Hellenic Theories

on The Origins of Language

presented by Sandrine Boisvert

Primitive Wisdom

As of nowadays, we are still unsure about the origins of language since we do not have sufficient evidences. You might have heard about the Tower of Babel, a biblical myth that would explain why there are so many languages spoken around the world. However, a myth does not provide enough proofs, which is why it remains a myth. In taking an interest to ancient knowledge, specifically from the Hellenic period, we would be really surprised about the studies that were done on language back then. Certainly, philosophers such as Plato, Aristotle and the Stoics were the first ones to question themselves on the origins of language, thus exploring the concept of nominalism. Within their studies we can find three main branches: naturalism, conventionalism and the myth of an original legislator. All their researches combined, they seem to all point in the same direction–that onomatopoeia would explain the reason for humans to have developed language. Surely, Plato’s naturalism seems to be the most knowledgeable theory regarding the others, though there are still certain points within these theories that necessarily relate to naturalism. As such, this essay concentrates mainly on Plato’s studies as to find the origins of language, suggesting that conventionalism and the myth of the original legislator are not that plausible.

In the first place, Plato introduces in his dialogue The Cratylus the theory of naming things according to nature, implying that we would have developed human speech in imitating natural sounds. He suggests within his theory of the rightness of names that words are formed naturally and that they diverge in different languages as to how they were first perceived by their original speakers–that names are true by nature as they are used as labels for certain things and concepts, which Plato refers to as ‘essence’. Indeed, even though at the time Greeks and Barbarians would use different terminology, syntax and/or semantics, certain expressions could be translated in each other’s language with a meaning that would not change: “in the sense that in English we say 'elephant' and in Malayalam we say ana, two different names obviously but the essence of an elephant will endure the same regardless.[...] We know that the words give us access to name therefore the names can be trusted to be natural.” (Haag) This idea of ‘essence’ can be then understood as ‘the meaning of something’ as to represent ideas, concepts, things that are truth.

As such, as Plato explores the rightness of names as to know if they are right in their use according to naturalism, he discovers that all words are true and natural as to how they were first perceived within their environment. In this case, naturalism refers to our imitation of natural sounds that were put onto language, thus that would explain the origins of human ability to produce sounds as to communicate. It seems that onomatopoeia would be the answer of where language comes from, though it would not explain how we are able to change it. As Plato mentions in The Cratylus, the name of an essence does change over time, and sometimes the name in itself does not fit the same essence as before. For instance, the word from Ancient Greek for 'man', anthrôpos, designs ‘one who reflects on what he has seen’. (Sedley 2018) In contrast, there is no single word that fits this same meaning/essence in English because it would be translated as 'wise person' or 'philosopher', and these names would refer to one who has studied the meanings of life, that has questioned it, or even refer to one who has had a great life experience (Cambridge Online Dictionary). As for the word anthrôpos, it is difficult to give it a right translation because in the English language there is no such names as to refer to the essence of anthrôpos. Even the words 'human', 'human being' and 'man' all represent different essences that do not meet the same being of anthrôpos, even though they seem similar. Those things considered, Plato presents naturalism as the theory that language would have been influenced and developed through human evolution and that it would find its origins within our ability to imitate environmental sounds.

Nevertheless, Plato does not believe that we could rely on onomatopoeia as to represent abstracts and non physical concepts, which links with Aristotle’s conventionalism. In theory, Plato’s student believes that there are complex ideas that do not have a natural phonetic form. In this case, these ideas do not have a physical body–their essence is beyond our concrete reality. For example, the concept of 'roundness' can be represented by many things such as an orange, a ball, the moon, even our own iris, but the concept of 'roundness' itself does not have a physical form. As such, Plato argues that naturalism is not reliable as to define names that refer to metaphysical beings compared to those we are able to perceived with our physical senses. (Haag; Moreira Barbosa 61-62 ) Aristotle agrees with his teacher as this argument supports his realist perspective of the world known as conventionalism. Actually, it is through semantic debates that the Ancient were able to name concepts that stand beyond our material world. (Blackson 65) Aristotle is right as he says that there are ideas that cannot be found within our physical world, though he claims that his philosophy would explain the origins of language, which is not exactly right. In fact, conventionalism is likely the origin for words that expresses complex ideas, but it is not for primitive words since they would have been created according to human’s nature to imitate natural sounds from the environment. Modern researches show that our ability to recreate sounds and identify them could explain how we came to communicate verbally. (Yule 3) Taking this in consideration, Aristotle seems to be half right when he says that it is only through semantic debates that we were able to name things because there are more evidences that prove that we would have developed language in relation to onomatopoeia.

