Philosophy and Philosophers - an Introduction to Western Philosophy - Chapter 10

back to ...

https://sites.google.com/site/philosophygreekancient/philosophy-and-philosophers---an-introduction-to-western-philosophy---chapter-2

or ...

CHAPTER TEN

Logical positivism and falsificationism: Ayer, Popper

It is perhaps unnecessary to make any connection between A.J.Ayer

and Karl R.Popper other than to point out that they both had great

influence on Western philosophy during the middle part of this

century, an influence that has continued to this day. However, a

common historical and intellectual connection is the Vienna Circle;

this was a group that met in Vienna during the 1920s and 1930s and

developed the philosophy of logical positivism, which was intent on

setting philosophy on a sure footing so that the scope of its tasks was

clear. Logical positivism, by way of a theory of meaning, involves the

elimination of much of traditional philosophy, in particular

metaphysics and also theology, as literally meaningless. What this

amounted to was the view that the investigation of any substantial

facts about the world was the province of science alone, not

philosophy, which could be concerned only with conceptual

elucidation and the linguistic task of precise definition. Both Ayer

and Popper attended the meetings of the Vienna Circle, but whereas

Ayer initially became a powerful advocate of its views, Popper,

although deeply interested, like the Vienna Circle, in the philosophy

and methodology of science, was critical of logical positivism.

Popper aims to demarcate science from non-science so as to

understand better the nature of scientific knowledge. Non-science

includes pseudo-science: areas which are not scientific but claim to

be so. It does not follow from this that what is non-science, including

pseudo-science, is thereby literally meaningless, as logical positivism

supposed, or even that it is untrue. Ayer has always had a great

interest in the problem of meaning, which Popper regards as a

largely fruitless field of philosophical investigation if regarded as an

end in itself. What perhaps unites Ayer and Popper, although they

259

are by no means alone in this, is their view that the heart of

philosophy is epistemology, and in particular the nature of empirical

knowledge.

Ayer

Alfred Jules Ayer (1910–89) was educated at Eton and Christ

Church, Oxford; his tutor in philosophy at Oxford was Gilbert Ryle

(1900–76). After graduating, he thought of going to Cambridge to

study with Wittgenstein; instead he went to study in Vienna in 1932

in order to find out more about the logical positivist philosophy of

the Vienna Circle. After a short period in Vienna he returned to

Oxford and became a lecturer in philosophy at Christ Church. In

1936 he published Language, truth and logic. While we must allow for

differences within the logical positivist movement, Language, truth

and logic states clearly what is essential to the doctrine of logical

positivism. In 1940 he joined the Welsh Guards and worked for

most of the war in military intelligence. He returned to Oxford in

1945 to become Dean of Wadham College. From 1946 to 1959 he was

Grote Professor of the Philosophy of Mind and Logic at University

College London. From 1959 until his retirement in 1978 he was

Wykeham Professor of Logic in the University of Oxford. In 1970 he

was knighted. Although he came to reject the most radical

proposals of logical positivism, Ayer remained a close follower of

the British tradition of empiricism and logical analysis. It was

Wittgenstein’s Tractatus that set Ayer on the course which led to

Language, truth and logic. However, the greatest influences on Ayer

were Russell and Hume. He continued to admire Bertrand Russell,

regarding him as probably the greatest philosopher of the twentieth

century; and, like Russell, he was an enthusiastic atheist. Ayer also

became interested in the American pragmatists, such as William

James (1842–1910). Again, like Russell, Ayer was a passionate

advocate of reason, and thought that intellectual honesty demanded

that we seek sufficient evidence for any beliefs that might be

proposed for acceptance.

The motivation for logical positivism stems from two connected

lines of thought: (I) the unity of science, and (II) the elimination of

metaphysics. In short, this amounts to the view that really all science

forms a single system; it alone is able to give true characterizations of

the nature of the world which can in the end be exhaustive. The unity

of science means that all branches of scientific inquiry have a

common epistemological basis: it is that determining the truth or

falsity of scientific theories about the nature of the world depends

entirely on an appeal to the evidence of experience and observation.

The elimination of metaphysics complements this, because

260 Logical positivism and falsificationism

metaphysics commonly supposes there is some way of determining

the nature of the world—perhaps its real or essential nature beyond

appearances—other than by an appeal to experience and observation.

The apparent assertions by metaphysics about the nature of the

world are, according to logical positivism, not true or false, but

nonsense—literally meaningless. With the elimination of metaphysics

as a source of knowledge about the world, science is unified as a

system of factual propositions, that is, statements whose truth or

falsity and, indeed, meaning depend on their being open to the test

of the facts of experience.

Propositions are what is determinately true or false: that is, they are

literally meaningful. Propositions are what literally meaningful

indicative sentences (sentences which grammatically appear to state

things) of any particular language express; this is important because

sentences of different languages can express the same proposition, as

in it is raining and il pleut. The criterion for a sentence is that it is

grammatically well formed, that is a necessary condition for it to be

meaningful, otherwise it is mere gibberish, such as “foot a fight will”.

The logical positivists argue that many grammatically well formed

sentences do not express genuine propositions, although being

grammatically well formed sentences they may appear to do so.

Sentences that appear to express a proposition, whether they do so or

not, Ayer calls putative propositions or statements. The logical

positivists argue that all genuine propositions are either analytic/

tautologies or verifiable by experience; statements—that is, indicative

sentences which appear to express propositions—which are neither

analytic nor verifiable by experience are literally meaningless or

nonsense. Sentences and statements that do not express genuine

propositions may be meaningful in some other way—they may have

poetic or emotive significance—but they are not literally meaningful. If

a statement is literally meaningless, then the question of its truth or

falsity cannot arise.

It has to be the case that a distinction is made between sentences

being meaningful in some broader sense than literally meaningful

because otherwise the criterion of literal meaningfulness would have

no possible application; in order to discover if a statement is analytic

or empirically verifiable, we already have to understand what it

means.

A sentence expresses an analytic proposition if, and only if, its truth or

falsity follows solely from the definition of the terms it contains. Thus

“All bachelors are unmarried” is analytic, since the predicate

“unmarried” is part of the definition of “bachelor”; establishing the

truth or falsity of the proposition consists in merely unpacking the

definition of its terms. The truth or falsity of analytic propositions

depends entirely on the meaning of the symbols in the sentence the

proposition expresses. Analytic propositions are true or false, and can

Ayer 261

be known to be so, a priori, that is, independently of the evidence of

experience; they are also devoid of factual content as they make no

claim about the world; their truth or falsity is compatible with any

evidence of experience whatsoever. That which is necessary is that

which must be and cannot be otherwise. If an analytic proposition is

true, it is necessarily true—it must be true and cannot be false. If an

analytic proposition is false, it is necessarily false—it must be false and

cannot be true. The denial of a true analytic proposition implies a

logical contradiction.

