Virtue As a Mean and the Need for Practical Wisdom
Note that virtue lies in a mean for each feeling or action. Where the mean lies can vary with the circumstances of the situation—that is, the mean does not always lie precisely in the middle between the extremes. For example, good-temper may require that we lean toward irascibility in some cases, and extreme mildness in others. So, on the one hand, we may be quite mild toward an elderly woman who carelessly causes an auto accident and is obviously emotionally upset; on the other hand, we may act irascibly toward a twenty-year old college student who aggressively runs a stop sign and then becomes belligerent about taking blame for the subsequent accident. In any situation, there is one best way to act. To know what this one best way is, however—in other words, to know precisely where the mean lies—requires a rational principle, that is, a principle determined by reasoning. According to Aristotle, this rational principle should be the one that persons of practical wisdom use. Aristotle presumes that some persons of practical wisdom usually exist and that we can recognize them. (See the definition of practical wisdom among the intellectual virtues.) It is the mark of persons of practical wisdom that they make the right decision in the right place at the right time, for the right reason, and with the right character. Note that it is not enough to make the right decision. One also must do it for the right reason and with the right character in order to exhibit practical wisdom and act virtuously. Thus, for example, the person who is temperate out of fear of what other people will say is acting rightly, but not virtuously.
Since persons of practical wisdom are able to make judgments in many different situations, they must have a considerable amount of experience first. For this reason, Aristotle is skeptical about claims to practical wisdom by young people—although he grants that experience is not simply a matter of age. So he does not assert that an older person is always more experienced than a younger one. When it comes to matters of sound judgment, Aristotle prefers middle age.
Although moral virtue lies as a mean between extremes, there is not a mean for every action because some actions are simply wrong. Aristotle says,
But it is not all actions nor all passion that admit of moderation; there are some whose very names imply badness, as malevolence shamelessness, envy, and, among acts, adultery, theft, murder. These and all other like things are blamed as being bad in themselves, and not merely in their excess or deficiency. It is impossible therefore to go right in them; they are always wrong: rightness or wrongness in such things (e.g. in adultery) does not depend upon whether it is the right person and occasion and manner, but the mere doing of of any one of them is wrong.3
A life in accordance with moral virtue is quite appropriate to the human condition, since we are so often concerned with emotions and actions. For Aristotle however, the most satisfactory life comes through contemplation. Human beings are too variable and imperfect for the highest virtue to be achieved in dealing with human emotions and actions. Of contemplation, he says,
. . . exercise of [this] faculty must be the highest possible; for reason is the highest of our faculties, and of all knowable things those that reason deals with are the highest.
Again it is the most continuous, for speculation [contemplation] can be carried on more continuously than than any kind of action whatsoever.
We think too that pleasure ought to be one of the ingredients of happiness; but of all virtuous exercises, it is allowed that the pleasantest is the exercise of wisdom. At least philosophy is thought to have pleasures that are admirable in purity and steadfastness; and it is reasonable to suppose that the time passes more pleasantly with those who possess, than with those who are seeking knowledge.
Again what is called self-sufficiency will be most of all found in the contemplative life. The necessaries of life, indeed, are needed by the wise man as well as by the just man and the rest; but, when these have been provided in due quantity, the just man further needs persons towards whom, and along with whom, he may act justly; and so does the temperate and the courageous man, and the rest; while the wise man is able to contemplate even by himself, and the wiser he is the more he is able to do this. He could contemplate better, we may confess, if he had others to help him, but nevertheless he is more self-sufficient than anybody else. Again, it would seem that this life alone is desired solely for its own sake; for it yields no result beyond the the contemplation, but from the practical activities we get something more or less besides action.
Again, happiness is thought to imply leisure; for we toil in order that we may have leisure, as we make war in order that we may enjoy peace. . . .
