Philosophy and Philosophers - an Introduction to Western Philosophy - Chapter 7

back to ...

https://sites.google.com/site/philosophygreekancient/philosophy-and-philosophers---an-introduction-to-western-philosophy---chapter-4-1

or ...

CHAPTER SEVEN

Later German philosophy: Hegel, Nietzsche

The philosophers Hegel (1770–1831) and Nietzsche (1844–1900) in

many ways could hardly be more different; they differ in style, method

and conclusions. Hegel is methodical and technical where Nietzsche is

deliberately unsystematic and literary; this renders them both obscure

and difficult to understand, but in different ways. Yet there is a

connecting intellectual element, although what each makes of this

common element produces quite different philosophies.

The question arises as to what extent we can have a metaphysics of

reality: to what extent we can be said to have knowledge of reality:

how in a general way the world necessarily is in itself, as distinct from

how it merely appears. A problem arises from the apparent separation

of our view of how the world is and the world itself; once this

separation takes place the problem is to determine to what extent our

view of the world given in the concepts can be known to correspond to

the world itself: reality. One way of looking at this problem of

knowledge of reality is to try to determine which of our basic concepts

with which we think about the world reflect actual objective and

necessary features of the world, and which of our concepts reflect the

contribution of what is merely subjective or contingent. In describing

reality we aim to identify features that are true from any point of view,

which is, so to speak, the point of view of things themselves.

A common connection between Hegel and Nietzsche is the German

intellectual tradition derived from Kant. Kant’s philosophy sets up the

way in which the question of our knowledge of reality is asked. Kant

suggests that there is no way that the basic concepts through which we

have necessarily to think about the world can be shown to be valid for

the world as a reality beyond experience and independent of all

subjective conceptions. Such independence would entail a world to

176

which we could never possibly know if our conceptions applied. What

Kant says is that our basic concepts do nevertheless have a kind of

objectivity through being necessarily valid a priori, if not for things-inthemselves

beyond experience, then in all cases for how things can

appear to us and to any rational beings. We cannot justify the assertion

of the objectivity and necessity of our conceptions of the world either

from experience or logically by their denial being contradictory. Their

necessity and objectivity are derived from the universal

intersubjectivity of any rational mind necessarily using these concepts

in all possible thought and knowledge; therefore anything that is

experienced must be formed by these concepts. The function of

philosophy is not then to give metaphysical knowledge of reality as a

whole—thus including things-in-themselves beyond possible

experience, and hence beyond being known as subject to our

conceptions—but must be content to give us knowledge of the a priori

structure of experiences, that is, the world as it appears. Kant also says

that it is within experiences that the appearance/reality distinction

must be made. The natural world as studied by science is the totality of

possible experiences. The function of philosophy is to justify rationally

the necessary application to appearances of the basic concepts which

are presupposed by natural sciences. For example, philosophy alone

cannot determine what causes what, but it can justify the necessity of

the concept of causation that is logically presupposed by science: the

concept of causation, that every event must have some cause, is shown

to be necessarily true in so far as the concept is applied to all possible

appearances but not to things-in-themselves.

Hegel and Nietzsche make something quite different of the

philosophy of Kant. Hegel thinks he can show that our concepts of

reason are necessarily and objectively valid for reality as a whole,

which includes appearances and things-in-themselves but ultimately

eliminates the distinction between them; thus knowledge of reality is

possible; metaphysics is possible. Nietzsche concludes that our

concepts can have no necessary and universal validity because no

concept can; they are interpretations that must be seen as originating

in certain features of the distinctively human condition; there can be

no overall non-perspectival conceptual system, devoid of all and any

points of view, which would give a complete description of reality.

Hegel sees the solution as lying in metaphysical or absolute

idealism. In Kant’s position, where the mind and the world are

separate in some sense, the concepts used by the mind can be known

to be a priori valid only to the extent that the world is regarded as

subject to mind or basic mental categories; that is, they are a priori

valid only for the world regarded as an appearance or phenomenon.

This leaves a problematic residual noumenal world, or thing-in-itself,

which is unknowable, beyond the phenomenon, because it is by

definition that which is independent of all of our conceptual

Hegel, Nietzsche 177

determinations. So long as features of the world are only partly a

product of mind, our concepts are assured as objectively valid only

for that part for which the mind is responsible. Thus with Kant we

cannot know reality as a whole, including reality as it is in itself, but

know it only as it appears: as it comes before the mind. The answer

for Hegel is to show how the mind and the world really form an

identity as one absolute spiritual entity which transcends the dualism

of subject and object; the concepts of thought are thereby necessarily

objectively valid for reality as a whole, not only for appearances,

because to know those concepts is the same as to know the structure

of reality itself; there is no world to which rational concepts could fail

to apply because the world in its entirety is a developing product of

the essence of absolute mind or reason. Our concepts no longer

merely give the form of any possible appearance of things, objective

merely for the world as experienced; rather, they are again absolutely

or unconditionally objective for the world-in-itself because the world

as determined by mental categories is one with the world itself. The

world/concept dualism is collapsed, as is knowledge and the object

of knowledge; thus the absolute objectivity of concepts is regained

with respect to reality in its entirety because there is no residual

thing-in-itself-world of which we have not taken account and for

which our concepts can fail to hold. This is not to say the world is the

product of finite individual minds as in subjective idealism; it is

rather a manifestation of infinite mind or spirit, or mind as such. The

understanding of the world is thus mind understanding the

development of itself.

In Nietzsche we see the triumph of perspectivism: the concepts

which constitute our notion of the world can have no unique objective

validity and represent one partial possible set of concepts which give

an interpretation which is the world to us; they give us, through a set

of classificatory and ordering concepts, a usable picture of the world

whose function and explanation are largely pragmatic. Our concepts,

far from describing the world in an objective and necessary way—

being valid from any point of view or universally—are constructed by

humans for their own peculiarly human purposes, especially the

purpose of survival. That is not to say that because there is no one

necessary way of construing the world any way is as good as any

other; but one view is not better than another in the traditional sense

of corresponding better to reality at all; views are better because they

enhance power and control to live one’s life in certain specific ways

and according to certain values. There can be no one conceptual

framework that gives the complete truth about the world; all views are

partial. Perspectives are a necessary condition of having a world at all.

Our rational conception of the world seems objective and necessary

because we seem not to be able to throw it off; but such conceptual

ordering of the world as we experience it is a kind of simplifying

178 Later German philosophy

fiction or falsification that serves to make the world amenably ordered

and calculable for human beings.

Hegel

Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770–1831) was born in Stuttgart, the

son of a minor civil servant with a Lutheran background. He was

educated at the University of Tübingen, studying philosophy and

theology. There he met the poet Hölderlin and the philosopher

Schelling. The French Revolution, which occurred during his time at

university, made a deep impression on Hegel; he thought it was

momentous in its rigorous application of reason, but it was also a great

failure because reason was applied in an abstract way that took no

account of particular circumstances of the community. After university

he held various private tutorial posts, and began working on his

philosophy. Hegel taught philosophy at the University of Jena from

1801 to 1803. On leaving he began his first great philosophical work,

The phenomenology of spirit. Jena was occupied by the French in 1807

following the defeat of the Prussians by Napoleon, and the university

closed. After working as a newspaper editor, Hegel was from 1808 to

1816 the headmaster of a Gymnasium at Nuremberg. From 1816 to

1818 he was Professor of Philosophy at the University of Heidelberg

where he wrote the Encyclopedia of the philosophical sciences. Hegel had

by this time attained a significant reputation as a philosopher, and was

offered in 1818 the prestigious post of Professor of Philosophy at the

University of Berlin. In 1821 he published the Philosophy of right. The

position in Berlin he held until his death from cholera at the age of

sixty-one.