A sentence expresses an empirically verifiable proposition if, and only

if, some possible experience is relevant to determining its truth or

falsity. The truth or falsity of such empirically verifiable or factually

significant propositions cannot be determined merely by examination

of the definition or meaning of the symbols in the sentence the

proposition expresses. Thus “The cat is on the mat” is a factually

significant proposition; its truth or falsity does not follow from the

meaning of the terms it contains—it is not an analytic but a synthetic

proposition; its truth or falsity can only be determined a posteriori by

consulting experience. That which is contingent is that which may or

may not be: that which could be otherwise. If an empirically verifiable

proposition is true, then it is contingently true—it is true, but could

have been false. If an empirically verifiable proposition is contingently

false, it is false, but could have been true. The denial of an empirically

verifiable proposition never implies a logical contradiction.

The two classes of analytic and empirically verifiable statements are

mutually exclusive and collectively exhaustive of all literally

meaningful statements: they are the totality of genuine propositions.

That is, it is a necessary and sufficient condition for a statement to be

literally meaningful, and so capable of being true or false—a

proposition—that it be either analytic or empirically verifiable. Put

another way, a statement is a genuine proposition if and only if it is

either analytic or empirically verifiable, otherwise it is nonsense.

Metaphysics generally attempts to describe the essential structure of

reality: what the real world must ultimately be like according to

intellectual argument, although it may appear otherwise. Plato speaks

of fixed “Forms” beyond the flux of experience and space and time,

but accessible to the intellect, defining the “whatness” of things;

Leibniz speaks of non-spatial “monads” as the indivisible,

indestructible substance of the world which remain the same through

all natural change; Hegel speaks of the fully real as “The Absolute”,

the universe as ultimately a self-thinking totality. There are also

theological statements asserting the existence and nature of an eternal

transcendent God outside space and time.

Metaphysics, with theology, is eliminated as literally meaningless

because what it characteristically proffers as propositions are not

genuine propositions at all. The need to be clear about what are

262 Logical positivism and falsificationism

genuine propositions arises from the fact that we are misled by the

surface appearance of statements in metaphysics into thinking they

express propositions; but we know they do not express propositions

because they do not say anything whose truth or falsity can be

determined in the only two ways possible: by their being analytic or by

their being empirically verifiable. Metaphysics is disposed of not

because it is false, but because it is composed of statements which are

largely nonsense; it may appear to be composed of propositions—

statements that can be true or false—but really it is composed of

statements incapable of being either true or false because their truth or

falsity cannot be established even in principle by the only two ways

possible. If we are to say that any of the statements of metaphysics is

literally meaningful, then it must be translatable into statements that

are analytic or empirically verifiable. However, if a statement is

analytic, it tells us nothing about the world, and if it is empirically

verifiable, then it ceases to be a metaphysical statement at all, but

merely becomes part of the body of scientific theory testable by

observation. Neither translation is congenial to the metaphysician who

wishes to contend that his statements both say something about the

world—are factually significant—and cannot be settled by empirical

verification; but it is impossible, Ayer argues, that both these

conditions can be simultaneously satisfied. Indeed, metaphysics often

claims to speak of the world behind or beyond the world as it appears.

Either a statement says something about the world, in which case it is

empirically verifiable, or a statement says nothing about the world; no

statement can be about the world and not be empirically verifiable.

Therefore metaphysics, which purports to produce truths and

refutations of falsehoods about the nature of the world or reality in

statements which are empirically unverifiable, is impossible; it

produces only literal nonsense. Metaphysics makes only literally

meaningless assertions and raises spurious questions; it is, in short,

composed of meaningless pseudo-propositions which have the

appearances of genuine propositions. It follows that there can in reality

be no genuine disputes between metaphysicians: if “p” is a

metaphysical statement, it is literally meaningless, but then “not-p” is

also meaningless.

Logical positivism holds that all a priori propositions are analytic

and, although necessary, are necessary only because they are factually

empty: they say nothing about the world, but reveal only the

conventional meanings of words. All a posteriori propositions are

synthetic and contingent, but they are, whether true or false, factually

informative: they say something about the world. Contrary to the view

of a philosopher such as Kant, there can be no a priori, necessary

propositions that are synthetic. These considerations can be

summarized in the following diagram:

Ayer 263

All genuine propositions—that is to say, all propositions—fall into

either, but not both, of the shaded areas: A and D. No propositions fall

into the unshaded areas: B and C. There are therefore only two classes

of genuine propositions:

A: a priori/analytic/necessary.

D: a posteriori/synthetic/contingent.

All statements that fail to fall into the classes A or D are not propositions

at all; they are incapable of being true or false—they are not

literally meaningful—although they may be meaningful in some

other way.

Thus, in so far as metaphysics does contain literally meaningful

propositions, it consists either of analytic propositions, which tell us

nothing about the world, whose truth or falsity can be determined a

priori, or synthetic propositions, which do purport to tell us something

about the world, whose truth or falsity can be determined only a

posteriori. There is no special class of metaphysical propositions which

are at once a priori and tell us something about the world: no facts can

be known a priori.

All the statements of logic, mathematics and geometry express nonempirical,

non-factual, propositions, that are a priori valid and

necessary in virtue of their being analytic or tautologies: their truth

depends solely on the meaning of the symbols of which their

statements are composed. They are also devoid of factual content; the

reason such truths are necessary is just that they do not make any

assertions about the world that could be confuted or confirmed by the

evidence of experience. We do not have to suppose, in order to explain

our a priori knowledge of necessary truths, that the truths refer to some

realm of entities transcending experience. All a priori analytic truths—

including those of logic, mathematics and geometry—are not about

anything at all, but simply reflect the meaning we have chosen to give

to linguistic signs.

Philosophers such as Kant have argued that there is a special class

of propositions which are a priori synthetic and necessary. Kant

accepted that propositions such as “All bachelors are unmarried” are

analytic, necessary, their denial implying a contradiction; the concept

of the predicate is implicity contained in the concept or definition of

the subject, so to assert that someone is a bachelor, but not unmarried,

is a logical contradiction. Such propositions, Kant agreed, tell us

nothing about the world. However, Kant thought that the propositions

264 Logical positivism and falsificationism

of arithmetic and geometry were at once a priori and synthetic. He then

felt obliged to construct an elaborate philosophical system in order to

explain how this was possible. How could a proposition which is

synthetic, so that its denial does not entail a logical contradiction, be

true, and be known to be true, a priori! It appeared to Kant that

arithmetical propositions such as 7+5=12 were known a priori, and

were necessary truths, and yet were synthetic because it was possible to

think of 7+5 without thinking of 12. Ayer argues that this is a purely

psychological point. Kant’s explanation for our knowledge of synthetic

a priori truths is that they characterize the form we impose on the

matter of sensation and so are valid for the world only as it appears.

Ayer thinks such an explanation quite unnecessary: the truth of 7+5=12

and the a priori knowledge of that truth depend entirely on the

conventional definition of the terms in it, and it is thus quite

independent of empirical evidence or, a priori. The same argument

applies to geometrical truths; such truths are not a description of

physical space, they merely unravel whatever definition of the terms

we started off with. Logical propositions such as “Either p or not-p” are

true regardless of any facts of experience and depend for their truth

entirely on the meaning of the signs composing them; they are

tautologies because they always come out true regardless of what

propositions are substituted in them provided the substitution is done

uniformly. It follows that such analytic propositions, although

necessary, are trivially true or devoid of factual content. The

proposition “either it is raining or it is not raining” tells us nothing

whatsoever about the weather, and is true independently of whatever

the facts about the weather are; its truth excludes nothing at all.

