived from reasoning that conflicts

irreconcilably with a properly understood truth of faith shows that we

have made a mistake in our reasoning. But we have, ideally, a twofold

route to some Christian truths.

Natural cognition is made up of the senses and the intellect, and of

these the senses are primary both genetically and logically for

knowledge of existing things and for possession of abstract ideas; all

the materials of our intellectual faculty—our ideas—are abstracted

ultimately from the senses. The intellect is involved in forming

judgements about what we perceive: that what we perceive really

exists, that it has certain properties and that it is a certain kind of

thing. The intellect also engages in abstract reasoning. The senses see

X; the intellect actively judges X as X; the intellect goes on to

understand and think of X when it is not perceived. The intellect goes

beyond the sensory experience in forming a judgement, which is an

affirmation or denial of some truth; this goes beyond the mere fact of

one’s having a certain experience. The sensible aspects of particular

things (red, sweet, warm, etc.) are given through sense-perception

alone; but the intelligible aspects of particular things (that they exist,

that they actually have certain properties and are certain kinds of

things) are derived not from the passive association of the ideas of

senses alone, but in conjunction with an active synthesizing and

interpretative intellect, which forms from the ideas of sense complex

conceptions and hypotheses. The intellect forms concepts—universal

ideas—of things by abstracting general ideas from sense-experience;

the intellect thinks of the nature of those things and how they are

connected to other things by understanding those general concepts.

Aquinas follows Aristotle closely in not supposing that essences (the

“whatness” of things) can exist apart from individual things;

philosophically speaking, there is no universale ante rem, that is, essence

before or apart from individual things; rather, essence is universale in re,

present in individual things, in the sense that real things are real

substances and are always compounded of two elements.

(a) Essence (essentia, quidditas, natura). This is “whatness”; viewed

epistemologically through a definition it tells us what a thing is.

(b) Existence (esse, which is a form of the Latin verb “to be”; but esse

is also used as a noun). This is the fact that a thing is.

The difference between a mere essence (quidditas) and real substance is

existence (esse); existence is what turns, by being “added” to it, a

merely potential essence into an actual individual substance. This is

the primary move from potentiality to actuality: mere potential

Aquinas 61

existence to actual existence. Once a certain essence is actualized, there

is a further process of change from potential to actualization as the

essence brought into existence strives to fulfil its potential within its

kind; an acorn (an actual acorn, but potential tree) will grow into a tree

(an actual tree). The terms above in (a) and (b) roughly correlate with

the following.

(a’) potential (potentia, potency)

(b’) actuality (actus, act).

The difference between essence and potentiality is partly one of

generality; to speak of essence is to imply some determinate

potentiality: a certain “so-and-so”; whereas to speak of potentiality is

to suggest mere possibility: some “so-and-so” or other. Anything that

is not logically impossible has potentiality in the second sense.

To know the essence of something is to know its real definition, the

essential features without which a thing would cease to be the kind or

sort of thing it is. The accidental features that an individual kind of

thing has are those features which it can lose or gain while remaining

the same kind of thing. It is most important to note that Aquinas

thinks that in giving a definition of the essential nature of an

individual, he is giving a real definition; that is, the definitions are not

a function of the way we conceptually happen to divide up the world,

rather the definitions, if true, reflect accurately the way the world

divides itself up.

The distinction between essence and existence is also a real

distinction. That is not to say we ever encounter in the world pure

existence or pure essence, but the distinction is real in the sense of

being independent of human cognition; it is not a distinction projected

onto the world by the mind. For to say what something is is one thing,

but to say that it is, is another; we can know what a dog is—the essence

“dogness”—without committing ourselves to affirming either the

existence or non-existence of dogs. Another way of putting this is to

say that essences have no existential import. This is true for all entities

except God; He alone has existence as part of His essence. For all other

beings, existence (esse) is something added to essence—added to a

mere determinate potentiality—by God; thus all things depend

ultimately on God. Essence and existence are never found in

separation; nothing simply is, a thing always is a determinate kind of

thing; to be is to be a “so-and-so”; to be is always a determinate way of

being. The obvious limitation of individual substances is explained by

essences receiving esse and at the same time limiting that esse to a

certain way of being. In God the esse is unlimited, and also eternal;

there are no limits to God’s being; He has “fullness of being”.