Seminal influences on Hegel’s work derive from his study of Greek

philosophy, particularly Plato and Aristotle, but also Heraclitus and

Eleatics such as Parmenides. Of philosophers nearer to his time,

Spinoza and Kant greatly affected Hegel’s philosophical outlook.

Among contemporary thinkers important to Hegel we have to look to

Fichte (1762–1814) and Schelling (1775–1854).

The aim of philosophy, according to Hegel, should be to show how a

complete understanding of reality as a totality is possible, and this

entails that all reality has to be conceptually accessible; that there is

nothing real which is not captured by the concepts of reason; there is

also nothing which is a concept of reason which is not real. To reach

this end Hegel claims to prove the necessity of absolute idealism.

Part of the key to the philosophy of Hegel is found in his rejection of

Kant’s limitation of rational philosophical knowledge to the basic a

priori conceptual structure of appearances, which rendered things-inthemselves—things

as not known in their appearances—unknowable.

Thus reality in its entirety is not knowable since things-in-themselves

Hegel 179

are beyond possible appearances and excluded. Kant’s position gives

an oddly bifurcated world: the world as experienced and the world as

not experienced; and within this duality, if we are to talk meaningfully

about “reality” at all, we must talk of some characteristics within

appearances, and not ascribe it to things-in-themselves. Kant’s “critical

philosophy” aims to delineate the limits of philosophical knowledge

and understanding; all knowledge and understanding are

conceptual—bring things under concepts—or are expressed in

concepts; and if the application of our concepts is limited, then so are

knowledge and understanding. Hegel makes a distinction between

understanding and reason; he thinks that proper philosophical reason

can go beyond the limits set to our knowledge by Kant. For Kant the

limits of knowledge of reality are reached when we meet antinomies or

contradictory theses which are irredeemably opposed and between

which we cannot rationally choose; for Hegel philosophical reason can

find a way of transcending the contradiction in a new synthesis.

The question arises as to why Kant feels the need to posit an

unknowable noumenon at all. Overall, the reason must derive from the

realization that the sense of “reality” he is able to give within the realm

of appearances is not fully satisfying. Kant suggests that the raw

sensation of intuitions must have an external cause and the cause is the

thing-in-itself; but the thing-in-itself cannot be the cause of anything,

since the category of causality cannot apply to it. In any case, Kant’s

successors were quick to point out that noumenon is contradictory.

Even if we avoid giving any function to noumenon, it is still said to

exist; and this means the category of existence applies to it in flat

contradiction of the assertion that no categories can apply to it; even if

only one category is applicable to noumenon, it cannot be wholly

unknowable, which contradicts the initial supposition that it is

unknowable.

The collapse through contradiction of the conception of the thing-initself

leads inexorably to absolute idealism, and to the complete

knowability of everything. If noumenon is eliminated as the external

source of the given element in knowledge, sensation, to which the

mind introduces a priori form, then the distinction between form

imposed by mind and given content derived from sensation is

destroyed, and the universe must in its entirety be a product of mind.

This attacks the vital Kantian distinction between form and content,

between the a priori and a posteriori. What can be brought under

concepts is knowable; but noumenon is contradictory if posited as that

which cannot be brought under concepts, since it can at the very least

be known to exist: it is. Therefore everything is necessarily knowable,

since it is contradictory to posit that which cannot be brought under

concepts. To posit an unknowable “something” is contradictory, since

in positing it as something which exists we apply a concept, and to

apply a concept is to know that thing to which the concept is applied.

180 Later German philosophy

Indeed, Hegel suggests that the whole notion of being able to know the

limits to our knowledge is impossible. We should also note that

proving that all is knowable is by no means the same as saying that all

is known and that there are not things of which we are ignorant.

Everything must be knowable because a minimum condition for there

being something unknown in the totality of the universe is that it is,

but in that case it is something known, not unknown. If the thing-initself

is said to be “nothing”, we have applied a concept that makes it

completely knowable. In short, if X is posited as unknowable, it is

knowable, therefore it is knowable.

The result of this is that we must reject all talk which divides

knowledge of reality from reality itself for we can have no conception

of reality apart from knowledge, no place to stand where we could

compare knowledge and reality. We always work from within existing

knowledge to understand reality.

The argument that reality in its totality is knowable logically

inclines one to monism: for the universe to be understandable as a

whole everything must be explicable—which is not the same as

everything being actually explained—and for it to be possible for

everything to be explicable the universe must be posited as one selfexplanatory,

self-contained entity. This is the Absolute or reality as a

whole revealing itself in the fully adequate conceptual description of

the Absolute Idea or Notion where subject and object are one in a selfthinking

thought. The Absolute is the universe or reality as a totality;

in short, everything. Everything in the universe is understood through

something else in the universe; but if the universe—reality as a

whole—is to be understood or explained it must in total form a whole

which is self-explanatory; otherwise a regress of explanation could

not be ended. As Hegel puts it, “The truth is the whole”, for to

understand any part involves understanding the whole. If we try to

understand the truth about a part in isolation we will find that a

contradiction will arise in that we have to refer to some relation

outside it; ultimately we can draw this process to a close only when

we have a view of the whole and there is nothing outside left to refer

to; we thereby transcend and include all relational thinking in

describing reality.

Once the thing-in-itself that is inaccessible to our concepts is

eliminated by being shown to be impossible, then all reality is

accessible to concepts, for to posit that which is inaccessible to

concepts is contradictory. Thus the real is the rational and the rational

the real. What this means is that all that is real is the rational process of

concept generation, and hence is knowable, and the rational process of

concept generation is the real. The world in its totality is the necessary

unfolding of the logic of concepts. There is no longer any question of

our concepts failing to apply to reality in the sense of the totality of the

universe, for just as Kant’s categories were objective for all

Hegel 181

appearances, Hegel’s concepts now apply to reality itself, for the world

as it falls under concepts is all the world can be at any moment in its

unfolding: it is the real.

The function of philosophy is to construct or understand the

Absolute, to prove that the truth about reality as a whole is knowable.

Since it is not possible to posit anything apart from what falls under

mental concepts, to trace the development of concepts is to trace the

development of reality itself. In the Absolute, mind (the subjective)

and object (the objective) are collapsed into an ultimate subject that

rises above the duality because its object is itself; that is, the totality

thinks about what can be its only object, itself. The Absolute is the

actualization of this self-thinking thought: reality as a whole fully

understanding itself as a whole. Some writers have given the Absolute

a theistic interpretation and have seen the description of the Absolute

as a description of God; however, it cannot be a transcendent God, but

God immanent in the world. Absolute knowledge is the point at which

the infinite mind, through our finite mind, has a complete

understanding of reality, and that is when the Absolute has a complete

understanding of itself, including the process that led to that complete

understanding. Absolute knowledge captured in the Absolute Idea

gives a perfect conceptual description of the nature of reality

including, of course, the charting of the logical progression of

increasingly adequate concepts to that Absolute knowledge which is

the realization that the true nature of reality is that of the totality

which knows itself. Absolute knowledge is the realization in the

Absolute Idea that reality is ultimately a self-thinking thought, that

absolute idealism is necessarily true so that reality is ultimately one

infinite self-thinking mind. Reality is like a sphere with a perfect

mirror on its inner surface where every part is perfectly reflected in

another—but in this metaphor we would have to realize that the

sphere could not have an outer surface.

It is important to note that the mind referred to here—which

produces through its concepts reality in its entirety and is thus

identical with that reality, so that to understand reality is just the same

as to understand those concepts of mind—is not finite individual

mind, but one infinite or objective mind, whose essence is reason.

