Essentials of a Spiritual Metaphysics

Essentials of a Spiritual Metaphysics

Five Essays by Christopher Ott

Essentials of a Spiritual Metaphysics

Chapter One: What do we know

Whether we are talking about an individual man, an individual woman, or an individual elephant, each individual only ever has contact with its own experience.

Pick up an apple and look at it. What do you see? Some will say "matter." That is wrong.

All you see is color. Even if you were colorblind and only saw shades of gray, gray is color. Black, white, gray, and red are all colors. So all you see is color.

But color arises only in the mind when the apple is perceived through the conditioning lens of eyes, nerves, and brain. There is no color independent of its being perceived. All that is there are frequencies of radiation. The skin of the apple absorbs certain frequencies; others are reflected. One frequency that meets the eye is interpreted by the mind as red. One is interpreted as blue. Thus you see the color that you do, the picture that you do. You do not see the matter of the apple. You see your own mental states.

This goes for all the other senses as well. Taste is an interpretation of something tasteless; sound is an interpretation of something silent, etc.

So you are, in a sense, stumbling blind in a world of your own experience.

Yet through the medium of your body, you have access to the whole wide world. So through a gross body you experience the gross world.

Now, what can you say of the apple in itself – as it exists unperceived?

All the qualities you can assign to the apple, even frequency and vibration, are irrational applications of a fallacy. Given the fact that you only have your own experience of the apple, you necessarily can only describe the apple in terms of analogues from your own brain-conditioned experience of it. And of course you cannot be sure that the actual apple is in any way analogous to the qualities you perceive, for you have no way to compare your experience of the apple to the actual apple. This fallacy of reading your apple experience into its cause (the actual apple) is the fallacy of reading effects into causes. It is false thinking – even though it feels totally natural.

So given that an individual only has access to his own conditioned experience, and has no way to understand or describe the world as it is in itself independent of his perceiving it, the question arises whether the individual has any way to say anything at all about things as they are in themselves?

Yes.

But before this individual can discover what that is, he has to give up most of his conditioning and become completely honest with himself.

For he must first admit that, as far as he knows, all things are provisionally possible about the apple. In fact, of the world beyond his experience, absolutely all things are possible.

No progress in understanding can happen until this is fully grasped.

Understand that what is said here is not that all things are actually possible. For it is also possible that some things are impossible. But what is being said is that, given the extreme limitation of the individual's scope of knowledge of things as they are independent of his experience of them, he has no leverage against which to assert that any particular proposition is impossible. So this potential we are talking about is a prescriptive attitude from which to move forward, not a description of things as they are.

If a man asserts that a proposition is impossible based merely on his prejudice, what he so often mistakenly calls his intuition, this also is of course bogus. For, since he is limited to his own orbit of experience, and has no immediate access to the world as it is in itself, independent of his perceiving or intuiting it, any claims from his so-called intuition are merely a repetition of the fallacy mentioned above. Having no access to the world as it is, independent of his experience of it, he has no way to compare his intuitions of how it seems it ought to be to how it is.

Now some say there is a class of propositions that we must say are impossible, i.e. those that are self-contradictory. This line of thinking holds that a proposition such as "The man both exists and at the same time does not exist" cannot possibly be true, for it defies the law of the excluded middle – whereby something must either be or not be. The claim that such self-contradictory claims are necessarily false still bleeds from the same fallacy as before. For such logical notions as the excluded middle, sound as they undoubtedly feel to us internally, are still grounded in intuitions found in experience. While it is soothing to the individual to have faith that his logic, derived from his intuition, is right, he has no way to compare his intuitions to conditions as they are independent of his experience.

Now there is another argument for impossibility that is equally false. It is the argument from definition – considered by logicians to be foundational to truth. This is called analyticity. For instance, the term "an immortal man" is deemed by logicians to describe an impossible creature because the definition of the word "man" includes mortality. But this definition of men as mortal is merely a regurgitation of the definer’s past experiences of men. What if there were men that the individual had never come in contact with that were immortal? Not having experienced them, the individual would not have counted them in his definition. His definition is thus objectively vacuous – telling us everything about the definer’s assumptions about things and nothing about things as they are. Words are mere placeholders for beliefs based on experience, not a compass to truth about things as they are.

If a logician continues to protest this point on the shear gravitas of analyticity (the power of definition), immortal men could be renamed "men prime," placating the logician with his own self-styled convention of attaching assumptions to signs (words). By such a simple child’s game the logician’s concerns are recycled to the oblivion from which they emerged – proving that the semanticist lives in his own hall of mirrors. The logician’s notion of truth is attached exclusively to his limited experience and bears the fig leaf of gentlemanly mannerisms. The only thing that definitions tell us is the suppositions of the definer, nothing about the world as it is in itself. Thus all that is known by definition is definition. We certainly cannot inform ourselves metaphysically from them.

If a logician says, "It is not possible that there is an immortal man due to my chosen definition of the word man, by which I include only those men who die” he is not saying anything substantive about the world beyond his experience, by which we include his experience of words and definitions. And it is precisely this world as it is independent of experience that we are seeking to describe. Logic is merely manners of speaking without contradiction – often formalized. Manners of speech do not and cannot impugn the fact that, given the limitation of our experience, all things remain possible irrespective of words. So analyticity (loading definitions into words and then deriving those definitions from those words) brings us no closer to comparing our experience with reality.

Now there is another semantic objection to the fact that, given the limits of the scope of individual experience, all things remain possible. It is sort of a pun. It goes as follows.

If all propositions are possible, then it follows that there is at least one proposition that is not possible. That proposition would be that – it is not possible for there to be anything impossible. And if there is at least one thing that is not possible, then it is false that all things are possible.

While this sounds like a fair objection to the proposition that all things are possible, in fact it is merely an entertaining abuse of words.

A logician will readily see that once this argument is stated formally, and the double negative is canceled, it merely reiterates that all things are possible.

It is not possible that there is at least one proposition that is not possible.

Reduces to:

It is possible that there is at least one proposition that is possible.

Reduces to:

At least one proposition is possible.

Enough said.

There is yet another way that people justify their assumptions about what is and is not possible. It is modal logic. In this formal language, certain conditions are deemed possible and others are deemed not possible. However, the criterion that is used to assign possibility to conditions is the imagination of the logician. Thus modal logic presupposes that the logician's imagination is the paragon of all possibility. But this assumption about human imagination, as the criterion for possibility, has no justification. If there was ever a game that logicians played without implications outside of logic it is modal logic.

Possibility is not the same thing as probability. Probability is a quantifiable attribute of world events. Possibility, on the other hand, cannot be quantified, nor can possibility be said to be strong or weak. Note that if, given the limits of human experience and imagination, all things remain potentially possible, and since possibility cannot be quantified or compared in terms of relative weakness or strength, then any claims of possibility are necessarily trivial claims – that is, they have no actual world implications and tell us nothing that was not known. And if possibility is ubiquitous and trivial than nothing substantive can be derived from it.

We have established four facts then:

    1. Individuals only ever have access to their own individual experience.

    2. Given the limit of the scope of individual experience, all things remain potentially possible.

    3. Given that possibility is ubiquitous, it is trivial.

    4. Since possibility is trivial, nothing certain can be derived from human guessing at the nature of things as they are independent of experience.

These are actual facts. From these four established facts, it would at first blush seem to follow that we could not derive anything at all about conditions independent of our experience either through observation, intuition, or inquiry. And since we have only these at our disposal, we can know nothing at all.

It is explained already that the proposition that all things are possible is not meant to be a description of things as they are, but rather an admission of the human condition of being helpless to discover how they are. It is a prescriptive attitude, not a description of conditions. This admission of mind, this complete surrendering and giving up of the old modes of thinking – in terms of imagination, invention, pretension, presumption, prejudice, claims of intuition (which are most often really a mere sense of familiarity), claims of common sense (which are really relative subjective sensations), consensus, logic, definitions, language games, possibility, impossibility – giving all this up honestly and completely marks preparedness for the attitude of thought and feeling that is the prerequisite for embarking upon true and fruitful inquiry, the path of dnyana marga. This prerequisite cleansing of the mind of the methods of false imagination are required before discernment can begin, i.e. the gradual maturation of discrimination between the false and the real.

Coupled with this abandonment of old false practices, it is imperative to retain the open-handed attitude to receive the grace of truth from a previously unexpected angle – nay even to expect it and be impatient for it. If there were not avenues of inquiry left to the honest human spirit, then all individual seeking would be pointless. And the immediate implication of this would be absolute nihilism – the spiritual death of man.

Fortunately for the life of man, not all things are possible, not even from the perspective of the individual locked in his solipsist interpretation of reality with no way to compare it to the objective world. Fortunately, for the life of man, there is exactly ONE proposition that is known with absolute certainty, and its negation is not possible by any argument.

It is that, from the point of view of any individual, it is necessarily true and obvious that

5. The percept presents itself as it does.

What this means is that the movie screen of experience (sensation, emotion, thoughts) presents itself to the individual, however conditioned it may or may not be, and by whatever conditioning factors might be active in its presentation, as it does.

In other words, 'This (pointing to what appears to be my world and thoughts) is how it appears.'

That cannot possibly be diminished. It is an indisputable unconditional fact for the individual – the only unconditional fact that the individual has.

Everything else is a mere guess.

Chapter Two: The objective and the subjective

So if the individual is limited to this solipsism, a bubble of personal experience, then how can he determine anything at all? How can he even guess at anything beyond it? How, for instance, would he even have guessed about the frequencies of radiation causing his sight perception?

Fortunate for the individual, it is generally agreed that there are hints within the scope of his experience as to its cause. While he cannot get outside of his own experience to directly perceive the objective world, a man can examine his individual experience more closely for clues to its nature.

The principle clue that something more is going on than solipsism are the two types of properties that a human being can find in his experience – called the primary and secondary qualities.

First let's look at the secondary qualities and see how early thinkers discovered their presence.

A medieval philosopher has a fever. He lies in bed as his wife cares for him. In the morning he is hot, perspiring. The bed is soaked. He strips to his undershirt, lays on top of his bedding – a cold towel on his forehead.