For Aquinas as a Christian, unlike for Aristotle, the existence of

things cannot be taken for granted but requires explanation. Aristotle

thought that the world exists eternally, and that any change in the

62 Medieval philosophy

world is not a change from absolute non-existence (nothing) to

absolute existence or vice versa, but a change either of an accident, or

from one form of substantial being to another. For example a

substantial change occurs when a tree ceases to be a tree and becomes

ash when it is burnt. For Aquinas the very fact of existence itself is a

problem; given that nothing, except God, has existence as part of its

essence, an explanation beyond the essences of things is required to

explain why anything is at all; that explanation derives from God the

creator who adds esse to essences.

Apart from God, no essence is fully actualized. In God’s case, the

positive essence is fully actualized. God does not merely actualize His

divine essence; He actualizes it all the way, so to speak. If we take any

other entity, we will always have an entity which has potential within

its kind—its essence will not be fully actualized; there will be aspects

of its essence that it does not fully exemplify. God’s absolute perfection

is to be identified with His complete actualization of His positive

divine essence—He is pure act (actus purus); He contains no

unactualized potential of His positive divine essence.

The relation between essence and existence, and between potency

and actuality, applies to any substance whatsoever. It must not be

supposed that all real substances must be material or corporeal; not

only material things have esse. The analysis of material things

introduces another pair of terms,

(i) form (morphe)

(ii) matter (hyle).

This gives a hylemorphic theory of material substance. In the case of

material substances, potential corresponds to matter; the matter is

potentially a “so-and-so”, and is actualized as an individual separable

thing of a certain kind by taking on a certain form; that form is

actualized in that matter. However, pure matter (materia prima) would

be completely ineffable; it would by definition possess no character, no

whatness. Only by the addition of form in act in the matter does it

become a determinate “so-and-so”; matter as a mere determinable is

not possible, although we can understand what we mean when we talk

of it. The notion of pure potentiality as pure matter is impossible as

something that exists—it would indeed be a contradiction—but it is

intelligible conceptually. Indeed, pure potentiality cannot in any case

exist. The soul is the form of human beings; and souls are individuated

by the matter of the body of which they are the soul. But pure forms

can exist, as well as material substances, when certain non-material

essences receive esse. What Aquinas has in mind here seems to be a

three-level hierarchy of being.

(1) Corporeal substances. These are matter and form; they are

perishable and finite.

Aquinas 63

(2) Incorporeal limited substances. These are pure form—spiritual

entities, which although imperishable are finite. The kinds of

entities Aquinas has in mind here are the separated soul and

angels.

(3) Incorporeal unlimited substance. This is pure act; all aspects of

the positive essence receive existence (esse). This is, in fact, God

who alone exists necessarily, since in Him alone His way of being

must be conceived as including existence; in Him no distinction

can be made between the essence He has and His existence, for

He necessarily completely actualizes His essence, all the positive

aspects of the divine essence there are; there is nothing He is only

potentially; there is nothing divinely positive He is not.

The object of human knowledge in intellectual cognition is the

discovery of what essence is actualized in any individual. We

understand substances in so far as we come to know the essence that is

in act—is esse—in substances. Aquinas holds that for each known truth

there must always be something existing (esse) that corresponds to that

truth. Individual substances are understood by us not as individuals

qua individuals (individual things as such: features which constitute

their particularity), but through knowing that which is general or

common in them that defines the nature of the kind in which all the

individuals of a certain kind share. Thus we know a dog in so far as we

know the real definition of “dog”, and hence understand it in its

essential dogness; we do not know the dog in its full particularity

because the terms we apply always have some generality of

application.

An essence is what must be the case for a thing to be what it is: that

which a thing cannot lack and still be what it is. Thus understanding

what a thing is—its essence—is logically independent of the fact that a

thing is, its existence. I can understand what a dog or a Phoenix is

independently of whether it is. The essence of X is given in a set of

necessary and sufficient conditions a, b, c for X to be the kind of thing

it is. In this way we can form a real definition: X is of a specific kind if,

and only if, a, b, c are true of X. When we are correctly said to know X,

the aspect of X we know is that set of features X has in common with

all and only other Xs of the same kind. We would not understand a

clock as a clock by referring to its colour or the scratch on the face, but

in so far as we understand that in virtue of which a clock is a clock:

what makes it distinctively a clock and not another kind of thing. We

understand the nature of the clock by understanding those common

features shared by all and only clocks which define them as clocks.