Reality can be nothing but the conceptual construction of infinite mind

(spirit or Geist), so knowledge of reality turns out to be mind’s

knowledge of itself. But the infinite mind understands itself through

finite minds; and the conceptual development manifest in finite minds

in various human activities, especially in philosophy, will reflect the

conceptual development of reality itself. The development of the

world, present reality as a whole, is towards the Absolute and is just

the same as the development to that point at which reality has a fully

adequate understanding of itself in the Absolute Idea under the

category of a single self-thinking thought.

182 Later German philosophy

There is a strong teleological element in Hegel’s account of reality;

the universe moves towards the Absolute as the end or result. Reality

is identical with, and includes, the process of infinite mind’s

conceptual development towards absolute knowledge, which is

knowledge of reality, which is reality as self-knowing. Reality at any

stage or “moment” in the development can be nothing other than the

total system of concepts of reality, which are manifest through the

conceptual development of finite minds. In the end state of this

conceptual development, where the Absolute is a fully self-knowing

thought, the subjective and objective, the concept of reality and reality

itself, indeed all conceptual opposites, differences and relations, are an

identity contained in a unity. A fully comprehensive knowledge of

reality will involve the identity of all opposing concepts, for the

Absolute includes in itself all concepts—all determinations. Otherwise

the understanding will be inadequate, as it will not be complete; for

what is rational is real, and what is rational is what can be brought

under concepts, therefore if some concepts are not included, there

cannot be an understanding of the Absolute, since such an

understanding leaves something out. The Absolute cannot be either

one thing or its opposite, but must be both in an identity. Where all

conceptual opposites become one, or identities, it might be supposed

that the Absolute is an indeterminate, undifferentiated and

unknowable “something” where conceptual characterization is

impossible because opposites have become identities. But Hegel does

not think of the Absolute as the vanishing point at which all

conceptual differentiation is destroyed; rather, it is where all opposing

concepts are unified into one all-encompassing entity which preserves

their real opposition: an identity-in-difference. The opposition of

concepts is not merely apparent, but real, and their real difference is

preserved in their identity. The Absolute, in knowing itself as a totality,

recognizes the various phases that lead to that final state as real

moments in its life. In the progress towards the Absolute nothing is

lost. An analogy might be the way in which the colour white is

produced by combining all colours.

If the rational is the real and the real the rational, this means that

reality just is the process of infinite mind actualizing the end state:

reality as the self-knowledge of the totality. This process of conceptual

development, which is also necessarily the development of reality

itself towards the Absolute, is dialectical. The dialectic development of

reality towards the Absolute takes place under three headings:

(1) Logic

(2) Philosophy of Nature

(3) Philosophy of Mind.

We can trace the development of dialectical Logic working itself out

towards the Absolute—towards the complete truth about the nature of

Hegel 183

reality, the whole, which is the Absolute’s conception of itself—in any

of the above. They must all amount to aspects of the same thing: the

necessary march of reason towards the total truth about the universe,

which is an infinite mind’s understanding of itself.

In (1) Logic describes the inner essence of the Absolute in its pure

form, including of course the necessary movements towards its

actualization. It is the study of the development of the Absolute in the

non-temporal dialectical Logic of conceptual development itself

abstracted from its manifestations in human minds or the natural

world. The manifestation of the process of the Absolute in (2) and (3)

involves the discernment, among the mass of facts about nature and

human world history, of the bare bones of reason’s conceptual

development in nature and through history given in (1). What is

studied under (2) and (3) is the progress manifest in the temporal

world of the Logic of the Absolute. In all cases this follows the same

overall pattern: objectivity as thesis, subjectivity as antithesis, which

form a unity in the Absolute Idea.

It is vital to understand that the terms of Hegel’s Logic are not

propositions but concepts and that, unlike traditional logic, it is

concerned not with mere form but also with content. Traditional logic

is concerned with valid argument-forms; the universal necessity of

these forms derives precisely from their being valid regardless of

content. We can see this in the following syllogism.

This argument is valid whatever we substitute for X, Y, or f; but for

that very reason traditional logic on its own can tell us nothing about

the actual world and is purely hypothetical, valid regardless of actual

truth. It is important to understand that Hegel is concerned with a

Logic of concepts which have content and which tell the truth about

reality. Once the distinction between conceptual development and

reality is ultimately eliminated as an untenable opposition, the

dialectic Logic of conceptual development is the development of

reality itself. The form/content distinction disappears, and thus the

aim of Hegel’s Logic is truth.

The dialectic of concepts is a structure whereby less adequate

conceptions of reality are overcome but retained to form conceptions

which are more adequate. We can envisage this as a series of

expanding concentric circles, each of which is more adequate in its

description of reality. At any level less than the whole, the concepts we

employ to describe reality are found to be contradictory; what this

contradiction amounts to is the idea that isolated description is

contradictory in different ways in different cases, but always because it

184 Later German philosophy

cannot be genuinely isolated. The attempt to describe a thing which is

less than the Absolute or whole in isolation will be contradictory

because it will necessarily involve relations to things outside it. Thus

the concept A will be found to involve not-A. It is not that both are

simultaneously true, thus breaking the law of non-contradiction, not-

(A and not-A); it is that both separately are inadequate in expressing

the truth, and to get nearer the truth they have to be raised up into a

higher synthesis which contains the truth from both. The less adequate

conceptions are not discarded but preserved in the more adequate

conceptions. Ultimately it is found that the whole system of concepts is

interdependent, and the whole system alone removes all

contradictions and gives an adequate description of the truth about

reality. Up to the point of absolute knowledge the impetus to improved

conceptual mastery of reality comes from reason being driven by

contradictions in its attempt to complete a conceptual description of a

part of reality in isolation. The intellect cannot rest content with an

incomplete and, in Hegel’s sense, therefore an internally contradictory

view of reality. The method involved in attaining the complete

conceptual grasp of reality involves an essentially triadic structure:

concept A (“thesis”) is inadequate in capturing reality on its own and

is found logically to involve its opposite B (“antithesis”); we cannot

think the A without the B; A is thus “contradictory” in isolation from

its relation to B; so both are found to be inadequate descriptions of

reality, and thus form, preserving their opposition and identity, C

(“synthesis”). But the C is also then a thesis and will also be found to

be inadequate, and to involve its antithesis D, which will give rise to

their resolution in E; and so on.

A (thesis)

® C (synthesis/thesis)

B (antithesis) ® E…

D (antithesis)

The nature of reality is deduced from the first principle using the

triadic dialectical method. The first principle turns out to be a category

or concept, since concepts have the right kind of logical, rather than

temporal, priority through their level of inclusiveness. The first

concept with logical priority is Being or “isness”. This is the

fundamental category of reality: whatever is real is, it has the most

abstract quality of “isness”; whatever the determinate character of any

real thing in the world, it logically presupposes the category Being.

But, just because it is the absence of all determination, Being is a

vacuity and is found to be identical with Nothing; Being contains

within it its opposite, Nothing. Reason cannot rest with this

contradiction. From the process of Being passing into Nothing because

the two are identical, we see that equally Nothing passes into Being;

Hegel 185

this leads to a concept in which the concepts of Being and Nothing are

unified in an identity of opposites: Becoming. In the category of

Becoming the concepts of Being and Nothing are preserved in their

difference and also in their identity. They are “sublated” or “put aside”

in a higher unity. The poorest, but still true definition or conception, of

the Absolute is Being; this is the starting point of the logical derivation

of all the concepts which give increasingly adequate definitions of the

Absolute which is reality as a totality; the dialectical deduction of

concepts produces increasingly adequate definitions or conceptions

which include the earlier ones, ending in the most adequate definition

of the Absolute, the Absolute is the Absolute Idea: self-thinking mind.