If it is the case that all a priori propositions are analytic, how do we

explain the usefulness of logic, mathematics and geometry, and their

ability to surprise us? The explanation lies entirely in the limitations of

our intellect. In the case of complex analytic propositions we are, as a

matter of fact, intellectually incapable of seeing at once all the

consequences of the definitions we adopt. To an intellect of sufficient

power, the complex prepositional theorems of logic, mathematics and

geometry would be of no more interest than “A=A” is to us. The

interest for us of analytic propositions is that we cannot always see

immediately everything that our definitions imply.

This brings us to what for Ayer is the function of philosophy.

Philosophy cannot determine the nature of reality, as metaphysics

would suggest. Any proposition concerning the nature of reality would

be a factual scientific or common-sense proposition whose truth or

falsity could be established only by the test of experience and not by

philosophy as such. The function of philosophy, once it is demonstrated

that metaphysics is literally meaningless, is analysis and clarification.

Analysis is a branch of logic and consists of giving precise definitions of

concepts, or presenting the logical consequences of definitions, of terms

Ayer 265

used in science and common sense; thus all the propositions of

philosophy are analytic. The function of philosophy is to translate talk of

one sort into logically equivalent talk of another sort, an activity which

has purely linguistic significance. Philosophy itself can produce no new

factual knowledge about the world but can only deduce the logical

consequences of propositions whose truth or falsity, if they are not

analytic—and so devoid of factual content—is determined by the facts.

It is important to establish more exactly what is meant by empirical

verifiability in order to determine which non-analytic statements are

propositions. Such propositions must in all cases be capable of being

verified or falsified by experience. It is necessary, however, to make

two sets of distinctions here:

(a) verification in practice

(a’) verification in principle

(b) “strong” or conclusive verification

(b’) “weak” or probabilistic verification.

In both cases Ayer says he adopts the more liberal of the two

alternatives, (a’) and (b’). The reason for this is that (a) would entail

denying as literally meaningful all sorts of empirical propositions

because we could not in fact verify them. Thus the proposition “There

are mountains on a particular planet on the other side of the galaxy” is

not a proposition which I could in fact verify; perhaps it never will be

verified; nevertheless we know what would verify the proposition; we

can conceive of certain logically possible observations which could in

principle be made which would verify or falsify the proposition. There

would be an inevitable tendency for (a) to lead to solipsism whereby

my possible knowledge extended only as far as propositions

describing my actual private experiences. Adopting (b) would also

prove or exclude too much, for no empirical proposition can be

conclusively verified or falsified; empirical observations can only render

the truth or falsity of a proposition more or less probable. One reason

for this is that, whatever empirical proposition we take, the conclusion

or import we draw from observations relevant to determining the truth

or falsity of the proposition will always depend on assuming the truth

of certain other propositions describing the circumstances of the

observation. But then the truth or falsity of these other propositions

describing the initial conditions of the empirical test could themselves,

if they are factually significant, be tested by experience, and so on.

Also most of the propositions of natural science of the form “All A is

B” would be rendered literally meaningless if we adopted (b) because

we could not even in principle examine what is an open infinite class

of cases; there may always be cases we have not examined, and there is

no way of demonstrating that there are not such cases. In short, Ayer

thinks all empirical propositions are hypotheses because there is no way

of absolutely confirming or refuting such propositions.

266 Logical positivism and falsificationism

Ayer admits that empirical hypotheses do not confront experience

singly, but only as part of a system of propositions. Thus if an

observation appears to verify or refute a given hypothesis, it is always

logically possible for us to refuse to admit to the significance of the

observation by modifying the other hypotheses that gave the

observation its significance as evidence of a particular sort. Take the

proposition “All trees have leaves”; suppose we test the truth or falsity

of this proposition by making observations; whatever observations we

make, they always depend on certain other empirical hypotheses

connecting the observation and the proposition under test; for

example, that we are not suffering from an illusion, or we have

correctly identified something as a leaf. Some of the logical positivists

argued that there is a class of isolated “basic propositions” about

which it is impossible for us to be mistaken, and which can be

conclusively confirmed or refuted by experience because they refer

only to immediate experience. Ayer initially thought that any factually

significant proposition involves using general classificatory terms

(such as “red”) which it is always possible to misapply, and so no

factual proposition can be conclusively verified or refuted, since we

can always find out we have made a mistake in the light of further

evidence.

Thus, according to “weak” verifiability (b’), a genuine proposition—

a statement capable of being true or false—if it is not analytic, is an

empirical hypothesis the truth or falsity of which experiences could, in

principle, render more or less probable. The purpose of formulating

scientific theories is essentially predictive and pragmatic: it is therefore

the very meaning of rational behaviour that we adopt those theories

and methods which function to enable us to anticipate and control the

course of our experiences. The function of theories, and the purpose of

testing them, is to produce theories which are more efficient

instruments for describing and anticipating experiences. Whether a

theory will be successful in this way can be revealed not by a priori

argument but only by its success in practice, but it is always logically

possible that it may fail in cases we have not observed.

The “weak” verification principle thus states that all literally

meaningful non-analytic statements are in principle verifiable by being

rendered more or less probable by propositions which describe specific

experiences; all other statements, apart from analytic ones, are literally

meaningless. So all statements which are not analytic propositions and

cannot be verified by experience are literally meaningless: they do not

express a proposition at all. The verification principle gives a criterion

for distinguishing the literally meaningless from the literally

meaningful.

The attempt to give a precise formulation of empirical verifiability

leads Ayer into difficulty. Ayer’s initial version of the “weak”

verifiability principle is: a non-analytic statement is a genuine factual

Ayer 267

proposition—and thus not literally meaningless—if we can deduce

from it, along with certain other statements describing the conditions

under which relevant observation could take place, some experiential

proposition which refers to actual or possible experience (sensecontents),

which cannot be deduced from those other statements alone.

This formulation is, however, faulty as it excludes nothing as a literally

meaningful proposition. If N is any statement you like, even one that is

meaningless or metaphysical, and O is an experiential proposition,

then O is deducible from [(if N then O) and N], without being

deducible from O alone. This means that N would, by the criterion, be

verifiable and hence a literally meaningful proposition even though it

can be any statement at all. If we say that the “other statements” must

be themselves factually significant, then we have got no further, since

distinguishing factually significant statements was the point of the

criterion, and we cannot assume we can distinguish which statements

are factual. Ayer tries to rectify this fault, but he does not succeed in

discovering a precise formulation that includes and excludes just what

he wants.