Then what makes a clock or a dog a particular clock or dog cannot be

its essence or form, since that is common to all instances of the same

kind, but must, Aquinas argues, be its being formed of a quantitatively

or numerically different parcel of matter.

64 Medieval philosophy

With incorporeal or spiritual substances such a method of

individuation is clearly inapplicable; he suggests that each incorporeal

substance must be individuated by essence; that is, the essence of each

soul or angel must be different, so each angel differs in essence as a

dog does from a cat; each angel is of a different, and unique, kind.

Aquinas strikes a middle course on the question of the reality of

universals. Universals are general concepts or categories with which

we talk about the world and with which we classify particulars into

kinds or sorts. Aquinas adopts a form of moderate realism. He rejects

the full realism of Plato, whereby universals exist as real entities in a

world of intelligible Forms independently of the world of sensible

things. He also rejects conventionalism, whereby universal concepts

are mere arbitrary, subjective mental constructs, for which the most

that can perhaps be said is that they are made for our convenience.

Aquinas compromises: universals are objective in being real,

extramental and immutable, but they exist in instances of individual

kinds of things and cannot exist apart from those instances. Universals

or kinds as such exist only in virtue of there being individual actual

instances of those kinds. Only individuals exist, but the natures of

those individuals radically resemble each other and are understood

from this essential common resembling nature as being members of

universal classes or species—for example, humanity, dogness, justice.

Individual material things of the same kind are the same kind in virtue

of sharing a substantial form; but that substantial form, although it

cannot exist apart from the individuals who share it, is nevertheless

something objective in the world, and derives its objectivity from the

really existing common nature shared by individuals of the same class.

The world divides itself into kinds, so to speak; the kinds are real and

there to be discovered, and are independent of our subjective mental

classifications. Abstracted forms are derived from individual instances;

the logical rules of the combination of such forms are revealed in real

definitions; the forms, through real definitions, give concepts which

have fixed immutable objective meaning; the forms and their logical

combination, known through their concepts, are the proper objects of

knowledge. Knowledge of the forms, through real definitions, is

derived from sensory experience and the intellectual faculty of

abstracting general concepts from the resembling essential nature of

instances of individuals of the same sort. Thus although universals do

not exist as separate entities, they are objective in reflecting the

extramental common defining real natures of individuals.

Ockham

William of Ockham (c.1285–1349) was born in the village of Ockham

outside Guildford near London. The details of his life are obscure, and

Ockham 65

often a matter of conjecture. Of his early life nothing definite is known.

We know that he was ordained subdeacon in 1306. He became a

student at the University of Oxford around 1309 and soon a member of

the Franciscan Order. He pursued his studies at Oxford until 1315;

from 1315 to 1317 he gave lectures on the Bible and, from 1317 to 1319,

lectures on the hugely influential Four books of sentences by Peter

Lombard. The Four books of sentences was compiled around 1150; it

brought together the teachings of the early Church Fathers—especially

St Augustine—and it was a cornerstone of Christian theology.

Ockham completed the requirements for the degree of Magister

theologiae, but he never became a Master occupying the Chair of

Theology. This was probably due to the opposition of Lutterell, a keen

Thomist, to the appointment of Ockham; Lutterell had been removed

from the post of Chancellor of the University by 1322. Lutterell left in

1323 for Avignon, the residence of Pope John XXII; there he set about

blackening Ockham’s name by accusing him of holding in his

Commentary on the Sentences heretical and dangerous views. Ockham

was summoned to Avignon in 1324 to have his views examined; the

examination lasted for three years. Ockham refused to retract his

views.

Michael of Cesena, the General of the Franciscan Order, also faced

the condemnation of the Pope for his Order’s espousal of absolute

apostolic poverty. Ockham joined forces with Michael, his superior,

and, together with another Franciscan, Bonogratia, they fled from

Avignon in 1328, seeking the protection of the German Emperor, Louis

of Bavaria. Louis had installed in Rome an antipope who had in return

crowned him head of the Roman Empire. Ockham, Michael and

Bonogratia joined the new Emperor in Munich, and were

excommunicated from the Catholic Church and their own Order. In

1342 Michael died; in 1347 Louis also died. This left Ockham in an

extremely vulnerable position; he sought reconciliation with the

Church and his Order. Before any reconciliation could be decided

upon, Ockham died in 1349, probably of the prevalent Black Death. He

was buried in the old Franciscan church in Munich; but in 1802 his

remains were moved to a place that is still unknown.