It should be noted that philosophy, in exhibiting the development of

reason through our actual history, as in (3) above, is not disputing, or

indeed discovering, historical facts; what it is doing is giving an

interpretation describing their dialectical Logic. The mass of factual

details is boiled off to leave the outline of the dialectical process.

In (3), which is the Absolute manifest as mind or spirit, we can trace

the Logic of the conceptual development in consciousness towards

attaining the complete truth about reality as necessarily being absolute

idealism. The Absolute’s knowledge of itself is not identical with the

thoughts of any finite mind, but finite minds are carriers of the

increase in conceptual mastery down through history. Thus we are

tracing in the philosophy of spirit the conceptual development of

mankind, which is the development of consciousness to ever higher

levels of understanding, eventually participating in the Absolute’s selfknowledge.

The phenomenology of mind or spirit studies forms of

consciousness as they acquire a better grasp of reality. We can trace the

manifestation of the dialectic of spirit in its objective manifestations

through the history of public institutions, societies and cultures, which

is the development of the idea of freedom.

In the Philosophy of Mind we can follow the dialectical development

in two connected ways: (a) “Subjective Mind”, (b) “Objective

Mind”,

(a) “Subjective Mind”

This is the phenomenology of mind—mind’s appearance to itself—

the way that mind itself has developed with dialectical necessity to

higher levels of consciousness so as to participate in absolute

knowledge. Hegel traces consciousness from its lowest levels to the

highest. This has three main phases.

(i) Consciousness This starts with “sense-certainty”: the awareness

of raw unclassified sensations. But it soon becomes clear that

knowledge, through awareness of bare particulars, is

contradictory because the awareness is ineffable: to articulate it

without using the universal categories is impossible; even

“this”, “here”, “now” take us beyond what is immediately

186 Later German philosophy

given. Universal terms are required. This leads on to the next

stage, “perception”, in which we classify what we perceive

under sensuous universals—“table”, “star”. But soon it is clear

that non-sensuous universals are involved which are not

encountered in experience—“many”, “one”—and these are

posited as existing as separate realities. These form the basis

for scientific laws. The universals are studied as independent

objects.

(ii) Self-consciousness This begins with the stage at which we realize

that the conceptual structure of the world is a construct of

mind; we become conscious of ourselves as active categorizers

and law makers. Consciousness recognizes the object not as a

not-self but simply as itself. This is the beginning of selfconsciousness;

we are turned back on ourselves. But the object

still remains obstinately regarded as external to the self and at

the same time really one with self. This gives rise to the next

phase, “desire”, in which the aim is pure self-consciousness

where the only object truly is itself; so the self tries to destroy

the external object by consuming it. But the very need to

destroy the external object shows that the self is still dependent

for its self-consciousness on the external. This solipsist phase

gives way to one in which the existence of other selves are

recognized in the world: other egos which are, of course,

themselves self-conscious. If we cannot negate the object, it

must negate itself; but only consciousness can negate itself; so

the external object is recognized as an ego. The independence

of the egos rival one another; this struggle is recognized in the

master/slave relationship, in which one seeks to destroy the

other. The independence of the other ego is negated by the

master in regarding the slave as a thing without selfconsciousness

but as mere consciousness. Thus the object for

the slave is not itself, but merely the external objects on which

it labours for the master. But again contradiction arises because

the master finds he is dependent on the slave through the fact

that the extent of independence of his self-consciousness

depends on negating the self-consciousness of the slave, which

proves independence of the slave, but that means the slave

must after all be self-conscious. The master finds he needs the

slave for his recognition as the master. Also the slave becomes

self-conscious in seeing himself in what he creates. Each now

recognizes the other as self-conscious again. The mutual

acceptance by all selves of each other ushers in the notion of

“universal self-consciousness”.

(iii) Reason The equal recognition of all egos means that another

consciousness is for my self-consciousness another selfconsciousness,

and is therefore myself. Ego contemplates ego

Hegel 187

as its object. Thus the object of self- consciousness is in

whatever it contemplates simply itself. Thus we reach pure

self-thinking thought, where the only object of thought is itself,

and the distinction between self and other is made within self,

since there is nothing beyond infinite mind. Thus we have

absolute idealism.

We can see how the triadic dialectic works here: objectivism and

subjectivism are combined in absolute idealism where the distinction is

transcended because the Absolute is the totality. The object for the

totality identical with mind can only be itself.

(i) Consciousness

(the object is

independent of

self).

® (iii) Reason (subject/

object distinction

is collapsed).

(ii) Self-consciousness

(the object is

identical with

subject).

(b) “Objective Mind”

This constitutes the public manifestation of spirit, which is in turn

the development of the dialectic. Hegel supports this belief with

interpretations of actual historical periods. Roughly, this historical

progression is “The Oriental World” (in which only one, the

despot, is free), “The Greek World” (in which only some, nonslaves,

are free), “The Germanic World” (in which, eventually, all

are free). The overall direction of history is towards consciousness

of freedom. Freedom is understood by Hegel not as absence of

coercion and doing what one likes, but as acting from selfdetermination;

and that means acting according to universally

valid rational principles because in acting under the

determinations of universal rational prescriptions one is most free

from individual causal circumstances. Obedience to absolute moral

laws and ethical individualism are synthesized in the “organic

community” in which the individual is free because the rational

moral principles he would, as an individual, obey in order to be

free are also the specific rational laws of the community: they are

in harmony. Moreover, since the community forms the individual,

what he naturally desires or wills is no longer pitted against the

attempt to obey abstract rational moral principles; rather, he

188 Later German philosophy

naturally wills those rational principles which are also society’s

laws.

Hegel’s philosophy of absolute idealism can itself be seen as a result of

a triadic synthesis of Platonism and Kantianism in the search for

knowledge of reality, which means the possession of necessary and

universal truths about the actual world. Empiricism alone cannot

through experience support such truths; such truths can only be

known a priori as the conceptual truths of the intellect.

(I) Platonism is a form of objectivism: one in which the sensible

world is found to be ontologically unsuitable for necessary and

universal truths. So the concepts constituting these truths are said to be

mind-independent and concerning an intelligible, world-transcendent

realm of mind-independent things-in-themselves, but they are not

properly applicable to the sensible world.

(II) Kantianism is a form of subjectivism: one in which the sensible

world cannot rationally justify such necessary and universal truths. So

the concepts constituting these truths are said to be mind-dependent

and concerning a sensible realm of mind-dependent appearances, but

they are not applicable to things-in-themselves.

(III) Hegelian absolute idealism. The concepts which are objective in

Platonism (I), apart from mind and not applicable to the sensible

world, and the concepts which are subjective in Kantianism (II),

dependent on mind and applicable only to the sensible world, are

synthesized in absolute idealism (III): they are found to constitute

reality itself in its totality. The concepts constituting necessary and

universal truths are subjective or mind-dependent and objective or

mind-independent because rational essence of mind, infinite mind, is

the only reality there can be; apart from reality constituted by the

rational concepts of mind there can be no reality. Finite mind

participates in infinite mind in so far as the infinite mind is in the

finite, and that means in so far as finite minds accord with the

dialectical rationality of infinite mind, which is to the extent that finite

mind abides by reason which is what is universal and essential about

mind. Thus objectivism and subjectivism, and the subject/object

dichotomy, are synthesized and transcended in absolute idealism,

where infinite mind and the whole of reality are one self-thinking

entity: the Absolute.

We can conclude with a general remark on Hegel’s philosophy.