One way of avoiding such problems would be to adopt the “strong”

verification principle (b). In this case it is not just a matter of some

empirical evidence being deducible which would be favourable or

unfavourable to the truth of a proposition. “Strong” verification

demands that the whole content of empirical or factual propositions,

when fully analyzed, be expressible in wholly experiential

propositions or observation-statements. Indeed, sometimes Ayer does

seem to be working with the “strong” verifiability principle, whereby

any genuine non-analytic proposition must, if we are to understand it,

be translatable into propositions which describe only actual or possible

experiences: sense-contents. A statement is then a factually significant

proposition if and only if it can be completely defined as a logically

equivalent set of purely experiential propositions which entails the

original proposition and is entailed by it; the two statements are thus

identical. The literal meaning of any factual proposition is then no

more or less than a set of propositions describing some actual

(categorical) or possible (hypothetical) experiences. The thinking

behind this is that understanding the meaning of factually significant

statements involves having, at least in principle, access to experiencing

the factual conditions under which the proposition which expresses

the statement would be true; that is, experience in principle of the

truth-conditions of a proposition is required to understand the literal

meaning of the statement it expresses. All factually significant

propositions, such as “I am now sitting in front of a table”, are

abbreviations for a complex of propositions describing sense-contents

alone. If any part of a statement appears to refer to something that is

not even in principle a feature of actual or possible experience, then we

can be sure that that part of the statement is without factual

268 Logical positivism and falsificationism

significance, and is meaningless unless it is analytic: that part is literal

nonsense, what we say is literally “sense-less”. Only by expressing a

non-analytic statement using symbols which wholly stand for sensecontents

are we able to make literally intelligible what it is we are

talking about.

It is surely this “strong” notion of verifiability that leads Ayer to

various forms of philosophical analysis and reductionism. Such

analyses are epistemological and are ontologically neutral. We find this

reduction at work, for example, in his analysis of the concepts of a

material object and of causation. In the case of material objects Ayer is

led to phenomenalism: statements about material objects, if they are

meaningful at all, must be wholly translatable into experiential

propositions which do not mention material objects; what we mean

when we talk about “material objects” is nothing more than some set

of actual or possible sense-experiences. Such a translation defines

“material object”. This disposes of the problem of the existence of the

external world arising from our making inferences from propositions

concerning our experiences to propositions referring to material

objects, because there is no gap in the end between experiences and

material objects: to talk of material objects is just to talk of certain

ordered collections of actual or possible experiences, and the set of

propositions describing particular sense-contents is identical to a

proposition describing a material object. The same analysis applies to

causation. Ayer agrees with Hume that “C causes E” is not a logical

relation: if “C causes E” is a non-analytic, factual, proposition then to

assert C occurs but deny E occurs is never a logical contradiction. To

say that “C causes E” is to say no more than that “whenever C, then,

under certain circumstances, E”; there is nothing further in our

experience, and indeed nothing further at all, to which the concept of

the “necessary connection” of C and E could correspond. Causality

amounts to no more than the definition “invariable association in a

potentially infinite number of possible cases”. Generally, to avoid

talking literal nonsense one must specify what feature of actual or

possible experience the talk describes.

The “self” is also not meaningfully identifiable with any nonexperiential

soul or mental substance, but is, like a material object

logically constructed out of sense-contents. The way in which we think

of the minds of others presents problems, however, because we have in

principle no access to their sense-contents, but only to their behaviour.

This produces an incoherent asymmetry whereby the ascription of

mental states to myself is phrased in “mental” sense-contents, whereas

its ascription to others is phrased in “physical” or “behavioural” sensecontents.

Logical positivism has a dilemma. The problem with adopting

“strong” verifiability is that although it excludes statements that Ayer

wishes to regard as literally meaningless, it also excludes statements he

Ayer 269

would wish to regard as meaningful. Ayer came to think later that the

complete reduction of propositions about material objects to sensecontents

was not possible, because no finite set of propositions

referring to sensory experience was ever logically equivalent to a

statement referring to a physical object. No finite set of observationstatements

can give the necessary and sufficient conditions which

would constitute the truth that X is a physical object, since further,

logically possible evidence—further experiences—may show we must

have been mistaken. So no finite set of propositions referring to senseexperiences

can conclusively verify the proposition that X is a material

object. Hence the problem with “strong” verifiability is that it implies

that most, perhaps all, of the statements of natural science are

meaningless. The problem with “weak” verifiability is that although

plausibly it permits the statements of science and common sense as

literally meaningful, factual, propositions, it fails to exclude those

statements which Ayer wishes to regard as metaphysical and

meaningless.

Take, for example, the statement “God exists”: the same

considerations apply to “God does not exist”. Ayer wants to say that

such an assertion is literally meaningless rather than false. But it is not

excluded by the “weak” verification principle, for someone might

admit that a particular experience was evidence for or against the

existence of God—thereby qualifying “God exists” as a literally

meaningful proposition—without thereby having to admit that what is

meant by “God” and “His existing” is wholly exhausted by those

evidential experiential propositions. Only by adopting the “strong”

verification principle is there hope of identifying “God exists” as

literally meaningless and so eliminating it. However, no sophisticated

religious believer is likely to admit that what he means by God existing

is nothing more than some actual or possible sense-experiences—for

example, the observed intricateness and orderliness of nature—even if

he might admit it as evidence of God’s existence.

Ayer’s analysis of apparent ethical and aesthetic statements—

“statements of value”—concludes they are not genuine propositions at

all; they are without literal meaning. They are not factual synthetic

statements, but rather expressions of feelings of approval or

disapproval, which may affect others so they feel the same way. Value

statements are not about anything—they do not even describe the fact

that there is a subjective psychological state which constitutes a

feeling—rather, they are an expression of feeling, akin to a cry of pain

or grunt of satisfaction. Expressions of value are therefore neither

rational nor irrational: they are just a piece of non-rational behaviour.

Since value statements are incapable of truth or falsity, then no two

value statements can conflict. If we argue with someone over value, it

must be over what are the facts concerning the situation which

prompted our feeling.

270 Logical positivism and falsificationism

A further problem that arises with the “verification principle” which

lies at the heart of logical positivism is the logical status of the

principle itself. For the statement “Every genuine proposition must be

either analytic or empirically verifiable” appears itself to be neither

analytic nor empirically verifiable, in which case it is self-defeating

and the “verification principle” is literally meaningless and incapable

of truth or falsity. Logical positivism is not the first or the last

philosophy to saw off the branch on which it is sitting. One response to

this is to say that the principle is not a statement, but a prescriptive

rule which we ought to adopt. But the problem with that is there is no

way of showing why the rule should be adopted.

Popper

Karl Raimund Popper was born in Vienna in 1902. Although his

parents were Jewish, they were baptized into the Protestant Lutheran

Church before their children were born. The circumstances in which

he was brought up were bookish and intellectual. His father was

doctor of law of the University of Vienna and, as well as practising as

a lawyer, he was also a scholar. With this background Popper began

reading early about philosophical, scientific and political matters. In

1918 he enrolled at the University of Vienna and sampled a wide range

of lecture courses, but concentrated his attention on mathematics and

physics. After university he taught mathematics and physics in

secondary schools. During this time he took a keen interest in leftwing

politics, although his later work was greatly concerned with the

totalitarian dangers of socialist and Marxist mass collectivization and

of the belief in inevitable laws of historical development. His

resistance to doctrines claiming access to final truths and dogmatism

led him to favour individualism and piecemeal evolutionary social

change rather than grand revolutionary change, also tentative

solutions to social problems against a background of the greatest

possible freedom for the expression of opinion and criticism which is

characteristic of an open society. The chief culprits attacked by Popper

are Plato, Hegel and Marx.