Ockham may be seen as something of a philosophical Janus, since

like that god, his philosophy looks in two opposite directions; it looks

back to the Middle Ages, and it looks forward to some of the ideas of

the Enlightenment—to the empiricism of John Locke (1632–1704) and

David Hume (1711–76), and aspects of materialism—but the forwardlooking

characteristics must not be overemphasized; Ockham would

have seen himself not as a philosophical revolutionary, but merely as

reinterpreting an already established tradition. The chief problem was

still to reconcile Aristotle and Christianity. A sharp distinction is found

in Ockham’s thought between reason and faith. The truths of theology

are based on revelation and are a matter of faith, and they are neither

66 Medieval philosophy

provable nor refutable by any process of natural cognition in secular

philosophy. Theology retreats to a domain of truths about which

natural reason can have nothing to say.

The chief characteristic of the tradition to which Ockham was heir

was realism in its various forms: that the human intellect can discover,

in the particular things perceived by sense-experience, a real objective

system of universal common essences which become somehow

individualized, and which can either have an independent existence

from, or exist as a real part of, particular individuals. These essences

have an extralinguistic reality over and above—really distinct from—

the particular features of individuals which are classified in virtue of

the essence as being the same kind. Then from the linguistic

connections in meaning between the terms that refer to these real

essences we can know necessary truths about an extralinguistic reality.

Necessary truths can be known about the world we perceive and about

God. The universals we intellectually abstract—humanity or horse—

from particular individuals are not merely arbitrary subjective mental

or linguistic constructs, or merely derived from objective particular

features of individual things, but have a real ontologically distinct

reference in or beyond the world, independent of individuals, or their

particular features, whereby such individuals fall into the general class

designated by universal terms. In short, the linguistic distinction we

make between universal and particular terms has a real ontological

counterpart.

The problem of universals—what if anything universal terms stand

for—to which realism is one answer, centres on the problem of the

relationship between the universality of concepts and our apparently

encountering as independent objects only particulars. Realists would

argue that, without a suitable system of real entities for universal terms

to refer to, our system of universal terms will be entirely arbitrary,

conventional and subjective. This would make any science, which will

inevitably be couched in general or universal terms (such as “body”,

“animal”, “heavy”), an arbitrary mental construction among other

possible constructions with no objective validity derived from its

reflecting an extramental reality; this leaves open the rationally

anarchic possibility of a variety of different incommensurable

conceptual systems of scientific explanation between which we can

have no common grounds or independent standard for a rational

choice.

Moderate medieval realism does not go all the way with Platonism,

which suggests that universal essences or “whatness”—such as

humanity, horseness, justice—can exist as Forms quite independently

of all particular individuals which are grouped together in virtue of

those universal essences. Moderate realism follows Aristotle in

maintaining that in some way there is a real distinction in the world

between the common universal essence and the individuating

Ockham 67

characteristics of particular things sharing that essence. Moderate

realism holds that, although the common universal essences of

individuals and those individuals cannot be found existing in

separation, the distinction between universal essences and particular

individuals which can be made in thought nevertheless reflects a real

distinction in things in the world. The same common nature or essence

is really distinct from things in respect of what makes them particular,

as it exists in all the particulars of the same sort, and it is this that

makes them the kind of things they are.

The forward-looking aspect of Ockham’s philosophy resides in his

rejection of realism and his alternative explanation: his rejection of the

reality of a world of intelligible, literally common, essences or forms

ontologically or really distinct from the characteristics that pick out

individuals, and his consequent propagation of nominalism and

empiricism. His nominalism and empiricism are closely linked.

Ockham objects to the idea of some literally common nature shared

by all and only individuals of the same kind; if this common nature is

singular and indivisible, then it cannot be shared by many individuals,

and if the common nature is many, then each instance of the many

must be singular and itself individual and cannot be shared in

common between various individuals.