Absolute knowledge is reached when the Absolute fully understands

itself in the Absolute Idea: for the totality to understand itself is to

show how the completely adequate understanding of reality is

possible. It is extraordinary to note that Hegel thinks that his

philosophy is the culmination of the Absolute’s self-knowledge, not

just a description of it; Hegel’s own philosophy is the manifestation in

the world of the Absolute’s full conceptual grasp of itself in the

Hegel 189

Absolute Idea in which the object and subject are one: the subject can

have as its object only itself. The development of infinite mind has

reached its culmination and is manifest through Hegel’s finite mind:

the philosophy of absolute idealism.

Nietzsche

Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900) was born in Röcken in Germany the

son of a Lutheran pastor. His father died in 1849; his upbringing was

dominated by his pious mother, also his sister and aunts. His rigorous

early education, which included classics, took place at the famous

boarding school at Pforta, near Naumburg. For most of his life

Nietzsche laboured under the effects of poor health, including weak

eyesight; for days on end he was struck down by crippling migraines.

Nietzsche studied philology at the University of Bonn and then at

Leipzig; while a student he encountered the greatest influences on his

early thinking, the composer Richard Wagner (1813–83) and the

philosopher Arthur Schopenhauer (1788–1860). Nietzsche’s

outstanding academic achievements are indicated by his appointment,

when only twenty-five, as Professor of Classical Philology at the

University of Basel. He resigned from Basel in 1878 because of illhealth.

From 1878 to 1889 he led an immensely lonely life wandering

from place to place in Europe, often in the high Swiss mountains. It

was during this time that most of his major works were written. His

romantic intentions were always hopelessly unfulfilled, and he

remained unmarried. In 1889 Nietzsche rushed into a street in Turin

and embraced a horse that was being flogged; he then suffered a

massive mental collapse that plunged him into a vegetative insanity

for the rest of his life; during the last ten years of his life all spark of

intelligence left Nietzsche’s mind; the decline may have been due to

acquired or inherited syphilis. Until the end of his life he was looked

after mostly by his mother but also by his sister Elisabeth, who

propagated mythology and obscurity around Nietzsche’s work.

It is impossible not to be controversial in giving an account of

Nietzsche’s philosophy; this is partly because of the scattered nature of

his views on any one subject, and partly because of his manner of

writing. In concentrating on that part of Nietzsche’s philosophy

concerned with the nature of philosophy, knowledge and metaphysics,

one must be aware that a great deal of his interest lies in the realm of

values and how one ought to live one’s life; but the two areas are

intimately connected in Nietzsche’s thought. Nietzsche’s grounds for

rejecting the possibility of absolute knowledge in general include

values in particular. Although Nietzsche deliberately does not produce

a systematic exposition of his views, nevertheless all parts of his

philosophy are interconnected. The overriding consideration in the

190 Later German philosophy

account of Nietzsche given here is to take seriously his repeated

pronouncement that he was doing something quite different from

what had gone before in philosophy. With this in mind, one should

avoid attempting to fit him conveniently into any philosophical school.

It is all too easy to construe Nietzsche as presenting albeit novel

answers to the same old philosophical problems. His aim, however, is

to question the very concepts in which traditional philosophical

problems are couched. Traditional philosophy has been concerned to

present to philosophical problems answers which it aims to be

universally and objectively true. But the presupposition that lies

behind this advancement of a philosophical position as universally

valid is that such universal and objective truths are possible—and it is

exactly this that Nietzsche denies is the case. This denial is not the

same as advocating scepticism with regard to knowledge, for

scepticism too assumes that knowledge must involve necessity and

certainty, but thinks it is something we cannot attain.

The key to Nietzsche’s philosophy is his attack on absolutism of any

sort, final universally binding answers to philosophical problems,

which easily leads to dogmatism. There are, in fact, no eternal

transcendental truths waiting to be discovered, independent of all

thinkers whatsoever.

Nietzsche refers to all views or theories as false or as fictions.

Everything is false, and what we regard as true are but convenient

errors required for our lives. This applies to our common-sense or herd

view of the world, which he regards as a convenient fiction, but on

which our survival has come to depend: it is a world of independent

things, of various kinds, that causally interact according to certain

laws, and is observed by a relatively permanent self. This view has

become so deeply entrenched that we no longer recognize it as a view,

among other possible views, at all. In particular the a priori categories

that Kant regards as universally valid, and hence objective, are

regarded by Nietzsche as having no absolute necessity or universal

validity, but as products of human interests and purposes; they are no

more than psychologically a priori. All views of the world are attempts

to schematize and organize experience for the sake of control and

power over our environment. But there is no reason therefore to

suppose that the way we view the world—our conception of reality—

need be universally valid in terms of power and control for everyone.

Nietzsche is opposing ideals which produce an ossified and idealized

“fabricated world” which is then regarded as the only “real world”. In

Twilight of the idols Nietzsche says, “I mistrust all systematizers and

avoid them. The will to a system is a lack of integrity.”

We must come to see our truths, and our claims to knowledge, in all

fields of activity for what they are: interpretations from certain

perspectives. There is also no possibility of a complete view of

anything or everything. Thus we find that he attacks metaphysics,

Nietzsche 191

knowledge, truth, moral values and values in general, in so far as

definitive answers are proposed. Once we see that we have no more

than different perspectives on the world, we are liberated from the

tyranny of supposing that any view has ever to be accepted as a final

universally valid view. It is not just a matter of being modest in our

philosophical claims by saying that we are not sure if we have finally

solved certain philosophical problems; it is a matter of actively

denying that such final solutions are ever attainable.

Nietzsche objects to the pretence of philosophers that they have, or

at least can have, a disinterested concern for the truth and knowledge,

one that is unaffected by, and separable from, any considerations of

conditions that would define in some way a point of view or

perspective: the specific values, personal predilections, and attitudes to

life that characterize what kind of people they are. It has been the habit

of metaphysicians to juxtapose a superior absolute disinterested view

of the world—which usually means positing another “real world”

beyond or behind the apparent one—with the unthought-out vagaries

of the common-sense view of the world whose chief aim has not been

the disinterested pursuit of knowledge and truth. There is no such

disinterested point of view which would fulfil the condition for

describing reality; all views are inherently perspectival and thus not

exhaustive; the view from nowhere is no view at all; it is not even an

unattainable ideal.

Unlike the systems of metaphysics proposed by past philosophers,

which give a view of reality, the indisputable value of the

commonsense view of the world is that it at least has been of

pragmatic use to us: it has promoted the survival of our species.

Indeed, the common-sense view has prevailed and is regarded as

“true” precisely because it aids survival; the views that did not aid

survival have, of course, died out with their proponents or have been

rejected as “errors”. The entrenchment, the seeming necessity of our

commonsense view, is determined not by its logically absolute or

universal necessity or by its accurate reflection of reality, but by its

huge value in promoting a particular kind of life and attitude to life:

specific interests and values. The imposition of false simplifications or

coarsenings by which we give order to our world is a precondition for

survival; they arrange a world in which our existence is made possible.

This applies to our belief in “things”, natural laws and causality, the

self, and even logic. In this sense Nietzsche’s account of why we have

the concepts we have, and which views we hold to be true, is

naturalistic, rather like the position of Hume. Nietzsche says in the

book The will to power that “Rational thought is interpretation

according to a scheme that we cannot throw off.” We become the

prisoners of our “truths” and “knowledge”: we forget they are fictions

serving our survival, and instead of their serving our needs, we serve

the “truths” and “knowledge” which we come to regard as more than

192 Later German philosophy

instruments of survival. The “truths” and “knowledge” were designed

to fit us and our needs; once we lose sight of this the relation is

reversed, and we begin to fit the “truths” and “knowledge”. For

Nietzsche this relation is particularly important in the area of human

values.

That a view promotes certain interests and values is not

objectionable in itself because every view does this in different ways.