Αθηναια

Aφροδίτη

Indeed, the Stoic Saint-Augustine would agree with Plato since he studied the origins of language, taking his main inspiration from stoic and non-stoic theories. Consequently, he presents in his work De Dialectica VI two important principles about the relation of sounds and things and how we came to give names to these things in question. His theory used to be controversial as the Stoics, in majority, believed in the myth of an original legislator: the fact that language would have been created by some divine providence, who would have put their own language onto sounds as for us, humans, to be able to recreate it. (A. A. Long 38-39) The idea that some divinity would have put their own language onto sounds in our material world still show an evidence that proves the relation of onomatopoeia and things, though the fact that it implies a divine providence go against naturalism itself. This is why Saint-Augustine decided to do his own study on the process of word formation and how we came to name non physical concepts–as to study the relation of sounds and things within human verbal communication. (Stoic Philosophy of Language)

As a saint of the Catholic Church and a Christian philosopher (Baltzly) he did not deny the possible idea that the divine exists, though within the years he seemed to agree more with Plato’s naturalism, which made him conclude to the fact that onomatopoeia would be concrete as to explain the origins of the first words ever created. He explains in De Dialectica VI that language is based on onomatopoeic similarity (similitudo) and proximity (vicinitas), a certain degree of similarity within the words. Names would have been given to words as to how we would have perceived their essence and qualities through sounds (Allen 16-17) and how certain terms refer to essences that derive from a main one. In taking for example ‘blue’, the colour, a word that would derive from it in English would be ‘blueberries’. This case well represents Saint-Augustine's idea regarding word proximity as the word ‘blueberries’ is made out of the two words ‘blue’ and ‘berries’, a combination labeled as compound words in linguistics. Therefore, Saint-Augustine demonstrates that it is highly possible that we would have developed language according to natural sounds, and that we would have been able to name complex ideas in using word affinity. Even though many of the Stoics believed in the myth of an original legislator, it seems that with one exception it became possible to know more about language and its origins, thanks to Plato’s influence and some others that motivated Saint-Augustine's research.

In conclusion, Plato’s naturalism seems to be the most plausible theory regarding the origins of language as not only his but also Aristotle’s and the Stoics’ theories link to the concept of onomatopoeia as humans were able to develop language in imitating environmental sounds. As we could name difficult concepts and ideas within semantic debates and word proximity with the help of primitive words made out of natural sounds, we have been able to create a form of communication as to understand each other, which is language. Thus, we came to have many different languages spoken around the world, even though their origins is still debated as of nowadays in linguistics. Yet, are you going to ignore the evidences as the theories relate to each other?

W

O

R

K


C

I

T

E

D


Baltzly, Dirk, “Stoicism“, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/stoicism. Accessed on March 30th, 2020.
Blackson, Thomas A. “The Stuff of Conventionalism.” Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition, vol. 68, no. 1, 1992, pp. 65–81. JSTOR, www.jstor.org/stable/4320344. Accessed on March 30th, 2020.
"Cratylus." The Internet Classics Archive, http://classics.mit.edu/Plato/cratylus.html. Accessed on February 2nd, 2020
Frede, Dorothea, and Brad Inwood (ed). Language and Learning : Philosophy of Language in the Hellenistic Age. Cambridge University Press,2005. EBSCOhost, search.ebscohost.com/login.aspx?direct=true&db=nlebk&AN=132290&site=eds-live&scope=site. pp. 14-40
¹Allen, James. The Stoics on the Origin of Language and the Foundation of Etymology. Cambridge University Press, 2005.EBSCOhost, search.ebscohost.com/login.aspx?direct=true&db=nlebk&AN=132290&site=eds-l ive&scope=site. pp. 14-35
²Long, A. A. Stoic linguistics: Plato’s Cratylus, and Augustine’s De dialectica. Cambridge University Press, 2005. EBSCOhost,search.ebscohost.com/login.aspx?direct=true&db=nlebk&AN=132290&site=eds-l ive&scope=site. pp. 36-40
Haag, Chad A. "Plato & Language: The Cratylus: Essence and Linguistification." Youtube, uploaded by Chad A. Haag Peak Oil Philosophy, 5 April 2019, https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=pH1WKc52pD0. Accessed on February 14th, 2020.
Moreira Barbosa, Maria Fernanda. "A Bref way on Philosophy of Language: from Plato to Port-Royal Grammar." International Journal of Language and Literature, vol. 3, no. 1, June 2015, pp. 61-70. PDF file.
Sedley, D. N. Plato’s Cratylus. Cambridge University Press, 2003. EBSCOhost, search.ebscohost.com/login.aspx?direct=true&db=nlebk&AN=120616&site=eds-live&scope=site. pp. 16-24
Sedley, David, "Plato's Cratylus", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.),https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/plato-cratylus. Accessed on February 2nd, 2020.
"Stoic Philosophy of Language." Visual Philosophy, https://visual-philosophy.blog/2019/02/22/stoic-philosophy-of-language. Accessed on March 30th, 2020.
Tornau, Christian, "Saint Augustine", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2020 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2020/entries/augustine. Accessed on March 21st, 2020
Yule, George. The Study of Language. Cambridge University Press, 2007. pp. 1-7