Ockham does not deny that the world falls into a mind-independent

system of natural kinds—in this sense he is still a realist. What he

denies in his nominalism is that a condition for its being correct to talk

about a natural order of kinds of individual things is the positing of

common natures or essences, ontologically or really distinct from the

individualizing characteristics, and shared by all and only the

individual things of the same kind. Moreover, he thinks that such a

view is an unnecessary misinterpretation of Aristotle. He denies in this

nominalism that universals subsist as ideas in the mind of God prior to

their actualization (their receiving esse); God is not necessitated even to

this extent; He is not constrained to create, if He creates at all, a

particular world-system of kinds. There is, therefore, no system of

essences whose necessary relations could be known a priori.

For Ockham, universality is a property primarily of thoughts,

secondarily of language which expresses thoughts, and not of entities

or natures distinct from the individual characteristics of things in the

world. Universality is the property of a thought, a generalized

abstractive cognition, which is entertained in such a way as to be

equally truly predicable of, or usable of, more than one individual.

Thus the term “city” is used of London, Paris, New York. Ockham’s

view is roughly equivalent to saying that universals are concepts,

along with the commitment that the being of the concepts is as mental

states. Nominalism holds that the only thing strictly in common

between individuals falling under a universal name is that they all fall

under that name.

68 Medieval philosophy

The question arises as to why we apply the same universal name to

many individuals. Ockham’s empiricism complements his nominalism

by maintaining that there are no literally common real essences

graspable by the intellect, but only individuals apprehended by the

senses between which we perceive similarities in the individuating

characteristics, and it is from these albeit objective but nevertheless

contingent similarities that we derive the meanings of universal terms

and their range of application to a determinate class of individuals.

Thus the connotation or meaning of a universal term such as

“humanity” is whatever characteristics we perceive as similar between

all those individuals whereby we classify them as human. This list of

characteristics defines “humanity” and gives us criteria for deciding

whether any given individual should be included under that heading;

the denotation or reference of the term “humanity” is then just all

individual human beings. The meaning of a universal term such as

“humanity” is not explained by its denoting a common essence distinct

from the characteristics of particular human beings; its meaning is

explained by the similar characteristics of a number of individual men,

in virtue of which we call them all “men”. Talk of something “similar”

between many individuals may seem to evoke a common nature again;

but Ockham would say that we perceive similarity not by perceiving

some literally identical common nature distinct from the individuating

characteristics, but in virtue of a resemblance between the

characteristics which are part of the natures or features of the

individuals themselves.

Thus Ockham denies that there is a metaphysical problem of

determining in virtue of what universals are individualized, since

there are no such universals to be individuated. Aquinas had

suggested that universals are individuated in virtue of their being

exemplified in a different parcel of stuff or matter; Duns Scotus (c.

1266–1308) rejected this and suggested that beside universal essences—

what features a thing cannot lack and still be the kind of thing it is—

there is an individuating essence, the haecceitas or individualizing

“thisness” of a kind, which gives this horse. Ockham, however, has the

logical problem of showing how to reduce universal concepts to terms

that signify what he regards as the only existents, individuals; and he

has the epistemological problem of saying how from experiencing only

individuals we form universal concepts.

It should be pointed out that for Ockham the primary carriers of

meanings are mental expressions—states of mind—with which written

and spoken expressions become associated by convention. Mental

signs mean what they stand for directly; linguistic expressions are

signs only conventionally; thus the mental sign for rain is the same for

the speaker of any language, but its linguistic expression may be

different.

Terms are elements in propositions and they take on different

Ockham 69

functions depending on the proposition they are in; in particular they

acquire a determinate “standing for” (suppositio) function. Here we are

talking of natural terms or concepts, not the conventional terms of any

particular language; the terms “homme” and “man” are conventional

terms for the same natural sign or concept. Ockham distinguishes

between “terms of the first intention” and “terms of the second

intention”. For example, a singular term such as “Socrates” stands as a

natural sign for the thing Socrates and is of the “first intention”. A

universal term such as “species” is of the “second intention” and

stands not immediately for things that are not themselves signs, but

for other signs that do stand immediately as signs for things. Thus,

“Socrates” is a sign for the individual man Socrates; “species” stands

not immediately for individual things, but for terms of the “first

intention” such as “man”, “horse” and “dog”; the term “species” can

be predicated of the terms “man”, “horse” and “dog”, each of which

stands for all the members of a different class of individuals, and says

of these terms that they are all species-terms which are the names of

many things. Ockham contends that the realist belief in universal

terms standing, albeit obliquely or indirectly, for entities distinct from

individual entities is a consequence of confusing the two levels of

intentions: terms that stand for things, and terms that stand for terms;

that is, talk about things in an object language, and talk about the

object language in a metalanguage. If we confuse these two we are

tempted to suppose mistakenly that metalinguistic talk is about things.