What Nietzsche objects to is the dogmatism he sees as inherent in the

various metaphysical systems of the past, which suppose they can rise

above perspectival interests and values and present to us a

disinterested, non-perspectival, complete, view of things truly, as they

really are in themselves. The philosophers’ metaphysical systems,

however, are really doing the same kind of thing as common sense:

they are producing organizing schemata that reflect specific deep

values and interests. This would be fine provided we realized what we

were doing, because we are not obliged to accept the systems unless

we want to accept those specific values as well, values which point to a

way of life and an attitude to life. The notion that metaphysics seeks a

non-perspectival value-free view of reality contains latent dogmatism

because if the view is transcendentally universal and necessary, as it is

usually claimed to be, then it demands of everyone that they accept it

regardless of their specific perspectival view and values. But

Nietzsche’s point is that there are only perspectives.

Nietzsche objects to the claim that the metaphysical systems of

philosophers are superior to common sense in being more true in the

sense of corresponding to the true nature of reality: all views are

equally false or fictions in that sense. Nietzsche does not defend

common sense against the metaphysicians because it gives the truer

view of reality, but on the grounds that it has, at least in the past,

proved beneficial to life. He does not attack common sense because it

is false or a fiction—not presenting to us the truth about reality in the

sense of corresponding accurately to reality—but because it has now

become inimical to life and harmful to that which is strongest and best

in us. Nietzsche wishes to replace the common view of the world, not

on the grounds that his view is truer in the sense of more accurately

describing reality in the way that traditional metaphysics advocates—

the common view is not therefore claimed to be refuted—but because

his view supports certain values, attitudes and a mode of life which he

wishes to advocate for the future development of man. His attempt to

replace common-sense or herd views of the world and values with

new views does not involve utterly overthrowing existing values, but

he admits it is dangerous because the herd view has undoubtedly had

survival value; the ushering in of new views is difficult and opens up

the possibility of our destruction through disorder or harmful views.

It is sometimes suggested that Nietzsche is rejecting the

correspondence theory of truth, whereby we suppose we can

Nietzsche 193

accurately reflect an independent reality, and replacing it with a

pragmatist theory of truth, whereby what is true is determined by the

effects holding a conception has on the practical conduct of one’s life

and whether it thereby works. This, however, is most misleading if one

thinks that Nietzsche’s criterion for truth is the base utility of our

views in the narrow sense of being practically useful. This would be

greatly at variance with the whole spirit of Nietzsche’s philosophical

outlook. Nietzsche defends common sense because it has been shown

to be motivated by serving specific values effectively—mainly practical

values connected with survival—but that does not mean that a view

has to serve those values, even if any view must serve some set of

values or other. He is in fact arguing against the delusion that what

promotes life guarantees truth in the sense of truths which must be

agreed to by all.

It has been said that while Nietzsche ostensibly rejects the whole

notion of views and theories of reality accurately mirroring, or failing

to mirror, a world which is an independently ordered objective reality,

he tacitly assumes a correspondence theory of truth in saying that

common-sense views, and indeed all views, are in that correspondence

sense false. Nietzsche is thus accused of inconsistency in that if all

views are false in failing to correspond to reality, there must be some

absolute standpoint which does correspond accurately to reality,

compared to which all existing views are not true; so, in fact, not all

views need be false. If, as Nietzsche says, error might well be a

condition for life, and views that promote life are not thereby shown to

be true, it suggests that there is some sense in which some theory

might be true in reflecting reality more accurately. Be that as it may,

Nietzsche wishes to undermine and replace the correspondence notion

of truth with a notion of “truth” that is open about its being motivated

by promoting some specific values or other, rather than claiming

disinterestedly to pursue correspondence to an objective reality; and

these values, and hence the associated “truths”, need not be accepted

by everyone. Nietzsche’s claim is that we cannot rid ourselves of the

values that motivate our “truths”, which such “truths” in fact serve

and which lead to our deciding what is “true”. But it is arguable that

because a view is shown to promote certain specific values, this is

sufficient to show that the view cannot nevertheless just be true in the

sense of reflecting reality.

Nietzsche does indeed present to us a theory in the “will-topower”

which is a view of the world; the world is the will-to-power,

and nothing else besides. Partly he seems to do this in order to show

that the world is such that no view of reality can ever be right if it

claims the world has an objective order. But that seems to suppose

some kind of correspondence notion of truth. However, he cannot

consistently support his assertion that no view can accurately mirror

reality by presenting an account of the world which gives just such

194 Later German philosophy

an account of reality. The will-to-power must be advocated on

grounds other than that it mirrors reality accurately, and this is what

Nietzsche does.

Nietzsche’s view is that the world is a never-ending flux or

becoming with no intrinsic order. The world comprises power-quanta

whose entire being consists in the drive or tendency to prevail over

other power-quanta. Power-quanta differ from one another entirely

quantitatively, not qualitatively, and they should not be thought of as

things; their entire being consists of their activity, which is their attempt

to overcome and incorporate in themselves other power-quanta. Each

power-quantum is the sum of its effects; it is what it does. Thus the

world is a constant flux of struggle, but it is not a struggle between

“things”, it merely involves a constant variation of power-quanta. We

too are part of this flux. Human beings are nothing more than complex

constellations of power-quanta.

In saying that the world is the will-to-power, Nietzsche sees the

will-to-power as manifesting itself in multifarious ways. But the willto-power

as such in its general form is fundamental, and

manifestations are modes of it. In all sorts of ways in personal and

social life we see the will-to-power manifest: in the drive to control,

organize and overcome. To control and make manageable does not

mean necessarily physical domination, although this is one

manifestation of the will-to-power. Any attempt to bring under control

our environment is a mode of the will-to-power, and one of the prime

examples of this is knowledge itself. Knowledge is a will-to-power

because within what we know we have a framework in which what

we deal with is manageable by being organized, so increasing our

power. By organizing under concepts of things and kinds of things we

have something that we call the world under which we transform

nature into something that is, in the broadest sense, mastered, its

disorder overcome and under control.

Nietzsche is advocating a view of reality in which his perspectivism

and his belief in the value of that freedom resulting from the creative

capacity to give various interpretations are supported, he is not

claiming a disinterested motivation. These new interpretations are not

easily achieved, nor can they be gratuitously adopted, since they

involve the adoption of values which fundamentally guide our lives

and characterize who we are.

Nietzsche’s view of the world has an affinity to that of the

Presocratic philosopher Heraclitus, whom he admired. In such a world

of universal flux it is certainly extremely difficult to see how any

theory of reality which identifies as real certain permanent “things”

which behave in certain ways could be anything but false and a gross

simplification of a flux so complex and ever-changing that it defies any

theoretical description at all. It is a world without objective order, so

there is nothing for putative objective truths concerning reality to be

Nietzsche 195

true of. Except in so far as it is trivially described as a world of

constant change, it is a world in which no description can be

objectively true at all. All views of reality which aim to be universally

true presuppose some objective fixity, so any view which purports to

be universally true of reality must be false if there is no such fixity. And

it might be argued that a view like Nietzsche’s, which merely asserts

that there is no objective order, is no view of reality at all. Reality has

no ultimate nature; that the world has a character is denied. Nietzsche

is asserting that the world has no objective order; the denial that we

can assert this without contradiction seems to amount to the assertion

that it is a necessary truth that the world has an objective order—

which surely cannot be right. There is nothing fixed for truths to

correspond to. This leaves us free, although not frivolously so, to

invent our own organizing systems, but not under the pretence that we

are reflecting an already existing objective reality.