Popper had contacts with the logical positivism of the Vienna Circle,

but he was never a logical positivist, and instead became one of its

critics, despite a common interest in the methods of science. The root

of Popper’s criticism was that questions of meaning were of relatively

little importance; what concerned him was the status of theories and

their testing. The logical positivists held that, apart from the

propositions of logic and mathematics, all literally meaningful

statements were empirical and scientific. Popper never held that all

non-logical statements that were not scientific were meaningless.

Popper’s “criterion of demarcation” was, unlike the logical positivists’

Popper 271

criterion, concerned with the distinction not between the meaningful

and the meaningless but between science and non-science. Nonscience

includes pseudo-science, which consists in intellectual

activities that claim to be scientific, but are not.

Before the Second World War, Popper left Austria, and from 1937 to

1945 he taught philosophy at the University of New Zealand. He came

to England in 1946. He remained on the outside of philosophical

activities as practised in both Oxford and Cambridge, and received

greatest intellectual sustenance from those who were not primarily

philosophers such as the art historian E.H.Gombrich and the

economist and political theorist F.A.Hayek. In 1949 Popper was made

Professor of Logic and Scientific Method at the London School of

Economics; and this position he held for the rest of his university

career. He was knighted in 1965. Popper’s work has been enormously

influential in the philosophy of science, and on the methodology of the

social sciences.

It is possible to identify three important connected strands of

thought in Popper’s philosophy: (a) the solution of the problem of

induction, (b) the problem of demarcating science from non-science, (c)

the importance of maximizing criticism and maintaining a “critical

attitude” as essential for rationality and vital for the growth of

knowledge.

The essential nature of philosophy involves the critical questioning

of fundamental assumptions that we might otherwise take for granted;

this is obviously connected with point (c). Points (a) and (b) are also

connected with this because it has been thought that what

distinguishes science from non-science is the inductive method: the

extent to which the truth of its propositions is derived from and

justified by their origin in the facts of experience. The ideal picture that

this inductive model of science evokes is its beginning by collecting

pure or presuppositionless observations which give the facts, in a

passive, unprejudiced, neutral manner; then from the repetition of

these observations certain patterns begin to emerge which lead to the

framing of universal hypotheses connecting particular observed

phenomena; these hypotheses are then, by further experimental tests,

proved true, or at least confirmed as highly probable. The aim is to

pick out, from the many features repeatedly observed, the necessary

and sufficient conditions for the event to be explained; that is, the aim

is to identify the cause of the event by identifying that feature of the

situation that is always present when the event to be explained occurs

and is never present when the event to be explained does not occur.

Popper argues, with others, that there are at least two major

problems that such a view of science encounters,

(i) The first problem is that there are no presuppositionless, neutral,

raw observations free of theoretical content. All observation

272 Logical positivism and falsificationism

involves some identifying, and therefore theory-loaded, idea of

the nature of the thing observed that already determines and

presupposes the kind of thing observed, which therefore

necessarily pre-empts any conclusion derived from observation.

To observe at all necessarily involves theoretical presuppositions

about what we are observing. We always when observing observe

something as a so-and-so which carries with it theoretical

implications which often take us beyond the bare content of the

observation. For example, the assertion “Here is a glass of water”

carries with it theoretical assumptions about the behaviour of

entities denoted by “glass” and “water”, assumptions with

implications beyond the evidence of present observations;

indeed, Popper says that such a statement is unverifiable, because

the universal law-like behaviour implicit in denoting terms such

as “glass” and “water” is not reducible to any finite class of

experiences. Another point is that when we identify two events as

a repetition of the same event, we are necessarily picking out

some respect in which they are similar, and ignoring other

respects in which they differ; they must differ or they would not

be two distinct events. Observations, to be possible at all, always

involve the selection, implicitly or explicitly, of certain of the

features of our environment and the rejection of others; the

possible range of things we could make note of is infinite, so we

are forced to be selective. What we choose to observe is guided by

theoretical interests.

(ii) The second problem is that of inductive inference; Popper

characterizes this as “Hume’s problem”. In valid deductive

reasoning it is not possible for the premises of the argument to be

true and the conclusion false; necessarily if the premises of a

valid deductive argument are true, then the conclusion is true. To

assert the premises and deny the conclusion of a valid deduction

is to contradict oneself. A deductive argument involves the claim

that the premises present conclusive grounds for its conclusion.

Thus if it is the case that “All men are mortal” and “Socrates is a

man”, then “Socrates is mortal”. Inductive arguments are not

conclusive in this way: the premises can be true, yet the

conclusion false.

The theories of science are characteristically universal

propositions of the form “All As are Bs” which go beyond the

evidence of experience; the proposition does not follow from any

finite number of observations of As and Bs—which give

propositions of the form “Some As are Bs”—for there is no logical

contradiction involved in the assertion that the next observed A

will not be a B. From this it follows that no universal scientific

proposition can be proved to be true. Scientific laws always

transcend experience. The inference from experience to universal

Popper 273

laws, or more generally to unobserved instances, is neither a

logically valid deductive argument nor an inference that could be

justified by experience, for the argument from “inductive

inferences have worked in the past” to therefore “inductive

inferences will work in the future” is itself an inductive inference,

so any such attempted justification would be circular. An

inductive inference could be made valid on the assumption that

regularities or uniformities observed in the cases we have

observed hold in cases we have not observed. But this assumption

is not a logical a priori truth such that its denial implies a

contradiction or such that it can be justified by experience. We

might say that uniformities have been found to hold in all cases

we have observed, therefore uniformities will hold in cases we

have not observed; but that evidence from cases we have

observed can be evidence for cases we have not observed is

exactly what the uniformity principle justifies, so such evidence

cannot be used to justify the uniformity principle itself.

It will not help to fall back on probability, for we can still ask

why we think the observation of certain cases should even make

more probable events we have not observed. We can say further

that no finite number of observations can make a universal

statement of the form “All As are Bs” more probable by the

frequency theory of probability; the class of examined cases is

always finite, and the class of unexamined cases is potentially

infinite, so that the probability of the universal statement “All As

are Bs” will always approach zero. Even if we restricted the range

of our general statement, we could still not be sure that the next,

ninety-ninth out of a hundred, A will be a B, on the basis of

observing past As and Bs, since “A and not-B” is never a logical

contradiction.