Later that same day he finds himself shivering with cold, calling out meekly to his beloved wife for more covers through chattering teeth.

What has changed? Not the air in the house. Nor has his body become colder. Rather the apparent change of temperature is in the man. It is not objective. It is subjective – from the point of view of the subject.

He recovers from the fever, having learned an important lesson. The sensation of the air experienced through the medium of the skin, nerves, and brain is not the temperature of the air. It is a representation of it which, when sick, fails to deliver properly. Even when he is well now, he recognizes that it is not the air on his skin that he feels, but his mind's representation of something he cannot directly feel or analyze.

An automobile inventor is standing with a stopwatch observing two cars race around a small track. Before the race began, as the drivers throttled their engines, the pitch of the engines had been consistent. But now as the cars approach on the track the inventor notices their pitch is higher. Then as soon as they pass him the pitch drops. As an inventor he knows that the source of the pitch, the speed of the pistons firing, remains consistent. The pitch that he hears, then, is not primarily a sound of pistons at all. It is a representation of their vibration, taking into consideration the Doppler effect.

Gradually men come to recognize that sense data, i.e. that which is brought to them by the senses, is subjective. It is relative to the reference frame of the observer, the condition of his organs, state of mind, laws of physics, etc. Subjective qualities are always relative.

The real facts, i.e. the objective data, are those facts that are not relative and remain consistent when measured. These are invariably only describable in terms of geometry and ratios. For instance, the speed of sound at sea level is a measurable ratio of distance to time, i.e. 340.29 m / s. This law never changes, even if it appears to change from a particular inertial reference frame of the observer. These objective qualities are called the primary qualities. They are called primary because they are first in the causal chain between objective world and subjective experience.

So, summing up, it is assumed that secondary qualities are how the body represents to itself the primary qualities. In other words, through the mediation of the central nervous system, the individual experiences the primary qualities as secondary qualities.

Chapter Three: Why not worry?

Now a series of concerns might arise. How, if we only have this paltry access to our own private experience, can we be sure of any of this about primary and secondary qualities? How do we know we are not all alone? Are we not locked into a limited solipsism? Did we not first assert that we are only guessing?

Yes, it is all just guessing. Given the pathetic limitation of the scope of personal experience, locked into the mediation of our nervous systems, nothing is certain. Not even that we have nervous systems.

These are some of the concerns that philosophers have raised:

    • How do we know there are truly other minds?

    • How do we know we aren’t disembodied brains in a tank hooked to a computer, fed false appearances electronically by a mad scientist?

    • How do we know our logic about the primary and secondary qualities is right, when it is already established that intuitions used to form logic have no genuine justification independent of experience of them?

These are all good questions, but no reason to worry.

If you see where you are in the diagram to above, you will see why it is so hard to grasp what is going on.

The seeming intractability of such problems is caused by the fact that you can never discover the source of the percept in the percept, due to the way you are situated in relationship to it. Plato described this as a cave, and from this come numerous mystical philosophies such as Emanationism, Illuminationism, etc. In this chart we simply update the metaphor into a more modern form – taking into account clues we know now that we did not know then, such as quantifiable natural laws. The principles remain the same.

But there's no harm in addressing some of these concerns.

How do we know there are truly other minds? When you dream, no one ever tells you anything true you didn't already know. It is impossible because in a dream you are the only mind and contain all there is worth knowing, even the contents of the apparent other minds in the dream. Life is different. In life, people constantly tell you things you never guessed. You can go and confirm these things. You can prove to yourself that others have mental content that you don't have. So you can't be the only mind.

The idea that you might be a disembodied brain in a vat, fed electrons simulating sense data by a mad scientist, is interesting as a narrative, but not very interesting philosophically. The scenario assumes that much of the content of the brain’s experience is in fact correct – that there are other minds (the scientist), that there are computers, that brains are brains and the scientist has a body with a brain, that at least one other person has had similar ideas to the brain’s (the computer programmer). This whole idea presupposes that the world beyond the brain’s experience is much like that experience. But note carefully the absence of profundity in the scenario. Beyond being a somewhat novel paranoiac story about the kinds of tricks that might be played on us outside our range of view, the scenario is strangely incurious about the more interesting questions, such as how the scientist knows that there is a world outside his experience? And so forth. Regrettably, bad things do occasionally happen, and sometimes they happen in places we can’t see. But such imaginative scenarios are not rightly called philosophical. They are mere amusements by people who have not yet developed much intellectual discrimination.How do we know our logic about the primary and secondary qualities is right, when it is already established that intuitions used to form logic have no sure justification independent of experience of those intuitions? From a purely intellectual point of view we simply don’t. The way that contemplatives have traditionally dealt with their own limitations is to seek a teacher or examine the testimony of scriptures. Plato learned from Socrates, Aristotle from Plato. Socrates was a master. Spiritual inquiry divorced from respect of the perfect masters and the Avatar is barren and bound to be fruitless and frivolous. Shankara interpreted the Upanishads. Meher Baba learned from Upasni Maharaj, Maharaj from Sai Baba. There is no being a maverick on the path of gnosis.

Someone once wrote to Meher Baba about a scientist who was keeping a monkey brain alive by feeding it blood from a donor monkey in a grotesque and cruel manner. He claimed this proved the soul of the monkey was in the brain. This was in 1967. Baba asked that the scientist be sent a copy of God Speaks and that he write to him immediately. The correspondence has not survived. This is all I can think of to say. One can only read God Speaks, the Vedas, the scriptures of the great traditions, or seek a master directly. All this that I am writing, right or wrong, is in one way or another no more than an interpretation of God Speaks, with an eye to shedding light on certain scientific and metaphysical points, and integrating those points into a cohesive spiritual metaphysics that might be of use to others.

The aim of dnyana is different from what people ordinarily call intellectual inquiry. While logic seeks to distinguish truth from falsity, the path of gnosis seeks to distinguish the real from the illusory – knowledge from delusion. The first relies most heavily on inference from axioms, but in the path of gnosis inference is only one provisional tool in a lengthy process of excavating and eliminating self-deception. The path of gnosis also uses the heart in choosing what testimony (such as what master or religious scripture) to trust that goes beyond its axioms, and it discriminates in the kinds of observations and judgments it should rely on, and what it relies on them for. In its quest for the truth dnyana marga (the path of gnosis) remains suspicious of its own judgments – never ideological about its methods or axioms as in the case of logic divorced of the heart.

Summing up, the path of gnosis requires a kind of shedding, rather than acquiring, of imagination. It works by respect for the teacher, observation, self-examination, release of false thinking once recognized – rather than by empty proofs based on axioms. It is an unearthing of the essential through the gradual removal of the unessential, in stages. Truth, in its traditional worldly sense, is derived by unexamined intuitions. For this reason it has been called “uncritical.” But true knowledge, i.e. gnosis, is uncovered by the seeker like the pealing of an onion, which amounts to the gradual refinement of the intuitions by recognition and purgation of hallucinations. As the mind is purged the intuitions grow finer, analogies become subtler, and eventually it is hard for the logicians, working uncritically and like automatons, to keep up.

Very often this leaves the logicians no choice but to judge the mystic, who has finer thinking than himself, in a poor light, as the one who is superstitious, obtuse, mysterious, or less epistemologically rigorous. The opposite is true, but only by experience is this understood. The logician deals almost entirely with projections of his own ego – and is disingenuous with himself. The dnyan, on the other hand, honestly seeks to overcome his projections by gradually discerning and overcoming his own fabrications, and thus conquering ignorance.

Chapter Four: Is there a me?

Most famous western philosophers are really not very good. There was a very famous French philosopher named René Descartes. René Descartes had a lot of trouble distinguishing his assumptions from what he really knew. This is all the worse because it was his intention to do exactly that.

One night Descartes stayed up late and meditated on his thoughts. He then asked himself what he was really certain of. His intention was to slough off all his presuppositions and begin fresh upon solid ground.He noticed that he could see the room, and ruminated that this appearance might be a trick being played on him by an evil demon and he wouldn't be the wiser. So he determined that he could infer nothing from his experience with absolute certainty beyond that he had it – much as we have previously said. Then he turned his attention to his linguistic thoughts, trying to examine them with the same honesty that he had afforded the room. But when it came to his linguistic thoughts Descartes came to some very odd conclusions.When he examined his thoughts, Descartes decided that, at the very least, he knew that he was a mind having these thoughts. He had the thought that since he experienced thinking, there had to be a thinker (since thinking implies a thinker), and this thinker had to be him. Thus he wrote his famous cogito, "I think, therefore I am."

Actually, for all his good intentions, assumptions clung to Descartes' intellect like barnacles to a ship lost in the fog.

When contemplating thoughts, there is no reason in the world to suppose (beyond ideology) that you are causing them. That thinking implies a thinker is a mere convention of speech.

If Descartes had wanted to strip himself of his assumptions, he would have done better to become a painter than a philosopher. For philosophers are taken in by their beliefs, and cannot detach themselves from thoughts enough to simply observe them impassively.

What do I see when I look at my thoughts? I see much the same sort of phenomena as I do when I look at the room. With eyes open I see a kaleidoscope I call "color" and to certain forms of color I assign words like "chair" and "window." To such words I further assign uses such as "sitting" and "staring." So, really speaking, I see only thoughts – colors, words, and definitions – the content of my mind with eyes open. It is all a game of giving name to form.

Now when I close my eyes, I see diffuse pictures and hear a diffuse voice. Through the belief that there is a me who has a voice, I assign my name to this voice.

Now I call all this that I see, with eyes open or closed, my percept. It is a gestalt, which taken all together I call the world. It is just by virtue of naming that I see some of it as real things, some as dreamt things, some as ideas, some as sounds, and so forth. So, really speaking, and I mean really speaking, I see thoughts through the veil of thoughts through the veil of thoughts.

But I can find no thinker at all in any of it. I can find no source of either thoughts with eyes open or thoughts with eyes closed in their field.