In rejecting the correspondence theory of truth, it must be

emphasized that Nietzsche is not, I believe, giving a new general

criterion of truth at all; that he is not arguing that one set of

considerations is universally valid when deciding upon truth. That

idea includes the rejection of both the correspondence theory and a

generalized pragmatic theory which would impose one universally

binding way of deciding on the truth. There is no universally valid

criterion for truth, no single scale along which truth can be graded; but

there are different views which serve or promote certain values and

modes of life, yet all are “illusions” if they are required to be more than

valid from a certain point of view. This is close to relativism, but not

equivalent to the notion that one view is as good as any other. Some

views are better than others from the standpoint of a certain set of

values, interests, and attitudes to life, although they are not binding on

all; it will certainly not be the case that one view will do as well as

another for a specific standpoint; some “truths” will promote it, and

some will be inimical to it. The view accepted is inseparably linked to

the deepest values in life, the lives themselves, and who one is, and

one cannot easily or flippantly swap one view or set of truths for

another.

This, however, is not the only interpretation of Nietzsche’s view of

truth. Some commentators have argued that Nietzsche wishes to

replace the correspondence theory of truth with a form of pragmatist

theory; this is pragmatic value determined not by base usefulness but

in terms of a more general criterion of power and control appropriate

for those people of higher “rank-order”, those capable of maximal

power, control and creativity. Thus truth in the new sense can still be

graded along a single scale, but this time not arranged in order of

greater correspondence to “the facts” (which Nietzsche says do not

exist apart from interpretations or views), but arranged in rank

according to effectiveness of power and control.

196 Later German philosophy

Nietzsche famously proclaims that “God is dead”, not so much

because the belief that God exists is false—although Nietzsche thinks

this is the case—but because God is a bastion for justifying objective

values which must be valid for all. Nietzsche further wants to banish

even the shadow of God from the world, that is, he wishes to banish

the lingering effects of the belief in God from the world; for even nonbelievers

still often act as if somehow there were a transcendent order

of values outside the world, and as if this world were not the only

world. He claims that it has not sunk deep into our consciousnesses,

and our way of living, that this world is the only world—there is no

world beyond. If we accept this, it profoundly changes the evaluations

we make in and of our lives. It is Nietzsche’s aim to present to us a

transvaluation of all existing values for the new life, and a suitable

world-view, for truly free spirits, for the higher man’s potentialities.

Thus Nietzsche’s views are not advocated because of their more

accurate mirroring of reality—because no view does that—or because

they are universally valid; but because of their efficacy with respect to

certain values and ways of life which Nietzsche believes in and wants

us to consider.

Another way of putting Nietzsche’s perspectivism is that all truths

and knowledge about the world are interpretations: a mode of

organizing our experience under concepts which give us a world-view

with the condition that no such view can possibly be complete because

it is dependent on qualifying reference to a point of view. Nietzsche

does not object to any view because it is an interpretation; he objects

only to the view being seen as more than an interpretation, whilst

there are values it probably deviously and dishonestly promotes under

the false banner of being the objective truth. This applies to the various

systems of metaphysics, Kantian a priori categories, natural science,

common sense, and even logic. What Nietzsche objects to is what are

in fact interpretations down to their most basic constituents being

viewed as other than interpretations and as absolute transcendental

objective truths.

What underlies Nietzsche’s position is a general attack on the whole

notion of separating our theories about the world from the world itself.

There are no facts but only interpretations, and no world left over once

all interpretations are subtracted. Our theories, when considered in

their entirety, cannot be compared with reality because there is no

reality outside our interpretation which is not itself part of an

interpretation. There is no neutral ground on which to stand whereby

our interpretation can be compared with reality because to have a

conception of reality with which an interpretation could be compared

is itself to articulate an interpretation. So Nietzsche is not saying we

always have mere interpretations, because the use of the word “mere”

here suggests a comparison with something we actually have that is

not a mere interpretation, compared with which mere interpretations

Nietzsche 197

are shown to be “mere”. Nietzsche denies that there is a view which is

not an interpretation; he denies the existence of a non-perspectival,

non-interpretative view that would alone make any sense, by contrast,

of any view being merely or only an interpretation.

It might be suggested that there obviously is an interpretationindependent

reality. But the response to this is that this view of the

world is itself an interpretation. The obviousness of the view that there

is an interpretation-independent reality made up of objective “things”

of various kinds that behave in certain ways, and our inability to see it

as an interpretation, both derive from the way that the view is deeply

entrenched in our form of thinking and way of life; and this

entrenchment manifests itself chiefly in the structure of our language.

Our world-view is inherited in our language, and for this reason we

have to use language self-consciously and critically. Deeply embedded

in language is the notion of a “subject” to which “predicates” are

applied, and we take this to reflect a metaphysical as well as a

linguistic distinction. The structure of the language we use to speak

about the world implicitly involves a metaphysics: it immediately

leads us to talk of the world as containing relatively autonomous

“things”, which “causally” interact, which are observed by relatively

permanent “selves”. Indeed, the notion of “things” results from the

projection onto the world of the fiction of the “self” (the “I” or “ego”);

and the “self” derives from our linguistically requiring an “agent”

whenever we speak of actions. We do not just say “think”, but

grammatically normally require a subject who does the thinking.

Rather like Hume, Nietzsche explains our belief in causally

necessary connections through our acquiring it in a way that is

rationally unjustifiable; the belief is rather a result of non-rational

processes whereby through the observation of constantly conjoined

events we acquire habits of association; there are no objective causal

connections. The division of the world into recognizable repeatable

events and things is the imposition of a fiction by us. No two things

are ever really identical, and no two events the same; but we ignore

differences in order to establish an order; and we are not refining our

experience by this process, but rather coarsening it by making similar

what is different. More sensitive creatures who refused to categorize

under universal terms would have perished, for a simplified world is

required for survival. We treat the world as if what is referred to in our

concepts is real. But these organizing concepts are only psychologically

a priori, not transcendentally a priori as Kant suggests.

Such concepts are rightly said to be irrefutable by experience;

experience already presupposes them and is organized in accordance

with them. But that does not mean, particularly with respect to our

values, which we have inherited—our whole notion of a single scale

for “good” and “evil”—that our entrenched beliefs cannot be overcome:

they may not be refutable, but they can, perhaps with difficulty, be

198 Later German philosophy

replaced by something new. Philosophy has spent much of its energy

finding a rational justification of existing values without first

questioning the value of those values themselves.

We find it difficult to articulate any other interpretation of reality

than our usual one because a metaphysics is embedded in the very

language in which any other view is to be expressed. The same

applies to values. It is not that Nietzsche thinks there is some ideal

language which would free us from the common-sense or herd

interpretation or metaphysics and give us a true picture of the world:

a correct or true metaphysics. Rather we are to be freed from the

tyranny of seeing any views as true in the sense of mirroring reality in

order to release our powers to create new independent interpretations

that are fashioned to suit what we value most in life; but we can do

this only once we are released from pursuing the chimera of the

absolutely true complete view of reality and universally correct

system of values.

Another way of putting the point about all views being

interpretations is that the old philosophical dichotomy of the

appearance /reality distinction is eliminated; the “real world” goes

because there is no single universal complete description possible; it

cannot be formed from piecing together or summing various different

views either. That does not mean we are left with the merely apparent

world; “appearance” and “reality” are mutually dependent contrasting

concepts, and once the “real world” goes, there remains no sense to the

supposedly contrasted “apparent world”, so that goes too. The

apparent world is the world; the world as construed under an

interpretation is the world. To suppose otherwise is merely tacitly to

suggest that there is another view which is not an interpretation

characterizing “the world” with which our supposedly mere

interpretation could be compared; but there is no view that is not an

interpretation; any other view would always be an interpretation too.