A B O U T◊

My name is Sandrine and even though I look like a shy person, I am very talkative. I can be spontaneous at times, but I am generally more of a temperate person. I really like hanging out with friends and having a good time, though taking time for myself in reading and sleeping are part of my hobbies.

For my program-related project I've worked on the link between philosophy and language in taking a bigger interest in Ancient Philosophy with Plato's naturalism, Aristotle's conventionalism and the Stoics' philosophies of the myth of the original legislator and Saint-Augstine's onomatopoeia similarity and word proximity. Overall a long but entertaining research!


M Y R E S E A R C H◊



C O N T E N T◊


1. Topic Selection
2. Plato's the Cratylus (sources 1&2)
2.1. Essence and Language 2.2. Naming–Nature or Convention?
2.2.1. Idea of 'essence'
2.3. Rightness of names
2.4. Being and Truth
2.5. Actions and Nature?
2.6. The Myth of the Original Legislator
3. General Case of Naturalism and Conventionalism (sources 3&4)
3.1. Explanation of Being = Essence + Name
3.1.1. Examples
3.2. Socrates' main principles
4. Philosophy and Language: From Plato to Port-Royal Grammar (source 5)
4.1. Plato and Aristotle: Correctness of the name
4.2. Relevant quotations
5. The Ancient and The Stoics: Primordial Wisdom (sources 6&7)
5.1. Plato's the Cratylus
5.2. The Stoics
5.2.1. Divine providence
5.2.2. Augustine's 2 main principles
5.2.2.1. Onomatopoeia
5.2.2.2. Epicurus and link with Augustine's theory
5.2.2.3. Derivation from words proximity
6. Ancient Theories of Language and Its Origin: Brief summary
7. Nowadays–What do we know? (source 8)
8. The Stuff of Conventionalism (source 9)
9. The Stoic Philosophy of Language (sources 10&11)
10. Brief Summary

T O P I C S E L E C T I O N◊

Brief Summary

Explanation of my topic (and brief summary of following sources)

As for my topic, I want to look at the ancient philosophy of language, meaning what did philosophers such as Plato, Aristotle and Socrates think about language and its origin–where do words come from, how are they built, etc. I've also seen that there was this idea of 'essence' and its purity: that essence (the being of a concept, object, animal, person, etc.) could have a perfect 'name', which means a perfect way to name a word that really represents the 'being' in question. The Ancient thought that the real essence of a word depended on naturalism, the natural way we name a word (e.g. onomatopoeia, which is according to sounds) or by convention–that people choose the name of a word in debating what are the best sounds in themselves and combinations of sounds that would perfectly represent an essence within its name (word chosen to name the thing itself).

◊ UPDATE ◊

I have decided to focus more on Hellenistic philosophies of language and do a bit of a compare / contrast between themselves (Plato and Socrates / Aristotle / The Stoics) in taking an interest in how we already perceived language and the fascination it brings within the questions that the Ancient were asking themselves. I think it shows the beauty of human nature–knowledge and the desire for knowledge, consistently questioning the reason of existence. Also, I want to add a few other theories that were suggested from the Scientific Revolution to our Modern Era as to understand which of the ancient theories of language is the most supported.