If, then, the life of the statesman and the soldier, though they surpass all other virtuous exercises in nobility and grandeur, are not leisurely occupations, and aim at some ulterior end, and are not desired merely for themselves, but the exercise of the reason seems to be superior in seriousness (since it contemplates truth), and to aim at no end beside itself, and to have its proper pleasure (which also helps to increase the exercise), and further to be self-sufficient, and leisurely, and inexhaustible (as far as anything human can be), and to have all the other characteristics that are ascribed to happiness, it follows that the exercise of reason will be the complete happiness of man, i.e., when a complete term of days is added; for nothing incomplete can be admitted into our idea of happiness.4
According to Aristotle, we associate a supremely happy person with nobility, greatness, self-sufficiency, and leisureliness. But what can be more noble or greater than contemplation of the highest truths? What can be greater or more noble or more self-sufficient than knowledge loved for itself, apart from the practical uses to which it may be put? What can be more self-sufficient than contemplation, which we can engage in even while alone? And what can be a more leisurely activity than the pursuit knowledge? By these measures, intellectual virtue is superior to moral virtue.
This stress on intellectual virtue should not blind us however to the practical side of Aristotle's position, which includes a wealth of commonsense wisdom:
(a) His insistence upon moral virtue as a mean between extremes leads to rejection of extreme asceticism and self-effacement—regardless whether they occur as insensibility, undue humility, inirascibility, modesty, or bashfulness.
(b) Where the mean lies varies to some degree with particular circumstances. And some actions are simply wrong without there being a mean for them.
(c) Moral virtues do not spring up within us suddenly or through study; rather they develop gradually through the formation of good habits of action.
(d) For an action to be truly virtuous, it must be done with the right character and for the right reason.
(e) Living well stands in need of both friendship and justice.
(f) We cannot be completely happy without some amount of good fortune—such as prosperity, physical attractiveness, friends, birth into a good family, and good children.
(g) Happiness is achieved in a complete life, not in a day or a short period.
(h) Since we cannot work continuously, we need relaxation and we get it through pleasant amusements.
(i) The good person seeks out the right pleasures, whereas the bad person seeks out the wrong ones.
(j) And he insists that it is foolish to expect the same certainty in ethics that is achievable in mathematics.
Regarding the prospects for everyone's becoming virtuous, Aristotle says,
Now, if theories had powers of themselves to make us good, “many great rewards would they deserve” as Theognis says, and such ought we to give; but in fact it seems that though they are potent to guide and to stimulate liberal-minded young men, and though a generous disposition, with a sincere love of what is noble, may by them be opened to the influence of virtue, yet they are powerless to turn the mass of men to goodness. For the generality of men are naturally apt to be swayed by fear rather than by reverence, and to refrain from evil rather because of the punishment that it brings than because of its own foulness. For under the guidance of their passions they pursue the pleasures that suit their nature and the means by which those pleasures may be obtained, and avoid the opposite pains, while of that which is noble and truly pleasant they have not even a conception, as they have never tasted it.
What theories or arguments, then, can bring such men as these to order? Surely it is impossible, or at least very difficult, to remove by any argument what has long been ingrained in the character. For my part, I think we must be well content if we can get some modicum of virtue when all the circumstances are present that seem to make men good.5
Besides commenting upon the human capacity for virtue, the passage also is somewhat pessimistic about the effectiveness of ethical theories or arguments. Given this situation of human imperfection, a society—in Aristotle's view—needs good laws that habituate its members to act rightly when possible and force them to act rightly when necessary.
Controversies: Some Objections and Possible Replies
(Note About Objections and Possible Replies: You should look upon the objections and possible replies as opportunities for further thought rather than as definitive statements. Holders of the original position are not likely to be overwhelmed by the objections; and critics of the original position are not likely to be convinced by the possible replies. These objections and possible replies accomplish a proper goal if they push you to think more deeply about an issue, leading you to seek more clarity and justification in drawing your own conclusions.)