Nominalism is in accord with the most famous feature of Ockham’s

thought, “Ockham’s razor”; this is a methodological principle

designed to keep the number of kinds of entities posited as distinct in

the world to a minimum—it is a principle of parsimony. Ockham’s

objection to realism and the positing of real ontologically distinct

essences is partly just that they are unnecessary to explain how we

come to classify things in a universal manner. Logically what this

means is that apparent reference to real abstract entities by universal

terms can in principle always be replaced by an analysis of universal

terms, so that they refer only to individuals. Thus “man” signifies

merely the total disjunction: Socrates, or Plato, or Aquinas, and so on.

Relational terms such as “taller” do not denote entities distinct from

the individuals to which they apply; in referring to A being taller than

B, we are referring to only two entities, and the truth “A is taller than

B’’ is reduced to a truth about A (A is six feet tall) and a truth about B

(B is five feet tall). The only sorts of thing that exist are individuals:

individual substances and their individual qualities.

It has been objected that Ockham’s criticism of the real distinction

between essences and individuals misses the point, for he attacks a

position which the most important medieval thinkers such as Aquinas

and Duns Scotus never sought to defend. The accusation is that

Ockham thought that if the distinction between the common essence of

70 Medieval philosophy

individuals and what constitutes their individuality were to be a real

distinction, then it must be a distinction between things of the same

sort, such as exists between any two existing individuals, and that

Ockham was led to this assumption by thinking of the attribution of

essences as noun-like rather than verb-like. If we think of the

attribution of essences or forms as more verb-like than noun-like—as

in “humanizing”, “equinizing”—we will see that there is a formal

objective extralinguistic distinction being made which is separable in

thought and is nevertheless not a distinction between separable

individual entities. It is not clear whether this pointing up of the

distinction between the grammatically verb-like use of ascribed

essences to things, as opposed to naming those same things, is

sufficient to maintain that there is a corresponding metaphysical

extralinguistic distinction between the common natures and the

particular features of individuals.

Moving to Ockham’s epistemology, we find that he distinguishes

between intellectual acts of apprehension and judgement:

apprehension or cognition is awareness on the basis of which a

judgement can be made, which is an intellectual assent to the truth or

falsity of a proposition. He further contrasts an intuitive cognition, on

the basis of which one is in a position to make a judgement of

contingent fact which is evident, and an abstract cognition, on the basis

of which we are not in a position to make an evident judgement of

contingent fact—such contingent judgement will concern whether an

object exists or whether it has some contingent property. The objects of

these cognitions are the same; what differs is the manner in which they

are apprehended; in an intuitive cognition the apprehension of the

object is caused immediately by the object apprehended; in an abstract

cognition the apprehension of the object is not caused immediately by

the object apprehended, but it always presupposes an intuitive

cognition of the object at some previous time. From an intuitive

cognition of X, or X as f, we can judge evidently that it is true that X

exists, or that X is f. Once we have an intuitive cognition of X, or X as f,

it can be stored in the memory as an acquired capacity (habitus) so we

can then form an abstract cognition of X, or X as f, which is divorced

from X existing or not existing, or X actually being f or not being f; but

this abstract cognition of X, or X as f, does not put us in the position to

make the judgement we might make concerning X evident. If I saw you

sitting in my study, I would be in a position to form an evident

judgement that it is true that you are sitting in my study; if, however, I

did not see you, but nevertheless formed from an abstractive cognition

the judgement that you were sitting in my study, then the judgement,

although it may be true, may also be false, and is not in any case

evident. Ockham is realist with respect to individual objects and their

individual properties in the external world: he does not doubt that in

mental acts of intuitive cognition what we directly apprehend is

Ockham 71

constituted by objects and their properties just as they really are in the

external world outside the mind. In intuitive cognition there is no

distinction between the way things seem to us and the way they really

are; the way they seem is how they are. Ockham holds that we can also

have intuitive cognition of introspectively apprehended mental states.