S O U R C E S 1 & 2

Ancient Philosophy and Language

according to Plato's The Cratylus

Essence and Language

  • Dialogue of whether names name the thing truly or if they are just arbitrary signs of convention and habit.

e.g. A butcher named "John Butcher"

A baker named "John Baker"

From Plato's theory of the name that truly names the thing.


Naming–Nature or Convention?

Do things have names by Nature or as a result of convention (agreement)?

  • Hermogenes: Naming is purely arbitrary. Names are accepted as the correct name for things only by agreement and convention (–see David Hume).
  • Plato: Names are natural, because truth is same for Greeks and Barbarians who speak different languages.

The Idea of ESSENCE:

"Truth is the same for Greeks and Barbarians alike, even though they speak different languages. So, if truth could have an endurance, amidst, an obvious difference in names–in the sens that in English we say 'elephant' and in Malayalam we say 'ana', two different names obviously but the essence of an elephant will endure the same regardless. [...] We know that the words give us access to name [ideas, concepts, things, abstracts that are truth] therefore the names can be trusted to be natural."

In other words, the essence of an abstract does not change, but its name does in different languages. As such, there is no 'right' or 'wrong' name for that abstract as that it keeps the same essence–the word 'elephant' in English does represent an elephant, and so does 'ana' in Malayalam. Even though they are different in pronunciation, symbols or characters, both names 'elephant' and 'ana' represent the essence of an elephant–which is its being, or the acknowledgment of its being.


  • Socrates: Are names arbitrary?

"How can you say something which is not if names are natural? If names are true and say the thing that is, how could you even speak falsely? Because in that case you'd have to be using a name which is not the right name. You have to be speaking a name of something that is not something where the referent does not exist."

Plato questions the natural theory of names as it only defines what is it the physical realm, as that many words do not have an essence which can be presented physically. For example, the concept of 'roundness' can be represented by many things such as an orange, a ball, and so forth, but the concept of 'roundness' itself does not have a physical form. As such, Plato here argues that the natural theory is not reliable as to define 'names' because there are many concepts that do not have a physical 'being'.


Being and truth

Does a true proposition say what is, and false says what is not?

"Language changes, but essence endures."

This means that even though language changes over time, that words derivate within the influence of other cultures, thinkings and motives, the essence of a being remains the same. In taking the word 'elephant' as an example, the word can variate in other languages or in the same one throughout time, though what the word 'elephant' refers to, its meaning (called 'essence'), does not change as time goes.


The Myth of the Original Legislator

True names are true because an original legislator made the names by putting the true natural name of each thing into the isomorphic form of a sound.


Note:

"Cratylus." The Internet Classics Archive, http://classics.mit.edu/Plato/cratylus.html. Accessed on February 2nd, 2020

Haag, Chad A. "Plato & Language: The Cratylus: Essence and Linguistification." Youtube, uploaded by Chad A. Haag Peak Oil Philosophy, 5 April 2019, https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=pH1WKc52pD0. Accessed on February 14th, 2020.

This source is extremely relevant to my topic as it summarizes Plato's the Cratylus as a whole in note forms. The previous informations are from this video as I put the most important points to well understand Plato's discourse.

S O U R C E S 3 & 4

General Case of Naturalism and Conventionalism

The Process of Word Formation

According to Plato, "names cannot aspire to being perfect encapsulations of their objects' essences, and some element of convention is must be conceded." (Sedley 2003) Plato says that he does not agree nor disagree with naturalism and conventionalism because they are both part related to natural influence.

"The relevant Form for a name-maker to look to, Socrates makes clear, will not be simply the generic Form of a name, but also one of its species, the specific Form of the name currently being sought. Presumably the generic form of a name as such, which as we have seen is to instruct by separating being." (Sedley 2018)

Name's function of instructing is by divising the essence and its label, but also by combining them.

In other words, once you acknowledge both the essence and the name, you recognize the being. Going back to the example of the elephant, the essence is the animal itself, while its name is the word 'elephant' that refers to the animal. Its final state in language–the being–is that we recognize both the essence as the elephant–the animal–and the name 'elephant' we gave it as to refer to it.

B E I N G = E S S E N C E + N A M E


Other example from Socrates (from Plato's dialogues)

"the Greek word for 'man', anthrôpos [...] appears to break down into anathrôn ha opôpe, 'one who reflect on what he has seen' (399c). That is, the species which uniquely possesses both eyesight and intelligence has been given a name which acknowledges precisely that distinguishing combination." (Sedley 2018) As such, Plato says that as humans we have the faculty to question our existence, such as in studying language.