Contra Aristotle
Aside from charges that Aristotle's ethics is overly genteel and therefore best suited for stodgy, well-off members of society, critics assert that he has not really established, with evidence, why good is associated with the special function of a human being and, in particular, with reasoning. Why can't “being religious,” for example, be the special function of a human being? Some critics also find difficulties with the person of practical wisdom. How can we determine who these persons are? And if we use them as models to imitate in doing right actions, do we not need to know the right actions already in order to identify the persons of practical wisdom—in which case we do not need to imitate them once we already know the right actions?
A Possible Reply: The initial attempt to determine what good is by examining the special function of a human being rests upon the common association of “good” with function. This is a reasonable first-step based upon common experience. Ultimately however, the success of the attempt needs to be judged in terms of its fruitfulness in developing an adequate ethical position, bearing in mind that the certainty of mathematics is unattainable in ethics. Aristotle's ethics, taken as a whole, is a tribute to the success of this association of good with function. Moreover, reason proves to be the special function of a human being (rather than being religious or having a sense of humor) because it is an essential, differentiating characteristic. Someone can be human without being religious or having a sense of humor, but not without being rational (although much of that rationality may be undeveloped).
Regarding persons of practical wisdom, identification is not a problem in a well-ordered society, that is, one organized to serve the common welfare. In such a society, those in positions of influence and authority are persons of practical wisdom; and they oversee the upbringing and education of the youth so that the latter may develop into morally virtuous persons through cultivation of the habit of acting rightly. If a society is not well-ordered however, that is, if everyone pursues selfish interests, then identification and recognition of persons of practical wisdom becomes a serious problem. From Aristotle's standpoint, the lesson then is quite clear—we ought to do all we can to insure the existence of a well-ordered society.
Perhaps Aristotle's conception of a virtuous person shows little appreciation for the flamboyant, eccentric genius and offers little hope to the person in grinding poverty. For Aristotle though, poverty is a misfortune that necessarily detracts from the potential for happiness; it also causes unwanted social unrest. So Aristotle at least makes a good case for the elimination of poverty in a society. Moreover, when we consider the “flamboyant, eccentric genius,” we can all question the degree to which such an individual should be set up as a model of virtue in a society. We can also question the alleged “stodginess” of Aristotle's virtuous person. We must remember that the mean varies somewhat with circumstances, that pleasant amusements are allowable, and that temperance, liberality, ready-wit, and friendliness are considered superior to insensibility, stinginess, boorishness, and surliness, respectively.
3.521 Go over the list of Aristotle's moral virtues. Would you strive to achieve these virtues and avoid the extremes in your own life? Would you disagree with any of Aristotle's virtues or vices? Do you think that you already exemplify these virtues and that talk about them is superfluous?
3.522 Does Aristotle's preference for contemplation make sense to you? How would you evaluate the "practicality" listing, (a) through (i) for Aristotle's view of the good life?
3.523 Aristotle is rather pessimistic about the prospects for making everyone virtuous? Do you agree with him? From what you know, which philosophers, if any, are satisfied with the ability and desire of the overwhelming majority of people to act in morally correct ways? Do the views of philosophers on this point make you more, or less, optimistic about human beings? About philosophers?
1. For an account of these intellectual virtues, see F. H. Peters, tr., The Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle (London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co., 1909), Bk. VI.
2. For an account of moral virtues, see Aristotle, ibid., Bk. III ch. 6 - Bk. V.
3. Ibid., p. 47.
4. Ibid., pp. 338-340. In the quoted passage, I substituted “contemplation” for “speculation.”
5. Ibid., pp. 346-347.
Topics
Need for A Moral Law
Acting from a Sense of Duty
The Moral Law, or Categorical Imperative
Capital Punishment
Controversies: Some Objections and Possible Replies
Thought Exercises
Deontological and Teleological Ethics
Infinite Worth and Preservation of Human Life
Rationalism and Character Development
Sources