Where is its origin? I have no way to determine it for certain. From where does it spring? Obviously the same question can be asked of its owner. Whose thoughts are these? So far they aren't telling me.

Unlike Descartes, I recognize my idea of myself (as something independent of the percept) for what it is – simply another thought found in the percept.

I most certainly cannot, in good conscience, claim all the various things that Descartes has claimed, e.g. that he is a mind having thoughts, that God is another greater mind, that God is good by definition, that being good God cannot deceive him, thus the world has to be real, etc. How does he make this stuff up?

I only see that there is 'this' and it presents as it does. I can only open my eyes and arms and say truthfully, "It presents thusly." How can I guess where it arises from or to whom? The perfect master Upasni Maharaj once said that everything in this world is good simply because it appears spontaneously. Can I be so vain as to contradict him?Some say that where there is a percept, there must be someone seeing it. It is said also, where there is smoke there is fire. This witness or fire is called the Absolute, the Unmoved Mover, the Creator, the Light, and God Almighty. Being infinite, it is said, the witness has infinite names. It is said by a few that I am in Him, and He is in me. If I am a mind as Descartes says, then I am God’s lens. The proponents of advaita say that I am not the real witness, but neither are we two.Chapter Five: Explaining the quality distinction

The artist who did this painting was named Henri Rousseau. According to my father, Lyn Ott, Henri Rousseau was a primitive artist, which means he had no formal education in art and was self-taught. He was also a customs officer. One day Rousseau said of Picasso's paintings, which he could not understand, "Picasso and I are the two most important painters, me in the modern style – and him in the Egyptian style." My father used to laugh and laugh.Similarly there are two main explanations for human experience, the evolution of consciousness as explained by Meher Baba and all mystics before him, and the deus ex machina explanation. A deus ex machina (lit: god from the machine) was a method of solving story problems in ancient Greek theatre. When the writer couldn't think of a way to solve all the plot problems at the end of the story he would arrange to have a crane lower in a stone statue of a god. Then the god – someone hidden from the view of the audience speaking for the statue – would magically solve all the problems. To this day the term refers to an artificial or improbable device resolving the difficulties of a plot, a cheap seemingly magical solution to a problem, or an unexpected solution for someone in a hopeless situation.First understand the deus ex machina explanation of experience. Take an individual, a man or an elephant. How do we explain how its experience arises in it as it does, with primary and secondary qualities? Easy. We hypothesize an invisible, odorless, untestable, indescribable inert material. Now we define this inert invisible undetectable material as "the cause." By defining it this way, the inert something is by definition the cause of everything including experience. That's it. Problem solved. It’s impossible to refute.The only problem with this machina (in the modern case – matter) is that we are left still with the machina to explain, along with how it causes experience. Whereas we began with only our experience to explain, we wound up with our experience and its explanation, matter, to explain.The modern deus ex machina theory is of course materialism. It is impossible to mount a refutation of materialism because it has no arguments of its own to refute. It offers no account of itself. That is why I say it is a deus ex machina. It works by magic if anything at all and is entirely unsatisfying. It is a cheap solution that leaves one stupefied and thirsting for answers. Like Tinkerbelle it only lives if you clap your hands and believe.

Materialism is appealing to some who pose as contemplatives precisely because of its magical nonsensical quality. It works because you say so. It can't be argued about because it has no articulation. It causes no concerns because it can't be understood. Its existence can’t be disputed because there is no test for its existence. It's a deus ex machina.

In fact, I would write a lengthy section about how materialism is supposed to work, so the reader could examine it, if there was something to write. I did my master’s thesis on materialism, and there just isn’t. All that can be said is that materialism is the view that there is an invisible substratum of matter that you can’t see and the primary qualities like number inhere in it. And this archaic enlightenment-era turn of phrase is believed to somehow (no explanation is yet forthcoming) explain your secondary experience called “sense data.” Materialism is actually defined as the belief that ‘some day everything will be explained in terms of matter.’

ma·te·ri·al·ism -noun

[muh-teer-ee-uh-liz-uhm]

the theory that physical matter is the only reality and that psychological states such as emotions, reason, thought, and desire will eventually be explained as physical functions

(Encarta World English Dictionary © 1999)

Now, besides materialism, there is a second explanation for experience, along with its dual quality nature. It is a process (or evolution) of conditions that are found every day operating in our experience and doesn’t require positing a mysterious invisible metaphysical entity. To see how process theories work, let's take a look at one in service today.

How did contemporary geologists go about guessing how the continents got into the positions they are now in? First they examined the processes that can be found still occurring on the Earth, such as volcanism, subduction, and erosion. Then they measured the rate of these ongoing processes. Based on this information they extrapolated how such processes, over a long period of time, might have caused the continents to take the shape they now have. This field is called "plate tectonics."Similarly, with a process of evolving consciousness, we search within our mind for ongoing processes, such as sight, memory, and apperception – and we extrapolate backward to a simpler state of these conditions.Just as in plate tectonics we discover that once the continents were unified as the continent geologists call Pangaea, we speculate that individual perception was once unified in a state that some mystics call the Universal Mind.Materialism is not a process theory like these. It is a steady state theory from an era when that was the only kind of theory that there was. It requires inventive imagination, a strong desire to believe that the conclusion is right regardless of absence of evidence, and is marked by a lack of genuine curiosity. It is faith-based – in the sense that it is grounded in belief without evidence. And it is superfluously metaphysical – in the sense that it is entirely immodest in its reliance on mysterious unobserved agencies and entities with no clear explanation of their nature or account of their declared causal power. And it is irrational in that it offers no justification whatsoever for its axiom that matter will one day explain experience (and everything else), beyond a kind of complacent timeworn familiarity that it incorrectly calls "intuition." The sensation that materialists ascribe to their intuition is actually the quality that mystics call gross or ordinary consciousness – the baseless sensation that sense objects (like cups and saucers) are the ultimate reality and that their cause must therefore be analogous to them.

Evolution of consciousness requires unflinching honesty, disgust for complacent acceptance of the baseless, willingness to reexamine assumptions shown to be groundless, deep observation and introspection, acceptance of facts as they present themselves, and reason.

Such a view as the evolution of consciousness can be intellectually calamitous to the individual for a period of time, because it demands that the contemplative give up age-old and deeply rooted beliefs. But the fact that it resolves riddles materialism cannot, addresses questions materialism fails even to pose to itself, and is intellectually and emotionally satisfying to the individual who contemplates it, offers a great deal of compensation.

There are at least ten questions materialists can't answer.

    1. How does matter cause experience? Allusions to nervous systems are a red herring and avoid the question. Materialists know this.

    2. What does the theory of matter account for besides and beyond what supposedly really is real, i.e. matter? Doesn’t materialism only accomplish this feat by defining “matter” as the only reality? What if this definition is the result of a wrong belief by the definer? How would you know?

    3. How did or do the natural laws evolve? Are they material? If not, what is their ontological state? Explain better what you mean. How do you know? How is this answer consistant with materialism?

    4. What existed prior to the Big Bang? Was this a material state? Whether yes or no, by what method was this determined?

    5. What prompted the Big Bang to occur?

    6. Is a moment in time for the Big Bang a coherent concept?

    7. What is time? How did time emerge? Explain the mechanics by which time arose precisely, without inventing anything that cannot be observed within or around us.

    8. What is space besides “space?”

    9. What is the logical justification for modus ponens?

    10. What is the cause of healthy human intuitions, and by what faculty do you know this?

Decade after decade materialism has survived through evasion, obfuscation, red herrings, band wagon, appeal to authority, straw man arguments, ad hominem circumstantial (attacking the sanity or judgment of the arguer, rather than his argument), intimidation, and posturing. Such methods never satisfy the heart and mind of a true contemplative.

Chapter Six: "The Matrix" as a depiction of materialism

Some people mistakenly believe that the movie “The Matrix” depicts a philosophical position known as idealism. In fact, it portrays many of the aspects of materialism.In the movie two worlds are depicted, analogous to the dualism found in materialism. On the one hand there is the world of sense experience (secondary qualities) that Neo enjoys when he is plugged into the computer – the plugging in being analogous to the network of nerves and brain that, according to materialism, feed us illusions from somewhere the materialist cannot isolate. At the prompting of Orpheus, Neo experiences the primary or real world, depicted in the film as a gruesome parallel duplicate of the sensory world of experience, only more hard-core and older. The twin real world is distinguishable only by Orpheus. Anyone stumbling around wouldn’t be able to tell.This is the view of materialism – a confused notion of a parallel world analogous to the one you see. Where you see the film’s logic break down – very much at the point that materialism breaks down – is when Neo is freed by being unhooked from his patch that is analogous to his nervous system. So he sees clearly when he gets unhooked from his own head (????). This is like removing your eyes in order to see properly.This movie confuses the dualism of materialism with mysticism or even Buddhism. In real mysticism there is no such nonsensical dualism. For the actual mystic, the Supreme Reality is not analogous to the world of sense experience – but to the witness of things seen.

We can put rocks in a jar. We can grind up big objects and put the grindings in several jars. We could even close up a jar and trap air in it. We could put anything in a jar so long as we found a big enough jar.But we can't put freedom in a jar. It's not that kind of thing. We can't put happiness in a jar. We can't put seeing in a jar.These things that we can't put in a jar are the kinds of things that metaphysicians think about.Now, because the ordinary human brain we all have was evolved to deal mostly with physical things that can fit in a jar, when we try to think about things that aren't physical we are very often prone to try to think of those things LIKE they were things we could fit in a jar. As silly as this sounds it is really a very important point to get hold of. Consider this quote by Meher Baba where he is expressing the same point in a little bit different context.