Main Principles

The original name–maker will have encoded in their products their own insights–some better, some worse–into the natures of the things they were naming. (#2)

Those original names have survived into today's language, but corrupted by sound-shifts over the centuries, so that to discern their originally intended message requires special expertise. (#3)

In other words, the philosopher is saying that the name of an essence does change over time, and that sometimes the name in itself does not fit the essence as it used to. For instance, the word from Ancient Greek for 'man', anthrôpos, designs "one who reflects on what he has seen". In contrast, there is no single word that fits this same meaning/essence in English because it would be translated as 'wise person' or 'philosopher', and these names still reference to one who studies the meanings of life OR question it OR it can also refer to someone who has experience in life (Cambridge Online Dictionary). As for the word anthrôpos, it is difficult to give it a right translation because in the English language there is no such names as to refer to the essence of anthrôpos. Even the words 'human', 'human being' and 'man' all represent different essences that do not meet the same being of anthrôpos, even though they seem similar.

A name is a tool, whose function is to instruct by separating the being and its object.

Here, Socrates refers to the process we go through in naming things, abstracts or concepts, as in divising the whole being into name and essence.

A name is a 'power' (dunamis) lies in its sucess in separating the beings of its object by descriptive means.

As such, a name is perfect since we still understand the essence through the name given to a word–which is descriptive.

Different names used for a same essence, but that still modifies the being as the name is not the same.

Plato refers to synonyms as they do not directly refer to a same essence as to create ambiguity in meaning. To better understand, the word 'animal' is to represent animate beings, while its synonym 'creature' means both being and beast, and 'beast' refers to a brute animal (Thesaurus). In this case, even though the words 'creature' and 'beast' can replace the word 'animal', they remain different in their whole being as their names are different, but also their essence.


Notes:

Sedley, D. N. Plato’s Cratylus. Cambridge University Press, 2003. EBSCOhost, search.ebscohost.com/login.aspx?direct=true&db=nlebk&AN=120616&site=eds-live&scope=site. pp. 16-24. Accessed on February 11th, 2020.

This book argues also on Plato's discourse, though it explains in more details Plato's intention about language. It confirms the informations I have found in the first source.

Sedley, David, "Plato's Cratylus", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/plato-cratylus. Accessed on February 2nd, 2020.

This is an updated form of Sedley's book that has been revised. It still confirm the points the author described in his first edition, but some are added to explain Socrates' point of view and how it relates with Plato's and Aristotle's arguments.

S O U R C E 5

From Plato to Port-Royal Grammar

The Correctness of Names: Plato and Aristotle

Relevant quotations:

"In the Cratylus, the problem addressed is whether the language is a means to teach the nature of things, as Cratylus believed, or if it is adopted by convention by speakers, as considered the Sophists."

The author says that, in the Cratylus, the theory of language of naturalism is used to teach the process that a certain being has been through as to how it is reflected in its name and essence, while the theory of convention defines words in debating the most suitable combinations of sounds, in relation to onomatopoeia, in order to find the best name to define an essence, and as such as being.

Also, Barbosa criticizes the ambiguous side of Plato's work as it does not really fully "stick", per say, to either the theory of naturalism or of convention. As such, Plato's view about the origin of language is pretty vague.

Further in the text, the author explains that Aristotle prefers the theory of convention as to how 'name' and 'essence' both represent a certain aspect in reality, though in the name / combinations of sounds used to describe this aspect as to how it is perceived in reality, which fits his realist philosophy.


Note:

Moreira Barbosa, Maria Fernanda. "A Bref way on Philosophy of Language: from Plato to Port-Royal Grammar." International Journal of Language and Literature, vol. 3, no. 1, June 2015, pp. 61-70. PDF file.

This source is relevant as to how the study of language has changed throughout history, though it mostly summarizes the arguments of Plato and Aristotle according to different authors (and their interpretations).

S O U R C E S 6 & 7

The Ancients and The Stoics

Primordial Wisdom

The Ancient: Plato

t h e C r a t y l u s :

Belief about words encoded into descriptive content that are derived from etymology ideas presented by Socrates.