In the natural course of events, if we have an intuitive cognition of

X, then X exists, since X is a part of the cause of the cognition of X;

thus the judgement that X exists is evident. However, since it is

logically possible, God could produce supernaturally in us the same

mental state as a cognitive intuition—that is, phenomenologically the

same intuition, which is as if we were having a real intuitive

cognition—without the object existing, which would in natural

circumstances suffice for the evident judgement that the object exists.

But, in fact, God does not normally act like this, although He did so in

the case of the prophets.

Ockham’s empiricism surfaces in his account of explanations of the

natural world. Strictly speaking, science is concerned with necessary

universal truths concerning that which must be and cannot be

otherwise, expressed in propositions that are proved from self-evident

propositions by syllogistic deductive reasoning. But one needs

experience even to understand the meaning of the terms in

propositions—at least those that stand for things—even when, once

understood, they are self-evident propositions; for to understand the

meaning of the terms we need a primary experience of what the terms

stand for. For Ockham, as for Locke, there are no innate ideas which

could account for this; all our ideas, by association with which words

get their meaning, are derived from experience.

Science in a narrow sense includes only necessary provable

propositions; and since the existence and nature of the world are in all

ways contingent (that which may be true or may be false), it would

seem that a science of the world is not strictly possible. In

mathematics, geometry, metaphysics and theology, there are truths

which are quite independent of whether any world exists or not and

these are suitable subjects for scientific knowledge. However, Ockham

extends science (scientia) to include hypothetical or conditional

premises of demonstrations or proofs, and evident contingent

judgements made on the basis of intuitive cognitions.

Ockham maintains that God must be supremely unnecessitated,

being completely free and completely omnipotent. This leads him to

assert that the world is radically contingent in its existence and nature;

necessity applies only within thought and language, not to events or

things in the world. All that is not self-contradictory is possible; what

is actual but not necessary cannot be determined by a priori reason or

logic alone; reason and logic can determine only what is necessary,

impossible and possible, not what is actual and contingent among

what is possible. Logically speaking in the world anything could

72 Medieval philosophy

follow from anything else, and the only way to determine what things

there are, and how things are connected, is by experience. Ockham

does not deny that there are real objective causal connections in

nature; the order we appear to see is not merely derived from the

conventional use of expressions; he does not deny that there is a

natural order in the world that can form the basis for the discovery of

universal connections which are the aim of science; what he denies is

that these universal connections in fact have any metaphysical

necessity which could be discovered through deductive reasoning

alone. All those connections between things and events that are not

merely analytically true by the definitions which give identifying

criteria are radically contingent and can be known to hold only from

intuitive cognitions. Thus to have new knowledge of connections

which goes beyond what is already assumed in definitions, as is the

case with causal connections, we rely on experience. If all connections

between things and events were analytic and merely followed from

definitions, then working them out would be a purely linguistic

matter. Clearly we suppose that most connections are not definitional

in this way, in which case the connections can be known to hold only

by experience.

Ockham does not tackle the question which was to concern Hume

much later, in the eighteenth century, of how we can rationally justify

the belief that there is any objective natural system of laws at all—the

problem of the “uniformity of nature”—or how the evidence from the

experience of a finite number of singular instances can ever justify the

assertion of universal laws of the form “All As are Bs” or causal

connections of the form “If A occurs, then B must occur”. Ockham

thinks that God has, as a matter of fact, so arranged things that we can

discover objective regular natural laws; but these laws are only

contingently—in fact—true, and God could have arranged the laws

quite differently; He was not bound by any kind of necessity to

arrange things the way He actually arranged them. It follows that if

the arrangement of things is not a matter of necessity, the discovery of

the arranged regularities is not knowable by a priori deductive

reasoning alone, which can give us knowledge only of necessities (that

which must be), impossibilities (that which cannot be) and possibilities

(that which may or may not be); rather, we require experience in order

to discover what actual contingent (that which is, but need not be)

arrangement exists. God maintains the natural order so that we can

rely (barring miracles) on B always following A; A is a sign that B will

follow, and we can be confident, thanks to God, that B will follow. This

is not to say that God, and not A, is the real cause of B, but merely that

God chooses to maintain a natural order whereby, albeit contingently,

A causes B.

Ockham 73

continued to ...

https://sites.google.com/site/philosophygreekancient/philosophy-and-philosophers---an-introduction-to-western-philosophy---chapter-1-3