If the mind tries to understand the spirit independently of the heart, it is bound to use analogues from the material world. (Discourses, 1967 edition, The Avenues to Understanding, p136)

An example of applying gross analogues where they don’t belong is a person who thinks his seeing comes out of his eyes and lands

At best, “The Matrix” depicts experience of alternate states of consciousness that have only relatively higher reality, but does not depict the Supreme Reality or first cause that is of interest in dnyana marga.The aim of mysticism or marga is not to trade one form of sense experience for a second. It is to see all sensations as illusions caused by conditioned mind, and to transcend illusion to remerge with the all-presiding source.In the understanding of the evolution of consciousness there is only one world, the one you see, because there is nothing to world(s) except your seeing them. World is created in the act of seeing it as such – by how you see. Oh! And you can't unplug your head.Materialism is a two-world Platonic philosophy stripped of Plato’s mysticism. In it there is the physical world you can't see unless you take a pill – signifying becoming a philosopher. And then there is the faux world of mere appearances that the slaves live in. “The Matrix” is, in the final analysis, faux mysticism.

It would be hard to make an interesting movie about perceptual evolution because there isn't any cool other world you can go to – just the dumb real one we live in until we overcome the influence of Maya. This is the sense in which Plato intended the tied slaves in the cave to be understood. They must untie themselves, pass even beyond the archetypes (sanskaras), and exit the cave into the unified and undifferentiated light of the Absolute Perfection.

Speaking Plainly

Metaphysics is the area of philosophy that deals with problems that the human brain wasn't really created to understand. When we were cavemen and our brains were evolving, we were dealing with physical objects like food and water, sticks and stones. So we were born into this world adapted to a harsh physical world, making objects and counting beads, not for the fine subtleties of abstract ideas.

So there is nothing so natural as having trouble with metaphysics for an ordinary man.

But just as there are finer thoughts than merely counting beads, there are finer faculties latent within man that, in the course of time, can gradually be unlocked and put to use. These finer faculties do not evolve in us in the same way that the rougher sensibilities we adopted to cope with physical life did, but rather these finer faculties were always dormant. It is not by evolution, but by wearing away of the rougher faculties that these finer faculties are revealed. And generally this is a slow process of wearing away of veils to expose the higher intuitions.

Still, if a person is interested and willing, is sincere and determined, and above all is honest with himself, the unlocking of these higher faculties can occur more quickly to some degree, even if the seeker is very new to the path. For to the degree of honesty, determination, and concentration, maturation can be fast or slow.

To this end, of explaining what metaphysics is and giving a boost to the seeker that is unfamiliar with such issues and is perhaps entirely lost or confused by them, I have devised what I hope is an introduction that is more simple without being simplistic.

We begin by isolating in our thinking what we mean by physical stuff.

To make it very simple, we can say that physical stuff is stuff we can put in a jar.

on objects it sees – like old comic strips of Superman’s heat vision. Such a person is making the mistake of imagining seeing like it's air or water. That's called an "analogue." He's thinking of something nonphysical – seeing – as if it's "analogous" to physical stuff. That's a problem. I can’t overemphasize how common such a problem in thinking is, or how much it impedes progress.Meher Baba was not only very smart and knew everything, but he was also very considerate of where people are and how they think. He knew their limitations but also wanted them to progress beyond these limits. He knew how people think, so he took the things he wanted to communicate and he explained them in a way that people could just barely get if they really tried, even with their very physical kind of thinking.So to make metaphysical things clear enough for people to focus on in order to progress, he used simple analogues that his devotees could picture, like drops and an Ocean, to explain issues of spirit and Existence.

But more privately, when Baba wanted to take certain people deeper into his gnosis, if they were duly prepared as his mandali were, he used finer, somewhat less physical, analogues – but still things from their experience they could relate to. So, for instance, in the Infinite Intelligence Notebooks taken from more private discourses given directly to his early disciples, Baba speaks about experience more like it is, using the word “oopabhog (meaning enjoyment or taking the experience of),” and sanskaras more as they are – analogous to glasses on the eye.

So the seeing of the shadow or the experiencing of the universe is done by his eye according to the glasses, i.e. subtle and gross forms, that his eye receives; and these glasses are produced opposite the eye according to the past impressions attached on the eye. (Infinite Intelligence)

Were Baba to use no analogies at all from our experience, we wouldn't have a clue what he meant.

Now, one of the reasons my own writing in the past was difficult to understand is that I often write in finer analogues or no analogues from the physical world at all. So, for instance, I will speak of perceptual schemata (ways of organizing experience) or of the process of psychological apperception, and I will give examples of sensory processes at work in experience that the reader can discover in his experience by examining its workings, but few or no analogies.

Nothing appears to be more difficult than when I talk about perception, for perception is something I don’t understand in a discursive linguistic way, but is rather intimately familiar to me in a way I can’t easily articulate. Sometimes I ask the reader to notice his seeing. But this is really confusing for some readers because people aren't sure if I mean the things they see like the things in the room they are in, or something else. So I explain I don't mean the impression they experience of things in the room. That, I explain, is the image or the percept. I mean the actual act of seeing like a verb. I have learned through trials that it is hard for many people, but not all, to hold their perception in their thoughts this way. As I have said, they are used to thinking of things like rocks and water and not at all designed by nature to think about the act of seeing the rocks, divorced from the rocks.

So that's what's so hard about much of my writing. It's the subject matter, not the language. Or this is what I now suspect.

So now that I've explained all this, the reader ought to be more than prepared for me to explain some of my most basic ideas – in very broad terms – in simple words.

There really is only perception.

There isn't even someone doing the perceiving.

If there is a seer, it is seeing itself.

If there is something seen it is the result of the act of seeing – and is nondifferent from the seeing itself.

Now if there is only perception, then it is no contradiction to assume that there are ways of perceiving. Just as, if there were only running, there would be no contradiction in saying there are ways of running.

I discern from reading Baba’s writing that these ways of perceiving (sanskaras) evolve and collect to produce an image.

This evolution of ways of perceiving (sanskaras) happens first in perception in its undifferentiated state of course. For by what manner of perception would it have to be divided?

Now, as this undifferentiated state of perception evolves, it gradually gives rise to individual states of perception called atmas, which are really only apparent states in the undifferentiated, caused by the accumulated ways of perceiving (sanskaras).

So, we take this always from the Beginning and move forward to see how this miracle of the self’s apparent emergence takes place.

First, time evolves in perception. Time is a way of perceiving. Seeing temporally causes things to be seen temporally.

Next is space. Space is a way of perceiving. Seeing spatially causes things to be seen spatially (with extension).

All natural laws are relations of space and time.

So now, relations of space and time evolve as new ways of seeing – and this is called the rise of natural laws.

Natural laws are ways of perceiving – laws of perception.

For example, seen through the law of gravity, things will be seen to fall.

These laws of seeing evolved even before there were any ‘things’ to be governed by them, e.g. gravity evolved as a way of seeing before there was anything to be seen falling.

So if the laws of nature are laws of perception, note the enormous implication:

Scientists can describe absolutely EVERYTHING about physical objects and their motions in terms of natural laws. This is not an exaggeration.

So when it is said that the natural laws are really laws of perceiving, nothing is left out of this account of physical things seen.

So speaking truly – all that is (physically) is seeing. And all that is ever happening (physically) is seeing and ways of seeing.

All living forms are reducible to natural laws, not simply governed by them. Thus arises in physical evolution the individual creatures.

The creature, i.e. the organism, is then the lens through which perception begins to perceive as an individual.

The brain and nerves of the organism evolve further. As it evolves more is seen, heard, smelt. Soon thinking evolves via ways of seeing. Seeing signs as symbols gives rise to words. Seeing objects through words gives rise to judgments, etc.

So the mental events also are caused by ways of perceiving.

For example, a man seeing a man through the schema of rich and poor, based on learned customs of dress and manner, he will see the man as rich or poor.

Now finally man finds himself in the world of his experience, when all the while his is nothing but Undifferentiated Perception that never went anywhere since it was never in space – but rather produced space in the act of seeing spatially. Perception never really moved forward in time, because it wasn’t in time – but produced time in the act of seeing temporally. Perception was never really conditioned by the laws of nature, because Perception produced the laws of nature by seeing in terms of them. Perception was never really a thought because Perception produced thought in the act of seeing things as signs symbolically. Perception was never a thing, because perception produced things in the act of seeing in terms of name and form.

This is consistent with Meher Baba’s principle book God Speaks. Creation is contained in the Universal Mind and is sustained by God seeing it. In jivatma (incarnate man) state, God sees the world as an individual, and this seeing sustains the world for him. In Paramatma (God) state, God, focused upon God, would see God, but being seeing itself there is nothing for God to perceive, but only Be. He knows everything for there is nothing but Himself to know, and he is formless and colorless. So what is there to know? What is there to see? He simply is. All that is apparently seen and known in illusion by man or the Universal Mind is the result of Maya (trickery of evolving imagination).

I'll repeat my main thought.

All that is is seeing and ways of seeing.

That’s it.

Remove the obstructions to seeing, the schemata of seeing, the sanskaras, and you see clear – you see your Real Self – by which you see nothing at all. You simply ARE.

Now this might frighten someone. But Baba tells us that this state is a state of Bliss and equipoise, and not annihilation of Consciousness. Thus Bliss experiences itself as Bliss. When delusion is removed, suffering is removed. When suffering is removed, the Bliss that was all along there, but not experienced for it was latent in Unconsciousness, is revealed and never lost.

This notion of the endgame of Creation being the event where God overcomes delusional separation from Himself is the ancient perennial knowledge you will find told in numerous ways in all mystical traditions. In the West it was expressed by the German philosopher Georg Hegel in the expression Spirit meets Spirit.

It is formulated in so many ways, and the many ways it is formulated can confuse people and make them think there are many stories. There is one story told in many ways, from many angles.

I like my formulation because I think it is accessible to our modern seeing-oriented screen-loving civilization. I even find meaning in the fact that so many of Meher Baba’s closest disciples were artists and screen artists. I also take heart that my book The Evolution of Perception & the Cosmology of Substance (2004) came out before I read the analogies in Infinite Intelligence (2005). This gives me hope I am doing some good for someone.

Just so I wouldn't die and leave my daughter not knowing what her Dad was doing – because it could be pretty hard to determine if you watched me – I asked her to memorize these words: "The laws of nature are laws of perception – seeing and ways of seeing." In a real sense, it’s really that simple. I hope I’m right. How can I know until I have the experience of Reality? But these thoughts encourage me to believe there is a Reality.