Popper rejects induction both as a fruitful method of formulating

scientific theories, and as a logic for justifying theories. He claims to

have solved the problem of induction, but he does not so much solve it

as sidestep the problem; he does not give or seek a justification for

induction, rather he substitutes a different scientific methodology that

is independent of induction, but does the same job as induction in

allowing us rationally to prefer one theory to another on empirical

grounds. Popper maintains the empiricist principle that it is only by

observation and experiment that we may rationally decide to accept or

reject scientific theories. Such decisions cannot be justified a priori. This

leads on to the heart of Popper’s philosophy, and the idea that what

distinguishes science from non-science is not induction as a method or

a justificatory logic, but that science consists of theories which are both

logically self-consistent and such that they can in principle be falsified or

refuted. Popper uses the terms “hypotheses”, “conjecture”, “theory”

274 Logical positivism and falsificationism

and “scientific law” interchangeably. The logical basis for this is quite

simple, and derives from the deductive principle of modus tollens:

Roughly this says that if asserting p entails asserting q, and q is false,

then p is also false. We can substitute in this formula, H, standing for

some universal scientific hypothesis, for p, and e, standing for an

observation-statement, for q. The observation-statement e is deduced

from H. We then have the following.

The essential point to notice is that this indicates a logical asymmetry

between verification and falsification: while it is the case that no finite

number of observations can ever prove the truth of a universal

scientific theory, logically only one case is required to contradict a

theory’s universal assertion in order for it to be falsified or refuted.

What is distinctive about scientific theories is not that they can be

proved true, or even made more probable, but that they are testable,

that is, they can be falsified. So from the universal proposition “All As

are Bs” (H), we can deduce the proposition that “It is not the case that

some (even one) A is not a B” (e); if we observe “Some (at least one) A is

not a B” (not-e), then it follows purely as a matter of deductive logic

that “All As are Bs” is false (not-H). The assertion “All swans are white”

is falsified by the observation of a single non-white swan which entails

that “Not all swans are white”. Thus a theory is falsifiable if and only if

there is some observation-statement deducible from it, which, if false,

would falsify the theory. A genuine scientific theory must exclude some

logically possible state of affairs by specifying more or less exactly what

the state of affairs will be: it must not be compatible with all logically

possible evidence. More exactly what is deducible from a scientific

theory is at least one “basic statement” which is a potential falsifier;

such a statement will be a singular observation-statement that refers to

some publicly observable event. This excludes pure existential

statements of the form “Some A is a B” from being scientific because

they are untestable; no possible evidence can ever refute them as there

is, so to speak, always somewhere we have not looked.

Popper was impressed by the contrast between the theories of

Marxism and Freudian psychoanalysis on the one hand, and Einstein’s

theories on the other. According to Popper, Marxists and Freudians saw

everywhere confirmation for their theories, whereas Einstein made an

effort to formulate a very specific observable prediction which followed

Popper 275

from his theory concerning the bending of light, which, if it failed to be

upheld by observation, would have refuted the theory. What is at issue

here is not the psychological fact, if it is one, of the reluctance of Marxist

and Freudian defenders to admit evidence refuting their theories, but

rather the nature or logical structure of Marxist and Freudian theories

themselves which rendered them immune from falsification. Popper’s

suspicion was that Marxist and psychoanalytic theories were only

“confirmed”, and seemed to explain everything, because they were,

through reasons of vagueness or devices designed to explain away

counter-evidence, irrefutable. Such theories are anathema to the proper

critical scientific attitude. That is not to say that Marxist and Freudian

theories were meaningless, or even that what they said was untrue,

rather the theories were not scientific in that they were highly untestable,

that is, difficult, if not impossible, to falsify. The theories were constantly

hedged around with caveats or qualifications, so that apparent counterevidence

was no longer a deducible consequence of the theories. For

Popper this indicates that the holders of these theories were not adopting

the proper critical scientific attitude. But far from pre-scientific myths

being meaningless, Popper says they can often be modified to form the

basis of later scientific theories and so become testable by experience.

A further point concerns a comparison of Newton’s and Einstein’s

theories. Popper argues that despite the fact that Newton’s theory can

be massively confirmed by observation, this is not enough to establish

its truth. He holds the view that discrepancies emerged in Newton’s

theory, between its predictions and observations, which led to the

development of Einstein’s competing theory despite the enormous

confirmation of Newton’s theory.

Having explained the logic of Popper’s philosophy of science, it is

necessary to distinguish this from the methodology or practice of

falsificationism. While the logic of falsification is quite simple, the

methodology is a good deal more complex. This arises because,

although it is clear what would, logically speaking, constitute the

refutation of a scientific theory, determining whether a theory is in fact

refuted is quite a different matter. Not only is it the case that there are

various reasons why it is difficult to determine if a refutation has taken

place, but Popper also acknowledges that there are various ways in

which an apparent refutation can always be avoided. These

considerations require that we adopt certain methodological rules so as

to maximize the possibility of scientific progress, although there is no

method that can guarantee it.

There are various problems that arise in attempting the actual

falsification of a theory by critical discussion, observation and experiment,

(i) It is always possible to doubt that the observation we have

made is correct—we may have made an observational error.

This introduces the problem of the empirical base: if we cannot

276 Logical positivism and falsificationism

be certain of the truth of the observation-statements we use to

test our theories, we cannot be certain our theories are refuted

by them. Popper admits that there are no indubitable

observation-statements; all observation-statements themselves

have some theoretical content and are open to further testing.

But this does not lead to a vicious infinite regress, because

although all empirical statements are potentially testable, they

can be provisionally or conventionally held as true, and so

used to test or falsify theories for which they are potential

falsifiers. If they are doubted, further tests can always be

carried out. There are no ultimate empirical foundations,

(ii) This problem concerns the fact that scientific theories are

always tested in groups. In testing any theory it is necessary

that we describe the initial conditions by a set of auxiliary

hypotheses; that is, certain other theories are involved which

act as assumptions concerning relevant circumstances of the

test; these also give the falsifying significance to the

observation deduced from a theory. For example, in making an

observation we might assume that light travels in a straight

line. Thus the falsifying modus tollens formula becomes more

complex.

Strictly speaking, all we can say in this complex situation is

that some element in the totality (H+h) is refuted—is shown to

be false—and that need not be the theory H under test, but

could instead be one or more of the auxiliary hypotheses h.

What can be said here is that the auxiliary hypotheses are

themselves open to testing.

(iii) Closely connected with point (ii), it is always possible to adopt

ad hoc hypotheses so as to evade refutation. By ad hoc

hypotheses is meant hypotheses adopted for no other purpose

than to avoid refutation. For example the theory “All bread

nourishes” can be immunized against refutation by the

example of some poisonous bread in France by tacking on to

the proposition “All bread nourishes” the expression “except

in France”. Another ad hoc method of evading refutation is

simply to define away apparent counter-evidence; thus if “All

As are Bs” is presented with the evidence of an A that is not a

B, it can be said that if we seemed to observe an A that was not

a B, then it could not have been an A that we observed at all;

this makes being a B part of the identifying definition of an A.

So we might say a non-white swan is not a swan at all.