The elements that Plato examines in his dialogue suppose that "the elements might be sounds with intrinsic mimetic characteristics and words compositions [...] good to the extent that they put the elements together so as to depict the items they name accurately and bad to the extent that they fall short of this mark." (Allen 15)

Briefly, it means that Plato makes the connection between the fallacy in using a word to describe an essence (so that the being is wrong) and the right way to do it, so the name (either from naturalism or conventionalism) is intended to the accurate essence of a being.

Allen refers to the fact that the "composition of words [...] were truer to life than their predecessors" (16) as over time, words did not necessarily kept the same meaning and/or pronunciation, which means that their whole being (essence+name) has been altered.


The Stoics: Epicurus, Lucretius and Diogenes of Oenoanda, Augustine, Origen, Varro

The Stoics mostly based their philosophy of language and its origin by divine providence, which contrast with Aristotle's theory. First, the given names to Gods from Greek mythology as 'natural evidences' and Plato's comic approach about it as they were probably made from opinions "that they designedly encoded in the names they invented." (A. A. Long 38-39) However, it made sense for most of the Stoics as the majority of them believed in the fact that the Gods created the first words as to make a perfect language–which then was used as the reason to explain the correctness of names.


D e d e d i a l e c t i c a 6:

Augustine and 2 (out of 3) relations between sounds and things:

  • Onomatopoetic similarity (similitudo) :

Augustine is a saint of the Catholic Church and a Christian philosopher of Antiquity. (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy) His interest in the origin of language focuses on the main point of onomatopoeia, which is the given names to words as to how we perceive their essence through sounds (within their qualities). (Allen 16-17) It is said by the author J. Allen that Augustine's work was influenced by Origen's theory*, Varro's work of grammar and non-Stoic theories, which is why he does not necessarily support the idea of divine providence–he studied theories that had not a direct link with a divine legislator.

Epicurus supposes that the first words created were based on "the result of spontaneous episodes of vocalisation." (Allen 19) His students Lucretius and Diogenes support this idea and reject the theory of a divine legislator for names.

*Origen's theory is that the Stoic meaning given to the 'naturalness' of names, in considering Epicurus' theory, defines the "utterances of the earliest human beings" as names are natural. (A. A. Long 37)

  • Affinity or proximity (vicinitas, a looser degree of similarity)

"The ‘naturalness’ of names consists, then, in their suitability for communication with others; though it presupposes a mimetic relation between words and certain kinds of objects, it is not confined to onomatopoetics; instead it makes use of other means to augment language by associations and rational derivations of further expressions that are gradually added to the original stock of words." (Frede; Inwood 5)

Augustine's view of language according to naturalism does not seem to depend only on onomatopoeia, but also on the words' proximity as to explain words that do not rely on sounds (such as the concept of roundness seen previously) in relation to the growth of language and its vocabulary. He defends that naturalism, in itself, is then a label on the fact that names are based on primordial sounds and use phonetics as to give names to words that the essence derivates from a main name–and that do not necessarily have a body in the physical realm–but that they are still related. This can be understood as lexical categories and/or synonyms.


Notes:

Frede, Dorothea, and Brad Inwood (ed). Language and Learning : Philosophy of Language in the Hellenistic Age. Cambridge University Press, 2005. EBSCOhost, search.ebscohost.com/login.aspx?direct=true&db=nlebk&AN=132290&site=eds-live&scope=site

This source is extremely relevant as to how the Stoics perceived language in Antiquity, also making contrasts with Plato's and Aristotle's view. It really helps me to understand the different ancient theories about the etymology of language as the contributors of the book compare and contrast those theories.

Tornau, Christian, "Saint Augustine", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2020 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2020/entries/augustine. Accessed on March 21st, 2020.

This source helps me a lot to understand the role of Saint Augustine in the research of the origin of language and in Stoic and non-Stoic theories. It confirms the previously mentioned source and support one of its paragraph where it was ambiguous for me to understand if the authors were reporting whether Origen's or Augustine's view.

Plato and Aristotle

Origen

Saint Augustine

S O U R C E 8

Nowadays–What do we know?

Scientific Researches

Charles Darwin once said that early humans had "already developed musical ability prior to language and were using it to 'charm each other.'" (Darwin 1871; Yule 1) His theory of the evolution of human language seems quite different from what I have learnt with the theories of the Ancient and the Stoics, though it is still relevant as he indirectly refers to the idea of onomatopoeia.