To make this idea that the laws of nature are laws of perception work brilliantly to explain experience accurately and completely as we receive it, it was important to propose an explanation for how there can be the objective world and at the same time our own individual experience of it, which is a little different for each person. It was very important to explain this. Even materialism cannot explain this. It just waits for an explanation.

To do this it was imperative to formulate the problem perfectly – explaining why there are two kinds of qualities we observe when we look at things. There are facts that are the same for everyone like relative measure, geometry, and natural laws, and things that are a little different for everyone such as how things feel, taste, and how we judge them. We had to explain how there were both "objective" facts and "subjective" facts.

This involved explaining how the two kinds of facts evolved, one from the other.

To explain this I posited a process that I now think is more easily understood from studying diagrams than words. I myself studied the central charts in God Speaks for years. I have the main chart framed in my living room and have literally studied it.

Explaining the chart above: The objective facts (same for everyone who measures them) are in the singular Universal Mind, while the subjective facts (more or less unique for each percipient who looks at them) are in the individual minds. The individual minds are contained in the Universal Mind, accounting for the fact that the objective and subjective experience are compossible and explaining why the individual has access to both – the subjective upon looking, the objective if he checks closer and thinks.

Another way to say this, and more accurate also, is that the individual minds are conditioned individually, and the Universal Mind is conditioned in a single stable way by the laws of nature. Since all individual minds are contained in the Universal Mind (or more accurately supervene upon the natural laws contained in the Universal Mind), they share the conditioning of the Universal Mind – thus each individual continues to see a persistent and stable objective world. But they do not share their individual conditioning (unless they do so by cultural accident). This then accounts for the apparent objective (stable) – subjective (relative) distinction found in ordinary human experience.

There are many fascinating implications to all of this. One of the most interesting is that it turns out to be an original idea. No one at Harvard, Stanford, Cambridge, or Oxford has thought of this. The reason I know that is that three of my professors were from Harvard, one was from Stanford, one from Cambridge, and a friend studied philosophy at Oxford. Plus I studied philosophy books written at all these places. There's no such thing as Arkansas philosophy, so I didn't have much choice.

Now when I read Infinite Intelligence I was delighted, though not surprised, to learn that Baba had used some of the same analogies that I did – the movie projector, the projectionist, the lenses of glass signifying the sanskaras or conditioning on the mind. So now I am pretty confident that I am not far off the mark.

But, like I said, this is difficult. If people feel more comfortable with other analogies like the Ocean and drops then they should not worry. Baba gave them too. For all I know my ideas could do people damage by confusing them. So choose what’s right for you using your own discrimination. Baba is perfect. I’m absolutely positive I’m not.

I see twelve hopeful things about this model.

1. Understood properly and in its entirety this idea expressed in my charts and writing gives a lucid account for the evolution and apparent presence of time, space, and the fixed reliable natural laws. Prior to this there was no explanation at all. That's very exciting. When I was twelve years old I buried a time capsule on the Meher Spiritual Center that contained a letter titled “Note to future scientists.” Maybe now I have something to tell them. The time capsule is still there, by the way.

2. This idea explains gravity in a metaphysically simpler way than the General Theory of Relativity and certainly simpler than String Theory. It has ‘less moving parts’ as one kindly reviewer of my book once wrote on Amazon. And metaphysical simplicity, less moving parts, is the criterion science uses for choosing theories. It's called "Occam's Razor." That's exciting too.

3. This idea, when fleshed out as it is in my book, accounts for numerous things that no one could explain before, such as the ontology of mathematics, color perception, the rise of the human psyche etc.

4. As of this writing, the most progressive theory of language was developed by linguist and social philosopher Noam Chomsky. In my book I explain why my own theory of language, which falls naturally out of my idea, actually succeeds in accounting for the rise of language, while Chomsky’s fails to correctly isolate the central issue and thus necessarily fails as an account. That's extremely exciting for linguists.

5. This idea can account for what is called the primary-secondary quality distinction in philosophy without having to propose an unobservable substance like other philosophers have been forced to in the past. This means that the system I propose is (perhaps some would think ironically) less metaphysical than materialism.

6. This idea explains the speed of light without producing paradoxes. Einstein's paradoxes are the cause of scientism, which I argue is one of the six plagues on modern intellectual thought and development.

7. Most important to me, this idea is completely consistent with the teachings of Meher Baba, as well as Advaita Vedanta and Illuminationism.

8. This idea explains everything (both physical and mental objects) without postulating anything new to explain. Materialism, on the other hand, was totally incapable of explaining time, space, natural laws, or human consciousness. It couldn't even explain how matter arises or even what they meant by matter besides “that which is real.” Matter creates a useful model for physical chemistry, but little else. Similarly, Ptolemaic astronomy (the old Earth based solar model) is still useful for nautical navigation. Models ought not be confused with reality.

9. This idea produces a far more elegant and robust theory of money. I show this later on.

10. This theory obviates numerous diffuse other theories, supplanting them with a single unified theory.

11. This theory, as far as it goes, has no loose ends that anyone has been able to determine. It explains every quality of experience, both actual and potential, by explaining it away as a way of perceiving, or perceptual schema, even itself as a theory. The only thing it cannot explain away is the unified perceiver, i.e. God. Yet is does this without making a second zat (reality) outside of God, which would contradict God’s omnipresence. Thus it is completely consistent, if different, as far as I know, with the few mystical schools that Meher Baba upheld without qualification.

12. This idea explains everything while positing nothing. Thus, given Occam's Razor and extrapolating it to its ultimate conclusion, this idea is the ultimate idea. Thus to my mind it must be nearly true.

Now is God really just perception? I don't know. I don't think so. What I gather is that such a view would be closer to Buddhism than Advaita Vedanta.

But perception, something we take for granted everyday though we cannot see it, is the closest thing we can find in our own daily waking lives to what spirit is – if it is not spirit itself. I once wrote that perception is not consciousness but we enjoy our consciousness as perception.

If God is more than his creative and impulsive imagination I have no way to know, but I doubt that He exists apart from his nature. And creative and impulsive imagination, i.e. creating by seeing, is his nature. I think of this impulsive and creative imagination that we enjoy as God’s own. I guess that's like saying I think God is imagination and beyond imagination. He is the imaginer, the imagined, and beyond the distinction. He is incomprehensible, but not as incomprehensible as matter.

Seeing Through and Seeing As

Below is a visual metaphorical model of my idea of a process of perception as described in my book, The Evolution of Perception & the Cosmology of Substance. This model (and the theory in my book) explains what is known in philosophy as "the primary/secondary quality distinction." It also gives an account for experience that is missing from contemporary models of reality based on the corpuscular theory of reality that is fashionable in western philosophy at the moment. Finally, and perhaps most importantly, it entails a view that we are all fundamentally of one cloth metaphysically, a view which, in my opinion, has powerful ethical implications.

It may help to understand that my background is in cinema and philosophy. I have been a projectionist, a camera assistant, have a degree from U.S.C. film school and a masters in philosophy. Thus it should be little surprise that I adopt a cinematic metaphor to explain a philosophical theory of perception.

Think of perception as light. Call it "the light of consciousness." This light is all that is.

If we want to speak of God we would say that God is this light – the light of consciousness. This light doesn't have consciousness. It is consciousness. It doesn't have imagination. It is imagination.

What but imagination can imagine? What but consciousness can be conscious? What but perception can perceive? Nothing. Nothing. Nothing.

Now use this analogy. God imagines ways of seeing, states of consciousness. Liken these 'ways of seeing' to lenses. God imagines lenses, and through these imagined lenses sees. But what does he see? What is the object of his perception? Light – because there isn't anything else. Thus God is both projector and camera. He sees nothing but himself through his imagined lenses. He is both what he sees (world) and what he does not see (witness). He is both what he takes himself to be (body) and beyond what he takes himself to be. There is nothing that God (light of consciousness) is not.

When God looks through his lens he sees only the light that he projects. And even the lens through which the world is formed and through which God is informed are nothing but figments of his imagination, thus not divided from himself.

What really exists in the absolute and eternal sense is the light. The percept (forged in the light caste through the lenses) is illusion—an ephemeral figment of God's imagination. Yet this illusion is not separate from God, nor independent of him. Just as a dream is not really separate from the dreamer nor independent of the dreamer. There is nothing but the light. Thus, illusion and reality both are of God. God is too infinite to be displaced by that which he creates out of himself, whether real or imagined.

He who knows everything displaces nothing. (Meher Baba)

Now think of a projector. For we are going to discuss the formation of things perceived.

The projector has lenses. They are nothing but light (God's imagination) but through these lenses the world forms in the light as appearances. God sees the light he projects from himself, caste into forms through the lenses. Being the light, God is really seeing Himself as all these forms.

To understand this we must understand the lenses and what they form in the world of appearances.

The first lens that forms in God's imagination is time. And after it comes space. And through time and space we have the potential for the distinctions of before-and-after, backward-and-forward. But the source of the light (the spectator, God) is really located back with the projector where the light source is. The source or spectator is not really "in" time or space.

Time and space (lenses in the imagination of God) do not really ever materialize except in appearance. So the light (spectator, i.e. God) never really enters into the world of time and space, for time and space are merely imagined ways of seeing. Likewise the dreamer of a dream never really enters his dream. But from the point of view of the mind of God that is immersed in his illusion (in the form of man) he finds himself convincingly in the world of time and space.

We are ensconced in the dimensions that arise in the percept as a result of these lenses. Thus they condition our minds and experiences. So if we ask, "Is God here or there; is he now or then?" the real answer is that he precedes as imaginer all such imagined distinctions.