Nietzsche found it difficult to express his perspectivism because of

the way that a certain view is already inherent in the language which

we have to use to express ourselves. It seems as though in asserting

perspectivism—that there are only interpretations of the world—that

we admit that there is a real world which could be described in some

way that was not an interpretation. This, it can be argued, is merely a

grammatical point: only trivially are our interpretations different

perspectives on “the world”, because this notion of “the world” is

utterly empty until an interpretation is submitted to fill it in; so there is

no “world” to compare with all interpretations; take the perspectival

interpretations away and “the world” vanishes. Truth and knowledge

necessarily involve having a view; without a view involving certain

basic concepts there is nothing for propositions to be true of, no world

for us to know; but there are no concepts we have to regard as

necessary and universally binding.

Nietzsche 199

It is sometimes said that Nietzsche’s perspectivist position is plainly

self-refuting. For if all views are perspectives—that is,

interpretations—then perspectivism must apply to itself, so

perspectivism may be false. There are a number of complex

discussions of this matter. Some critics are unable to see how selfrefutation

can be avoided. Others argue that perspectivism does not

apply to all views, but only to “first order” views about the world, and

it does not therefore apply to itself, which is a “second order” view

about views. Still others argue that perspectivism is not self-refuting:

perspectivism must admit that it is possibly false, but that is not the

same as admitting that it is false; that it is false could be shown only by

actually producing a view that was not an interpretation—one that is

free from being motivated by, and independent of, specific values—

and not merely by suggesting that a view which is not an

interpretation is possible. Perspectivism, on this account, cannot claim

that it is necessarily true, and that means it cannot claim that views

which are not interpretations—which are objectively true—are

impossible.

Nietzsche’s perspectivism is not equivalent to relativism if

relativism is construed as saying the world has more than one

character and there is no way of choosing between various complete

views of that world; perspectivism denies that the world has any

character independent of interpretations, and that any view could

possibly be complete or exhaustive. Perspectivism also holds that some

views are better than others on the grounds that they are more fitted

for certain purposes, promoting the way one wishes to live one’s life

and the values one holds most deeply about life, but these values are

not universally applicable to all individuals of different sorts at all

times and places; they are not “better” from all points of view.

Nietzsche rejects the positions which suggest that there are views of

the world and systems of values that are binding on everyone equally.

He also rejects the notion and pretence that truth can be pursued in a

disinterested fashion. The view that there is one truth, and one system

of values, is itself a view which is intended to promote—although it

may do so covertly and even deviously—certain values which involve

holding back more creative and courageous spirits who want to

counter the idea of universal truths and values themselves. Thus the

advocation of universal truths and values binding on all is itself one

manifestation of the will-to-power, to control; but it is also a sign of

weakness; for the belief in universal objective views and values

binding on all itself manifests the lack of power or strength and

creativity—unlike the “highest type” or “free spirits”—to transfigure

the world with new views and interpretations of one’s own and

sustain those views and interpretations without the support of a belief

in their being universal and absolutely objective.

It can clearly be argued that, far from leading to an advocation of

200 Later German philosophy

domination and tyranny, Nietzsche’s position that there cannot be

objectively true or false values suggests that each person must now go

away and find his own way, do his own work—as Zarathustra

suggests at one point—and Zarathustra tells of one way which gives

new meaning to the world. As Nietzsche writes in Thus spoke

Zarathustra, at the end of Part I:

I now go away alone, my disciples! You too now go away and

be alone! […] Truly, I advise you: go away from me and guard

yourself against Zarathustra! […] Perhaps he has deceived you

[…] One repays a teacher badly if one remains only a pupil […]

You are my believers: but of what importance are all believers?

You had not yet sought yourselves when you found me. Thus

do all believers; therefore all belief is of so little account. Now I

bid you lose me and find yourselves; and only when you have

all denied me will I return to you.

In Ecce homo, before quoting from the above passage of Zarathustra,

Nietzsche points out that these words are “Precisely the opposite of

that which any sort of ‘sage’, ‘saint’, ‘world-redeemer’ and other

décadent would say in such a case…He does not only speak differently,

he is different.”

However, there is the possibility that pursuing my own way, such as

that involved in the way of the Übermensch (Superman) depicted by

Zarathustra, could involve the subservience of others, in particular

that of the “herd”, who have a slave mentality in that they need

masters to lead them, and who lack the creative power to generate and

sustain their own new views. Nietzsche indeed seems to suggest that

such subservience is required.

There are two central notions in Nietzsche’s world-view: the will-topower

and eternal recurrence.

The doctrine of “eternal recurrence” has its origin in the idea that

the world is infinite in time, but finite in space or energy, and therefore

states are bound, given sufficient time, to repeat themselves. Thus this

world is our eternity. Although Nietzsche does seem to have believed

in “eternal recurrence” as a scientific cosmological theory, the

importance and main grounds of the view lie not there but, rather, in

its power as a myth whereby our decisions are concentrated on this

world; we had better be authentic and true to ourselves, and not

wasteful of our lives, for this is the only life we have and we are

destined to repeat what we choose for eternity. We must free ourselves

of the attitude carried by the belief that this life is a “waiting room” for

something else. There is nothing beyond, no life beyond, which would

compensate for, or relieve us of, the weight placed on our choices in

this life. To carry this burden is to support the values of strength and

independence, and not to view this world as inferior: this is amor fati, a

yea-saying to life.

Nietzsche 201

These views are better because of their fecundity in promoting a

certain way of life. But this notion of better does not apply with

absolute universality. The life is that of the “Superman” or Übermensch,

as foretold by Zarathustra. This is the life of the “Beyond-Man” or

“Overman” who sees all views as interpretations, and is released as a

free spirit to transfigure the world according to newly created “truths”

and values which are his own, and he has the strength or power to do

so. The notion of the Übermensch as creator involves the idea of

creating one’s own self. Now we are, of course, free to accept this view

or not. If we wish to embrace the values of strength and enhance our

feeling of power and control as free spirits, then Nietzsche commends

to us the will-to-power and eternal recurrence as “truths” to live by.

Previous interpretations have outlived their usefulness and have

become constraining and inimical to the exploration of new

interpretations that would transform or transfigure our world-view.

Once we see common sense, and indeed any view which seems more

than an interpretation, as an interpretation, we are liberated to explore,

and will feel we should explore, other ways of viewing the world.

Nothing could be more stultifying to pursuing other ways of viewing

the world than the belief that one has found the final correct, complete,

view; the pursuit of other views will in such circumstances, as with

much metaphysics, carry no conviction and will be seen as a mere

game played away from the only correct view. But once the notion of

an absolutely correct view, and even its pursuit, is abandoned, the

exploration of alternative modes of interpreting the world cannot in

this way be deleteriously compared. This mode of viewing the world—

that all views are interpretations from a perspective—commends itself

to those who have the strength to break with habit, custom, the belief

in absolute standards, and to produce their own views, suited to their

own values and purposes, which in turn will fundamentally

characterize who they are. One cannot separate the basic beliefs and

values one holds, and what one does, from who one is, but thereby

who one is can be changed; and Nietzsche praises those who have the

strength to give themselves laws and so create themselves.

The will-to-power, both as a view of the world as one of

ontological flux with no objective order, and as an account of the

drive behind knowledge itself, undermines the idea that knowledge

can be a disinterested activity separable from specific values;

knowledge is rather a means to support specific values. The doctrine

of eternal recurrence emphasizes the weight of the choices we make

in our new-found freedom as free spirits who have the strength

creatively to transfigure our world with new truths and values in a

way that has no end.

202 Later German philosophy

continued to ...

https://sites.google.com/site/philosophygreekancient/philosophy-and-philosophers---an-introduction-to-western-philosophy---chapter