In The Study of Language, the author suggests that there is no direct evidence from the past that could prove any theories seen previously, perhaps due to the absence of physical proofs. Indeed, language has developed between 100,000 and 50,000 years ago, while written evidences of language were found from 5,000 years ago. As such, even though we have an idea of when human speech was developed, it is still merely impossible to assure that one of the theories is the right one.


The Physical Adaptation Source

Yule also presents the idea that speech is a human thing since we evolved as to create sound physically as we became bi-pedal, so that our body had to adapt to a new way of breathing. Rhythm breathing was also influenced by the rhythm of walking, thus becoming a "one pace–one breath relationship." (4) Breathing is an important part of language since we exhale 90% of the air in speaking. As such, as human beings we seemed to have developed the ability of speech within the physical adaptation our ancestors have gone through in order to become bi-pedal beings with an upright posture.


Note:

Yule, George. The Study of Language. Cambridge University Press, 2007. pp. 1-7

This source is important because it proves the theories presented by Plato (naturalism), Aristotle (convention) and the Stoics (divine legislator). It also adds relevant scientific informations as to understand how the human body had changed in order for us to produce language.

S O U R C E 9

The Stuff of Conventionalism

Can You See This?

Aristotle agreed with Heraclitus and his followers who said that, as conventionalist, things that cannot be found in reality cannot have names. As the author Blackson says, we might say that "metaphysically speaking [...] what we are pointing at is in the first instance a lump of bunch of stuff, with no 'built-in' identity conditions or modal features, so that we cannot even clearly speak of some thing which we are pointing." (65) As such, conventionalism does not include ideas or concepts that do not have a physical form in reality.

In my opinion, this source only helps to weaken the conventionalist ideology since, as I said as an example, the concept of roundness as no properties in itself in the physical realm, though that they are things that are round, and so can illustrate the concept itself. However, if we take for example an orange, even though it is round–that it shows roundness–it does not represent 'roundness' itself, but an orange. In this case, the essence of an orange is not the same as roundness because they are two different being in themselves. The orange in my example refers to the fruit, which is round with its orange colour, sweet, and roundness is an abstract that implies something circular, round, and/or that is full. Hence, as Plato says, there are things that cannot be represented physically that can still have names, which goes against Aristotle's view.


Note:

Blackson, Thomas A. “The Stuff of Conventionalism.” Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition, vol. 68, no. 1, 1992, pp. 65–81. JSTOR, www.jstor.org/stable/4320344. Accessed on March 30th, 2020.

This article is important as to support Aristotle's claim since it better explains his conventionalist philosophy, though it also helps to do a contrast with Plato's naturalism in discrediting Aristotle's argument that according to conventionalism, it is not relevant to consider metaphysical concepts.

S O U R C E S 10 & 11

The Stoic Philosophy of Language

Why Do We Exist?

In the article Stoic Philosophy of Language, it is said that the Stoics' "conception of existence is dynamic. Matter as such is passive, but bodies are not, since they are also infused by logos, which is active… only bodies can act or be acted upon". In this case, it implies that even though many of the Stoics believed in an Original Legislator, there is still a number of them (like Epicurus) that believed that names represented bodies (and as such essence).

From the diagram, what we've known up until now as names is called the "signifier", which is made out of (external) sounds. For the essence, it would be the combination of both the "sayable" (the meaning) and the "name-bearer" (the thing that is getting signified). Ultimately, the being here is called the "body".

Unfortunately, we cannot see in the diagram that there are non-corporal things, so the creator of the diagram (and the site) has made further clear that metaphysical concepts are there as "they do not exist, but subsist (ὑφεστάναι, hyphestanai); yet they are real (ὑπάρχειν, hyparchein). We can think of them as conditions ‘without which the interaction of bodies in the world would neither be analysable nor intelligible”.


Notes:

Baltzly, Dirk, “Stoicism“, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/stoicism. Accessed on March 30th, 2020.

This source confirms the points made in the following source.

"Stoic Philosophy of Language." Visual Philosophy, https://visual-philosophy.blog/2019/02/22/stoic-philosophy-of-language. Accessed on March 30th, 2020.

This site is really relevant because it explains Saint-Augustine's view and how it could have been affected by other Stoics.

Ancient Theories on Language and Its Origin

Brief summary


T H E E N D◊