Now we can use this analogy of the projector to see how the world forms, and especially to explain what is called

in philosophy the distinction between the objective world (same for everyone, such as the fixed formula of gravity F=Gm1m2/r2) and the subjective world (a little different for each observer).We account for this difference with the order of the lenses. When we understand the sequence of the lenses, we see why we find this objective/subjective quality distinction. The answer lies in the order of the lenses.Each lens forms the raw material for the next distinction. For example natural laws are merely variations on pure relations of time and space, and the body of a man (or animal) is merely variations of pure relations of natural laws.Study the picture above. In it lies the key to why the facts of reality were so hard to discover. Seeing the world through the distinction of time we say that there is time. And we cannot conceive of a world without it. This is because time is part of the fabric of our conception. Thus we cannot possibly discover the cause of our percept by simply examining our percept. It must be revealed by a master or through inspiration. This explains why western philosophy has moved in endless circles, chasing its own tail as it were. Time, space, and natural laws, we thought, must be independent of perception since they are the same for every observer. In fact they are independent of the individual's perception, but not independent of perception itself – for they precede in the perceptual process the rise of the sense of individuality. We have been mistakenly reading the effect (laws of nature) into the cause. This error in thinking is called the historical fallacy as described by philosopher John Dewey.

A set of considerations which hold good only because a completed process is read into the content of the process which conditions this completed result. (The Reflex Arc Concept in Psychology, 1896)

Now look at the picture below. It shows where in the sequence of the process of perception the primary and secondary qualities (and the worlds that supervene upon them) emerge in the image.

Note that the real witness of all of the percept (both the objective world and every individual's subjective impression) is all the while at the point of the projector. The real witness (God) never really enters into his percept, but merely evolves the impression that he does. Thus in this view we are all One with God.

I have drawn light lines to show that the same light is passing through every lens, even each human body. And thus the experience of distinction of 'selves' is actually an illusion.

In this view there is only perception, an evolution of perception, in the imagination of God. God (light of consciousness) is the only perceiver and all that God ever perceives is himself (light). The percept that God perceives is his own invented illusion, which he takes himself to be part of as man. When God (as man) realizes his real original nature, he does not see light so much as becomes light and conscious of his true identity as light. In mysticism this greatly anticipated event is called "God-Realization."

The above illustration is meant to show that each person sees the same world conditioned by the primary lenses such as time, space, and natural law, but sees that world slightly different according to their own individual psychology and biology. Realize too that the psychology and biology they are using as a medium for interpreting their perception of the world of laws, is itself an outcome of those primary lenses that precede them in the process that is forming the image world. Thus, a way to think of this is that the world is partially formed behind them, and partially in front of them – behind them by God's lenses, in front of them by their own. The person arises in the middle out of the laws. Thus, like God, man is really looking at the light of God through his lenses.

Thus each person sees a slightly different variation of the same world. The world is filtered to the individual through the eyes and brain. But the one receiving the impressions is God himself actually. The one who searches is God himself. The one who becomes confused is God himself. The one who realizes his true original nature is God himself. This non-difference between the individual and the whole is called nondualism, the view that there is no true separation in time or space because time and space never really existed at all. Thus division (world) is illusion and unity (light) is reality. But both are Divine because both originate in God and remain in God for there is nowhere to go but God.

From the point of view of one who has not gone beyond Maya, it seems that there are as many individuals as there are minds and bodies. In Truth there is one Universal Being behind the minds of seemingly different individuals, who through them has the experiences of duality. (Meher Baba)

It is truer to say that the world is in you than that you are in the world. (Meher Baba)

Neither shall they say, Lo here! or, lo there! for, behold, the kingdom of God is within you. (Luke 17:21)

What is unique about this view is that it does not fall into the spiritually paralyzing trap of "mind idealism" where human intellect is the ultimate reality. Rather it is both perceptual idealism and perceptual realism and obliterates the distinction, for the world that people and living creatures experience is the actual world. In this view Plato's forms become ways of seeing and lose their ontological existence – ceasing to be mysterious metaphysical things. The image world is the only world to see, not a faint copy of an ideal primary one. Thus it is the first system to escape what is called representationalism, the idea of perception as a faint copying of something unseen. Even materialism has never successfully escaped this intractable noose, where the so-called qualia of experience are believed to represent an unseen unheard mysterious substratum. The system also is compatible with both biological evolution and an all-creating, all-knowing, all-seeing God, yet does not collapse into anthropomorphism or atheism. It is even compatible with existentialism and one could do away with the idea of God if they had too many bad emotions tied to the word "God". So it is a very elastic and adaptive basic concept. It represents a generalized shift in paradigm, a turning inside out of our old conceptions, but not a new dogma.

Another note of interest is that this model obliterates the need for a model of an atom – if one wanted to take it to an extreme. The natural laws (including quantum ones) are reassigned as perceptual schemata, or regular ways of organizing experience, rather than properties of tiny entities, a manner of thinking that seems to have no conclusion as we subdivide and subdivide and never seem to find the working core of reality.

If we were to sum this view up we would say that consciousness, which is real, creates matter, which is appearance. This isn't very original. What is original is the order of lenses and the notion of replacing metaphysical entities with a single repeating process.

In the evolution of perception, represented as progressing from left to right in the above chart, each perceptual schema (represented as pink ovals or lenses) gives rise to the raw material for the next perceptual schema. As they emerge in God's imagination, the impression they produce supervenes with the previous impression to form the world of appearances. The world of appearance is what we refer to as the phenomenal world. The world is illusion in every sense of the word, a complete chimera, a delusion. Yet what arises out of this process is God's own awareness of his existence. God himself is cause and world (appearance) is effect. Only the cause (God) ever truly exists. God (who is invisible) exists. The world (that appears) is illusion.

Post-modernism

One of the problems that faces our time is the view of relativism. For instance, people seem to have misinterpreted the implications of quantum mechanics to be that the percept is entirely in the individual's mind. This misunderstanding is expressed in new age literature such as Seth Speaks and Jitterbug Perfume, and popular movies like What the #$*! Do We Know? The newly popular but confused view is that everyone has their own reality (ENTIRELY!). This has led to the false idea that the whole world is an expression of your own ego or thoughts. An individual's thoughts, it is falsely assumed, is causing the image world. How absurd!

What needs to be understood is that some of the world that you perceive is the same for everyone and some is an outcome of your personal biology and beliefs, i.e. an interpretation of that objective reality.

Currently the world is divided into two false views. One is that the world is independent of all perception – objectivism. The other is that it is dependent on an individual's beliefs – subjectivism. Both are wrong in that they are incomplete. The whole world is perception, but not the perception of the individual.

The above model accounts for both the objective and the subjective. It does away with the old false dichotomy that it is one or the other.

Another outcome of this confusion is the sense that there is no truth and that all beliefs are mere opinion – or worse – mere "language games" (Wittgenstein). This frightening view has led to two equally frightening responses. On the one hand you have a loss of respect for truth and a view that everyone has their own truth... and of course a totally self-absorbed way of living. The other is in reaction to this nightmare – fundamentalism. Fundamentalism (the reaction to relativism) is now leading us backward to a time of dogmatism and superstition.

In the new view it is possible to have a clear sense of reality, without succumbing to dogmatism. For one has a sense of what is true for all and what is not. And one need not choose between "all is individual" or "nothing is individual." So I think this view heals a terrible divide between relativism and fundamentalism.

Quantum Mechanics

Quantum mechanics has come to be associated with a lot of hocus pocus. People use the apparently amazing nature of quantum events to justify almost anything. This is a terrible state of affairs, as it leads to the argument from ignorance that can be abused to justify almost any claim. In the new view, quantum events are rather boring and trivial. In The Evolution of Perception & the Cosmology of Substance I explain what quantum events are and why they seem so bizarre. They only seem bizarre through the lens of the old way of looking at reality. In the new way they have no magic and they have no important implications. Quantum events, in recent times, have also been used to further justify that everything is in your head. This is a socially and scientifically dangerous misunderstanding. Quantum laws arise prior to the rise of individual mind. Thus individual observers are not creating quantum events as certain philosophers have thought. Nor are they very mysterious when understood in the context of an ordered process that gives rise first to individuality and then to the image world.

George Berkeley

George Berkeley was the philosopher with a view closest to this one. What Berkeley calls 'ideas in the mind of God' simply are lenses in this view, ways of seeing. But Berkeley failed to account for the influence of the principle of time and thus imagines God as truly distinct from our minds. Yet Berkeley comes amazingly close.

Myth

Anyone who has studied the work of Joseph Campbell has realized that the subject of myth is embedded in a deep mystery. I believe that myth arises in man's own mind and is a layer of man's individual lenses, born of thought and education. But what has mystified me is that all cultures have certain common myths (See The Hero With a Thousand Faces by Joseph Campbell). This has made me wonder if I have it wrong. Does myth arise earlier in the process, before the rise of individual awareness? Or could it be that the universal mind (collective unconscious) realizes its own journey in the state of man as individual and then expresses this dimension as myth. If one studies what Campbell calls "the hero myth" he sees that it oddly reflects the whole process above as an inner journey. I think these are questions for future generations. Myth is key. In the hero myth man seems to have guessed his own real purpose, to journey into illusion to discover by trials his own real original identity.

Understanding how the model works

I want to try to explain the logic behind process theories. This will help to understand the evolution of the perceptual schemata shown above and how they give rise to the aspects of what we see. My daughter once saw a steam shovel and asked what it was. Perhaps they call them back hoes now, but I said, "It's a steam shovel." Then she asked me how it was made and I said, "It was made out of metal." Then she asked me where all that metal came from and I said, "It was dug out of the ground." To this she asked how we got the metal out of the ground and I said, "We used steam shovels." Of course she laughed cause she had caught me in a circle of reasoning. So I made up the following story.