Popper 277

The adoption of ad hoc hypotheses and definitional

manoeuvres Popper regards as intellectually dishonest. We

must therefore adopt some methodological rules so as to avoid

adopting ad hoc hypotheses. Partly this is achieved by the

methodological principle that if we modify a theory with the

addition of some new hypotheses so as to avoid refutation,

there must be some consequences that can be deduced from

the original theory and the new additional hypotheses that

were not deducible from the original unmodified theory. In

other words, the additional or modified hypotheses must form

a new hypothesis which is testable in some way the original

hypothesis was not: they must be independently testable. Thus

we reject as ad hoc “All bread nourishes, except in France”, since

it has no new testable consequences which are not also a test of

“All bread nourishes”; the reverse is not the case, since there

are testable consequences of “All bread nourishes” which are

not also testable consequences of “All bread nourishes, except

in France”.

It is clear that some hypotheses are more testable or falsifiable than

others. The theory that “All planets move in loops” (H1

) is less

falsifiable than “All planets move in ellipses” (H2

), because H1

is less

specific about what evidence would refute it. To put it another way, H1

excludes less than H2

: its truth is compatible with a far greater range of

possible observations. H2

not only says that the planets move in closed

loops, but also specifies the exact kind of loop that is involved. Thus

we can say that all the observations that would falsify H1

would falsify

H2

but some observations that would falsify H2

would not falsify H1

; if

the planets moved in anything but ellipses, H2

would be false, while as

long as they still moved in some kind of loop H1

would be true. Popper

expresses this point by saying the greater the information content of a

theory, the more falsifiable it is: it tells us more about the way the

world is by excluding as being the case more logically possible states of

affairs. The information content increases with the set of statements

which are incompatible with the theory.

Popper also notes that the falsifiability and the information content

of a theory are in inverse proportion to its probability. The information

content of a tautology—for example, “Either it is raining or it is not

raining”—is zero, and its probability is at the maximum of 1. The

probability of H2

(“All planets move in ellipses”) being true is far less

than the probability of H1

(“All planets move in loops”) being true

because the class of potential falsifiers of H1

is a proper subclass of the

potential falsifiers of H2

. For example, “The planets move in a straight

line” would falsify both H1

and H2

, but “The planets move in a circle”

would falsify H2

but not H1

because a circle is a kind of loop.

Popper’s overall position is then that we make progress in our

278 Logical positivism and falsificationism

knowledge, and approach the truth, by a process of trial and error.

Popper gives the following evolutionary view of the growth of

scientific knowledge:

P

1

® TT1

® EE1

® P

2

Here P1

designates a problem, for which we propose the tentative

theory TT1

; we then try to eliminate false theories by testing them

severely and subjecting our theory to critical discussion, EE1

; then P2

is

the problem-situation as we emerge from our attempted solution to

our problem, and so on. Science makes progress by conjecture and

refutation; we learn from our mistakes. We start with problems, not

with neutral observation: that is, we start with the failure to explain

some phenomenon. No mere observation constitutes a problem; we

have a problem only in the light of some existing theory which fails to

explain an observation. We try to solve the problem not by proposing

the most probable theory—for more probable theories have less

information content—but by proposing bold conjectures or guesses

which, because they are highly specific and precise in what they say

about the world, are highly falsifiable; we can then test these theories

in severe and crucial tests. The tests are severe because what the theory

entails is incompatible with a very wide range of possible

observations. Intuitively we can see that the severity of a test will

increase with its improbability. A new theory will be bold and

improbable (unlikely) and its tests severe because it involves rejecting

part of the background knowledge of scientific theories of its historical

time. For example, Einstein’s theory was bold relative to the theoretical

background assumptions of its time because it contradicted the

background assumption of its time that light travels in straight lines.

It is significant that in Popper’s falsificationism the source of a

scientific theory is totally irrelevant to whether it is scientific or not. A

theory is scientific if and only if it is falsifiable; it is quite unimportant

whether the theory arises from laboratory observation or an

inspirational blow on the head. One method might as a matter of fact

be more fruitful as a means of producing good theories than another;

but that is irrelevant to the question of whether a statement is scientific

or not, and, if it is scientific, how good a scientific theory it is. Science

has no mechanical method by which it can make progress; Popper’s

philosophy gives free rein to imaginative bold speculation. Good

science requires just as much imagination as any of the arts. Popper

says we do not in fact come to the world as passive or neutral

observers, but are born with certain natural expectations or

dispositions that operate in the same way as consciously constructed

theories. Indeed all animals are in their behaviour acting out innate

solutions to problems. But while these innate “theories” might be

psychologically a priori, that does not mean they are a priori valid. The

main difference between man and other animals is the extent to which

Popper 279

man can allow his theories to die rather than dying himself; man can

adopt new theories rather than hanging on to his theories and dying

with them. One sees the point of this in considering the way a wasp

unremittingly batters at a glass window and so “fails to solve” the

“problem” of escaping.

Normally we will not be in the situation of testing one theory in

isolation, but will have to choose between a number of competing

theories. Even if we find an observation that falsifies a theory we will

not reject it unless we have some better theory with which to replace it.

Indeed, Popper’s methodological rules demand that we do not hastily

reject a theory after a single falsifying instance, but only after frequent

and rigorous falsification has taken place, and we have a better theory

with which to replace it. The choice between competing theories

should be made in the following way: theory T

2

should be preferred to

T

1

if T

2

solves all the problems that T

1

solves and it solves the problems

T

1

failed to solve (that is, where T

1

was refuted), and it offers solutions

to some additional problems about which T1

says nothing, thus

allowing the further possibility for refutation. To put it another way, we

should choose the theory that explains all the previous theory explains,

explains what the previous theory failed to explain, and offers an

explanation for further phenomena not explained by the previous

theory. The satisfaction of these conditions effectively rules out our

new theory being merely the old theory plus some ad hoc hypotheses

which serve only to avoid the apparent refutations or failures.

Popper’s philosophy of science can be summarized in the following

way. Knowledge progresses by proposing bold explanatory theories,

that is, explanations with a high information content that are highly

falsifiable, by subjecting those theories to severe and crucial tests and

by the replacement of falsified theories by better theories. We can be

said to replace a theory by a rationally preferable, better theory, even if

the old theory has not been conclusively falsified, when the new theory,

provided it has not been falsified, is able to explain all that the old

theory explained, and things the old theory failed to explain, and

offers as well explanations for things for which the old theory offered

no explanation. That is, the better theory T

2

will contain T

1

as an

approximation. If any falsification of T

1

would be a falsification of T

2

,

but not vice versa, then T

2

is rationally preferable to T

1

provided T

2

has

not been falsified. This means we choose the theory which is more

falsifiable—has more information content—provided that theory has

not been falsified. We can make our assessment of theories only from

the position of the current historical state of critical discussion.

If a theory survives continuous attempts to falsify it by severe tests,

it can be said to be highly corroborated. That is not to say its truth has

been conclusively established, or even made more probable. The

corroboration of a theory at a certain time is essentially a report on its

degree of testability, the severity of the tests to which it has been

280 Logical positivism and falsificationism

subjected, and the way it has stood up to those tests. The corroboration

of a theory will increase with its falsifiability, provided it is not

falsified, because the more falsifiable it is the more severe the tests it

can potentially survive. It can then be subjected to further severe tests.