"Long ago a man picked up a stick and dug up some soft metal near the surface of the soil. From this soft metal he made a little trowel. With his little trowel he could dig much deeper and dug up heavier metal. With this heavier metal he fashioned a strong hand shovel. With this strong hand shovel he dug up even more metals, mixed them to make even stronger alloys, and from these new alloys he fashioned a steam shovel and many other machines like cranes. And with these cranes he built this city."As you see, the only way out of circularity is to postulate a process. Otherwise we fall into an infinite regress. The same story can be told about the image-world and how it was formed. "Long ago there was perception, but it had a whim to know itself and so it went seeking. Since there was only perception, perception had to invent a first way of perceiving so it could build something out of itself. This first way of perceiving was distinction or duality, i.e. splitting in two. But this wasn't enough for perception could not pull its distinctions apart from one another so it used distinction to make a particular kind of distinction which served as a medium in which to manifest its idea of distinction. And this way of perceiving was time. Time made it possible to perceive relations. Out of relations perception created natural laws. And out of these natural laws perception formed a body. And now looking through this body perception saw other bodies. And now using its old idea of distinctions perception divided the bodies it saw into up and down, good and bad, rich and poor. Then perception (seeing and moving about through the vehicle of its invented bodies) built buildings out of decomposed bodies (trees and stones) and shaped houses and roads and labeled some good and some bad, some sacred and some profane, etc. And then perception had created a world out of distinctions in a world that we call the world of duality, which is really only in the imagination of the one and only reality which itself never went anywhere since there was nowhere in reality to go. But by this time perception was quite caught up in this fantastic illusion it had formed and took itself to be this one and that one. Slowly perception (in the form of a man or a woman) began to question the distinctions it saw all around itself and wonder about its true identity. And one day it dawned on perception that perception had always been, always was, and always would remain the one indivisible source of all that it had come to perceive. Then perception no longer took itself to be the things it saw, but rather their source. And it saw that that impression was simply its own indivisible reflection in the world of forms. The world was of him, yet he was not of the world. In that moment perception realized that the world of duality was really nothing and that perception, its source, was really the everything.

In short, out of perception is formed the schemata of time and space. Out of the schemata of time and space are formed the laws of nature. Out of the laws of nature are formed individual bodies. Through bodies color, sound etc. are perceived. Through the schema of reference objects are seen as signs. Through signs language is formed. Through language intellect is born. Through intellect cultural schemata are perceived, creating the cultural world around us.

Mysticism

What does this model allow us to see that is of spiritual value? It helps us understand what is and is not real?What is important to see through this model is that that which is truly real (on the left of the above diagram), precedes or transcends the percept, i.e. does not fall into the scope of its imagined schemata (seen in the gray region of the diagram). In other words, God (or Self) cannot be understood in terms of the dimensions that we think in. Even to say "God is One" is merely a concept understood in contrast to duality. And no such contrast can apply. Thus the mystics say of the transcendental, "not one, not two." What they mean to communicate is that about the "I am" we can only speak in negative terms, for we have no schemata to understand it with.

To understand what we 'cannot' know and why is the end of philosophy (and the final frontier of human intellect) and the beginning of mysticism. If this model allows one to see this single idea then it is of value. Of course the 'eye picture' on the left is simply a symbol that maps to nothing that we can conceive. It is more a 'place-marker' for what we cannot know with the mind.

Comparing the Old Model and the New

The old model was called 'representationalism.' That idea is that you are looking at something primary (noumenal or mathematical) and interpreting it with your brain. The new model is different. It is a seeing through invented evolved schemata (ways of organizing experience) and the result is seeing as. Each perceptual schema brings complexity to the percept, which itself is nothing but a seeing as. In this sense there is no subject or object, but rather an evolved process of simply seeing. What I see is a result entirely of how seeing is occurring. The sensation of subject and object materialize out of this process. In a sense there is no seer or seen, but rather simply seeing. But this is nothing new to the mystics. In reality this is the truly old model.

We live in succession, in division, in parts, in particles. Meantime within man is the soul of the whole; the wise silence; the universal beauty, to which every part and particle is equally related, the eternal ONE. And this deep power in which we exist and whose beatitude is all accessible to us, is not only self-sufficing and perfect in every hour, but the act of seeing and the thing seen, the seer and the spectacle, the subject and the object, are one. We see the world piece by piece, as the sun, the moon, the animal, the tree; but the whole, of which these are shining parts, is the soul. (Ralph Waldo Emerson, Essays: First Series, The Over-Soul)

The Holy Book of Science

Science is reasoned-based analysis of sensation upon our awareness. As such, the scientific method cannot deduce anything about the realm of reality that is beyond what is observable by existing means. — Lawrence Kuznar, Reclaiming a Scientific Anthropology

Picture a fictional planet that explains its corner of the Universe by imaginatively inventing magic invisible objects, forces, and substances. How easy it would be for the priests of this planet to explain whatever they wanted when their invented invisible objects could do it by a simple decree. Where is the scientific genius in that?

Now further picture this planet. If someone asks the priests for an explanation of these invented invisible magical entities, forces, and substances he is looked upon as a maverick. If he demands to see them he is told they are known only by their effects. If he asks for proof of this magical realm he is told that its existence is so self-evident that it requires no proof. If he asks the priests to articulate a way to comprehend these objects he is told they are beyond the mortal mind – asked for their cause the priests are silent. If this someone goes further and asks the priests how the invisible objects they speak of create the visible world, they are told that the priests don’t know, but that it is so obvious that they do that the question is silly.

That planet is Earth. And those priests are the magicians and sophists that have usurped the title of ‘scientist’ to perfume the expressions of their quasi-religion. The invisible objects are the forces and metaphysical substances that they insist are there that no one can see. This is not science at all. This is pseudo-science, and we have been living in a dark age of it for a very long time.

Science must find itself again, upon a renewed empirical footing.

Chapter One: Observation

What kinds of things can be observed?

    1. Pictures.

    2. Sounds.

    3. Taste.

    4. Fragrance.

    5. Pressure upon the skin, pain, heat, cold, itch…

We’ll use the first as an example to make a point. We observe pictures. Where are these pictures that we observe?

Can we honestly say that these pictures, that appear to be in front of us, are actually in front of us? Isn’t this notion of a head on our shoulders with things in front and behind it derived from the picture itself? It makes no sense, then, to say that the picture, from which we are attempting to derive information about the location of the picture, is where it appears to be in the picture. Remember, it is the picture we are asking about, not the relative location of objects in the picture. How then can the picture tell us where the picture is? We only have the picture, and not a diagram of where the picture is. Now if we were to ask how the picture originated, from whence it arose and by what process, we would encounter once again the same problem.

Now observe still deeper. Do not give up observing what exactly you observe. Think back in memory on what varieties of experience you have had.

    1. Emotion – such as light or heavy heart, butterflies in the stomach or a sense of strength and can-do energy, alert anticipation of the mind or boredom and disappointment, anxiety in the form of tension and fear.

    2. Strength and weakness in the body.

    3. Night dreams.

    4. Thoughts such as internal talk.

    5. Pictures in the head when we imagine or fantasize.

    6. Memories. Right now you are observing your memories to see if these things are present there.

Where are all these subtle experiences we observe located – such as our dreams and thoughts?

If we think they are in something called a mind, didn’t we get such a notion from our thoughts and thus from our mind?

Remember – our visual picture of physical objects can tell us where those objects are located relative to one another within that picture, but that visual picture cannot tell us where the picture is. This is because we cannot get a vantage point from outside our picturing to see where the picturing is occurring. Nor see what is causing it.

Similarly, the mind can show us a thought about thoughts, such as a theory, but the mind cannot observe the mind or how it comes into being. This is because, while the mind contains many marvelous and interesting thoughts, it cannot possibly tell us anything definitive about itself as a whole – but only its parts. It can merely guess and express its guesses using analogues borrowed from experience. This creation of analogues from experience to explain the mechanics of experience is pleasurable but not rationally justifiable. It is not really science.

At this point the mind rightfully gives up. For if we cannot get far enough outside of our experience to say anything definitive about experience itself, what is the point in talking about the subject? If the mind is smart it finds a guru at this point and surrenders itself to him. The guru is the one who has gone beyond the mind itself and thus knows the nature of the mind. Meher Baba is such a guru.

Chapter Two: Reason

Notice what is meant by intellect and notice what is meant by reason. By intellect we mean all the operations of the speaking mind, both smart and stupid, both good and bad, both mundane and profound, both passé and novel.

But by reason we are more specific. We mean only those thoughts that have a reason to be had, i.e. a justification or rationale. Furthermore, we do not mean some absurd rationale that could as easily lead us to falsity as truth, but only those rationales that could never lead us to a falsity but only lead us to truth.

How do we demarcate a just rationale from an unjust one, i.e. a good reason for holding a belief from a poor reason. The principle method is to test the justification by means of a counter-example. If someone offers a justification for a belief and you can show an instance where that exact same justification can lead to a false belief, then you have shown that it is an inadequate justification. In fact the initial laws of logic are derived in just this way – as simple and crude as it may appear.

But there is a second part of reason that arises only when we measure the veracity of a belief within the larger context of a full set of beliefs. This second part of reason is consistency.

If a system of beliefs can be derived by arguments that cannot be shown to lead to false beliefs, and secondly that system of beliefs does not contain an irresolvable self-contradiction, then that system is said to be a rational (internally consistent) system.

Now, the question will arise: can we have two systems that are both logically sound and internally consistent and entirely complete in their explanation of a particular phenomenon? The answer is yes. Thus it is possible to be rational and also wrong. The common example that is given is Aristotle who was entirely rational in his belief that the Sun revolved around the Earth (given the facts he had), but he was wrong.

Now this apparent inability of reason to determine truth with any degree of certainty would be enough to lead one to be a relativist or even a nihilist. It could make a person despair. But this pitfall is a chimera and can easily be transcended.

For, while a particular phenomenon, such as the relative orbit of two heavenly bodies, can be explained by two opposing systems, the Universe in its entirety cannot. There is only one rational system that can do that.

To understand the relationship between the global and the particular in explanations, consider this. The principal reason that Aristotle could not guess that the Earth orbited the sun was that he did not have a global enough picture of the movement of other bodies and the evolution of the Cosmos. Had he had a more complete body of information he likely would have. Having an incomplete picture of what it is you are trying to describe and explain can have a detrimental effect on the soundness of the system you form to explain it.

So in explaining the Universe in its entirety it needs to be understood what it is we are explaining – and with a completeness of observation that has not been previously practiced.

I do not mean we need to know all the facts about the Universe. There are too many. But we need to know all the facts about the nature of our experience of it. Once we fully grasp our experience of the Universe we can explain the Universe, where it is, and how it originated. But only a true guru (sat guru) can divulge its theme and purpose.