Popper is quick to deny that corroboration reintroduces the notion of

induction, for he says that the corroboration accorded to a theory does

not say anything about its reliability in the future or anything about its

future performance. The less the probability of a theory, the higher its

degree of potential corroboration can be. A less probable theory can

pass more severe tests and so can be more highly corroborated. A

theory that has been well corroborated can be provisionally accepted. If

there is more than one theory covering the same ground, it is rational

to choose the best corroborated theory because that has been most

severely tested. This again gives an account of rational preference

between theories: T

2

is preferable to T

1

if T

2

survives all the tests T

1 survives, survives the tests T

1

fails, and goes on to explain further facts

which are testable consequences of T

2

, and if T

2

has not yet been

refuted.

It is clear from Popper’s position that we can never establish that a

theory is true. He says that we can never “know” in the sense of

conclusively establishing a theory to be true so that there is no

possibility of our being mistaken. In this sense Popper is a fallibilist:

we can never be certain that we have found the truth. All our theories

are conjectures or guesses which are open to testing; we can then

perhaps say that some conjectures are better than others because they

have stood up to tests better.

Since we are interested in the truth we shall be interested in

eliminating a theory which we discover to be false, for that way we

might hit upon a theory that is true. Popper is absolutely clear in

distinguishing whether a theory is objectively true or false as a matter

of correspondence, or failure of correspondence, with facts (p is true if

and only if it corresponds to the facts), from our knowing if p

corresponds to the facts. Popper takes from the logician Alfred Tarski

(1902–83) the definition of truth: “‘p’ is true if and only if p”. Every

unambiguous statement is either true or false, and there is no third

possibility; but determining when a proposition corresponds to the

facts is quite a different matter, and Popper thinks we are never in the

position to say that we have established or justified the truth of a

theory. However, the correspondence definition of truth can act as a

regulative principle: it is something we can aim at and get nearer to.

Indeed, as the corroboration of a theory increases, it is reasonable to

conjecture that we are getting nearer the truth. The extent to which a

theory approaches the truth Popper refers to as its verisimilitude.

Popper derives the notion of verisimilitude from the information

content of a theory: the content of a theory T is all those propositions

entailed by it. The content of T can then be divided into its truthPopper

281

content (the class of all true statements entailed by T) and its falsitycontent

(the class of all false statements entailed by T). The

verisimilitude of T is its truth content—minus its falsity—content.

Assuming that theories T

1

and T

2

are comparable, then T

2

has greater

verisimilitude than T

1

if its truth-content is greater than T

1

, but its

falsity-content is less than T

1

, or the falsity-content of T

2

is less than T

1 but the truth-content of T

2

is greater than T

1

. If more true statements,

but not more false statements, follow from T

2

than T

1

, then T

2

is nearer

the truth.

If T

2

entails all the true statements entailed by T

1

, and T

2

entails

some true statements not entailed by T

1

, and T

2

does not entail more

false statements than T

1

, then it is reasonable to say that T

2

is nearer the

truth than T

1

:T

2

has greater verisimilitude even if it is false. Thus we

can rationally prefer T

2

to T

1

if we are in pursuit of the truth even if T

2 is false, provided that the falsity-content of T

2

is not too great.

The verisimilitude and the degree of corroboration of a theory are

connected. If we compare the corroboration of two theories and

determine that all the tests passed by T

1

are also passed by T

2

, and that

T

2

passes some tests that T

1

does not pass, and that T

2

does not fail

more tests than T

1

failed, then it is rational to prefer T

2

to T

1

because T

2 can be conjectured to have greater verisimilitude: it is nearer the truth.

T

2

will be more testable than T

1

: it will have a greater information

content; it will say more about the way the world is. Although we have

not established the truth of T

2

—indeed, as we are fallible, it is likely to

be false—we can express a rational preference for T

2

as being better

corroborated than T

1

and nearer to the truth than T

1

. T

2

is more testable

and survives more tests than T

1

.

From Popper’s acceptance of the correspondence theory of truth it

can be seen that he is a metaphysical realist. He thinks that our

theories, if true, refer to a reality which is independent of mind and

our theories. However, he agrees that such metaphysical realism does

not take us very far except as a regulative idea, for we still have to

determine when our theories correspond to things as they really are.

We cannot “look around” our theories to reality, but can only take to be

reality what our best theories in the light of current critical discussion

and testing say reality is. Popper thinks it unlikely that we will ever

discover “the truth” about the world. Popper is opposed in science to

instrumentalism, which asserts that scientific theories do not refer to

real entities which explain the course of our observations, but are

rather useful devices which posit whatever is required—without

maintaining its reality—for predicting accurately the course of our

experience. On this view scientific laws are rules rather than truths.

Popper also opposes essentialism, which maintains that we can

discover an ultimate reality in terms of which everything else is

explained. This attitude he sees as stultifying to the pursuit of ever

better explanations. Popper takes a middle course in which science is a

282 Logical positivism and falsificationism

genuine attempt to explain some real state of affairs which is known or

assumed to be true by some other real state of affairs that is unknown

and requiring discovery, the truth of which can be tested

independently of the phenomena to be explained; but there is no end

to the depth to which we can progress in pursuit of explanations.

When Popper talks about “knowledge” he is not referring to finally

established, or justified, truths. He also emphasizes that when he talks

about “knowledge” he is talking about knowledge in the objective

sense. He intends by this to make a distinction between any person’s

subjective knowledge and objective knowledge as it is formulated in

language and existent in books and journals in libraries and research

institutions open to public inspection and testing. Scientific

knowledge is objective in this sense. Objective logical relations exist

between statements which are formulated in language, regardless of

whether anyone is actually aware of them or not. What individual

scientists believe is relatively unimportant compared to the objective

growth of knowledge. The error of what Popper terms “belief

philosophy” is that it tries to see knowledge as an especially sure kind

of belief.

Popper, in fact, makes a distinction between three interdependent

worlds: World 1 is the physical world; World 2 is the subjective mental

world; World 3 is the objective world of theories, mathematics,

literature, art, and the like, within which there exist objective logical

relations—objective, that is, in being independent of the awareness of

individual minds. The objects of World 3 are developed by World 2

minds, often in response to problems perceived in World 1; but once

formulated, they have an objective status transcending the intentions

of the individual. Yet it is knowledge in the subjective sense—what the

individual person can know—on which traditionally philosophy has

concentrated, the notion being that it is only from what an individual

mind can really know that any further knowledge claims can be

justified. Yet most human knowledge in the objective sense is not

known by anyone in the subjective sense. Human knowledge,

especially scientific knowledge, almost entirely consists of knowledge

without a knowing subject. Popper’s World 3 has some similarities to

Plato’s realm of objective Forms; however, a vital difference is that

Popper’s World 3 is by no means fixed, but constantly changes and

develops as knowledge grows and progresses through the critical

examination of the knowledge we already have.

Popper 283

continued to ...

https://sites.google.com/site/philosophygreekancient/philosophy-and-philosophers---an-introduction-to-western-philosophy---chapter-10-1