Chapter Three: Science as an examination of experience

It seems strange to say that science is a discussion of experience. But if it is not, then what is it a discussion of?

Science interests itself exclusively in experience because there is nothing else that it can, by its methods of observation, concede exists. For, if it creates a conjecture of some metaphysical separation between experience and the physical world, it can offer no justification. If it creates a conjecture of a metaphysical substratum that is not observed or observable then it has abandoned its tenets and embraced those of pseudo-science where anything is believed on a whim.

Now it is not controversial that a person only has immediate access to his own experience.

A professor tells you something to be true. The sound of his voice was found in your experience even if it did not originate there.

You think about what the professor has told you and come to your own conclusions. This thinking you have found in your experience. Regardless of how or where you might theorize that that experience originated, you find it in your experience. You can trace it no further except in your fantasies (theories) and even those you find in your experience only.

There is nothing you can talk about that you did not discover in your own experience. As you muse on your memory to see if it is true, you are musing on your experience. As you read this page, you are reading your experience of a page. You pick up the page and feel its temperature and texture and you are feeling your experience. Smell it and you are smelling your experience.

Even by the theories of science, disregarding for a second whether those ideas are true or not, you only have access to your own experience. Let me explain this, for it is helpful.

Science posits that a tree that falls in a forest does not make a sound. Rather it makes a vibration that we can only describe in algebraic terms. The vibration of the falling tree shakes the air molecules and the frequency of this vibration is transferred to your eardrum in the form of a sound wave. When the sound wave hits your eardrum this shakes the drum, which then sends an electrical signal, again sending the frequency information and not a sound, to the brain. Only at the brain is the sense data of the frequency of the vibration interpreted as a sound with a particular pitch and volume. Thus, science posits that objectively speaking we live in a silent world.This repeats with all the other physical senses. But I'll just cover pictures you experience. Science again posits that when you look at a room the picture is only in your head. The color you experience is really only the brain’s interpretation of a colorless frequency that can only be described algebraically. Even black, white, and gray are only interpretations of frequencies that in themselves have no color. So from the point of view of science, we live in a colorless silent world. Sound and picture supervene only in the mind. They do not exist in the world.

If we follow this through to its conclusion, we see that the entirety of our experience of the world is “in our head” according to science. We thus do not experience the world as it is, but only a neural interpretation according to science.

I need to clear up one misconception. Some people think that the experience of touch is unlike the other four senses and is direct. Thus they imagine that the feel of the shape of an object is a feel of how the object ‘is in itself.’ This notion is incorrect. In actuality, science posits that the brain and nerves of the skin are interpreting something that the mind cannot directly verify. To assume that ‘the world in itself’ is analogous to the brain’s interpretation of it is again a metaphysical conjecture that has no rational justification at all.

I will take this just a bit further, for it is vital that the reader get a strong sense of just how “in the dark” science posits that we are.

I said that there is no rational justification for assuming that the world as it is in itself is analogous to our experience of how it feels to our touch. There are reasons for believing that it is. But they are not rational reasons. Here are some such reasons.

    • We all assume that it’s that way.

    • It just feels that way.

    • It conforms to my intuitions.

    • I can’t imagine it any other way.

    • It’s just common sense that it is that way.

Conviction in this belief would only be justified by these kinds of reasons if there were no instances where such reasons were used to justify beliefs that later turned out to be false. We needn’t look further than the Earth-centered solar system of Aristotle. Certainly the world has had beliefs that most people assumed were true, that seemed right, that conformed to our intuitions, and that we couldn’t imagine any other way, that turned out to be false. And about the notion of common sense, many commonly held beliefs that are experienced as common sense by a person before he is educated in a particular field of study are abandoned once he becomes fully ensconced in the details of that subject. Additionally, what is common sense to one culture is not common sense to another, and so forth.

We have established that:

    1. It is a non-controversial point that we only have access to our own internal experience.

    2. We only have our internal experience to rely on as a basis for introspection.

    3. Even our introspection is a form of experience.

    4. This is consistent with the prevailing notions of sciences to date.

This is not to say that there is nothing beyond our experience. We have merely established that we have no choice but to begin to wonder about ‘reality in itself’ along with its mechanics and causes, by observing and contemplating our internal experience. If we don't understand that, then we are too unintelligent to continue.

Chapter Four: Positing a substratum

It's important to understand what is meant by a material substratum.

Very few are actually aware of what the word "matter" denotes. If asked, a common reaction is to point to something in one's experience or to pick something up to show. This is not right. The word "matter" does not refer to objects or substances as experienced. "Matter" is a word for something metaphysical that no one can see, feel, or confirm through observation. It is a theoretical entity, a placeholder for what science assumes must exist in some yet undetermined way. It is theorized to be colorless, tasteless, odorless, and beyond the scope of human imagination.

The reason it was theorized will be explained in greater detail in the next chapter. But in short it is said to be the first cause, to be known by its effects, to be the true underlying substance and fundamental reality that undergirds and creates experiential phenomena, though to this date no one has ever offered any explanation for how it does so. In philosophy it is often referred to as "the substratum." As something that is beyond the scope of observation, yet the fundamental core reality and cause of all things, it has evolved to take on all the characteristics of the deity that it replaces – minus the personality.

The constantly repeated refrain that matter and energy are interchangeable by established equations, and that this somehow establishes something about matter, is misleading. The equations referred to are found in analyzing events in experience – not by observing these theoretical entities. Rather the data found in observing events in experience is attributed theoretically to these entities. They are not actually measures of the substratum. No one is trying to fool anyone; scientists are simply so generally confused by these concepts that many of them honestly think they are touching their created conceptions. Other defenses of the concept of matter that have emerged in the last half century include that matter is simply identical to experience, or that experience is a "function" of matter. These views and others like them offer only semantic solutions to the intractable problem of explaining what matter is, and can offer no proof or observation, in fact or in principle, to test if they are true even if you can make sense of them. Thus such views are no less metaphysical and imaginary than the original form of the notion. In other words, it's just a lot of talk.

By positing a metaphysical entity, by any name, science loses site of the central purity of its method. As said above, it is by focusing more deeply into human experience that science will begin to come out the other end and discover the truth about experience itself, its nature, cause, etc. It is not, as science has vainly attempted and covered its failures with alluring fictions, to be found in circumventing experience by positing non-experienced fantastic analogues.

Science needs to return to examining experience if it wishes to find its cause, and below we begin to make a start at doing just that.

Chapter Five: The public and private quality distinction

Let's talk a moment about the nomenclature of the science of experience.

By the words “experience,” “perceive,” and “observe,” we include those observations that occur through the faculty of thought, the organs of sense, and through the medium of scientific instruments.

One who experiences something, whether we are talking about physical objects and events, or mental thoughts, is called a "percipient."

That which the percipient experiences, whether we are talking about physical objects or thoughts, is called the "percept."

In the relationship between percipient and percept, the percipient is known as the "subject" and the percept is known as the "object."

The various pieces of information that the subject can ascertain about an object are called its "properties" or "qualities."

Now, we are going to point out an important aspect of the object of experience that must be observed with extreme clarity to make further headway.

This aspect is called the primary-secondary quality distinction, and it is mostly misunderstood by this name. Here it will be explained properly and by a different name – public and private qualities.

To point this distinction out it will help to take a very simple physical object that one can go outside and carefully observe or examine mentally. It will also help to choose an object that can be observed with the eyes since the experience of sight is the most constant and thus the most conducive to slow methodical analysis.

The simple object we will examine will be a common stop sign. We will choose a stop sign because it has an easy to discuss quality, a familiar easily describable shape – an octagon.

Normally when examining a stop sign, nothing of particular philosophical interest pops out at us. But it is when examining one in person and walking around it with another person that its public and private qualities emerge.

The stop sign has two distinct sets of qualities – those qualities that are the same for every observer, and those that are different for each observer. One set are shared. The other are had only by the individual.

Herein lies one of the major clues left in the percept by the Creator to direct man to the truth of the origin of everything he perceives.

Now it is important to properly tease out of the visual image of a stop sign exactly what qualities of the sign are identical for all who labor to ascertain them, and what qualities are different for each individual who observes.

We are going to a great deal of trouble to avoid a common misconception. That misconception is that the shape, in the sense of how you see it with your eyes, is a primary quality. That is entirely incorrect.

The apparent shape of the sign is different for every observer from every given angle. The observed shape is therefore a subjective interpretation of the actual shape that must be the same for everyone. Each observer simultaneously experiences his private qualities (visual and slightly different for every observer) and the object’s public qualities (same for all who labor to ascertain them mentally from his experience).

The public qualities are purely conceptual ones, such as the number, geometry, weight, and mass of the sign along with its electromagnetic frequency. They are only describable in mathematics and geometry.

The private qualities are the individual’s impression of the stop sign, such as color, apparent relative shape, apparent relative weight, apparent relative distance, and apparent relative size.

The public qualities of the sign (such as electromagnetic frequency) are not observed by the same process as the private qualities (such as color). Private qualities are experienced through the medium of the sense organs. Public qualities are ascertained through the medium of the mind while reflecting on that experience.

As mentioned already, a common misconception is that the shape as experienced (the apparent shape) is an objective public quality. There is a difference between the objective shape describable in geometric terms and the apparent shape as it appears to the senses. The first is public; the latter private.

This misconception is often expressed in the statement, "One could imagine for example an apple without color. One cannot imagine an apple without a shape, because it is a primary quality; it exists even if unperceived." This is incorrect. You cannot imagine an apple without color. You can imagine one in shades of grey, but grey is a color. And if you imagine its shape, that too is color and form and is only a memory of its apparent shape. And if you imagine how it feels you are imagining sense data.

Now there is another misconception about qualities that has beguiled philosophers to their great detriment.

It is true that public qualities are not relative in any way. But this is generally misunderstood.

The misunderstanding arises from the belief that the public qualities include number – that number is the same for everyone and is not relative. This is partly true. The number of stop signs is the same for all who count them.

But when we go to apply this to weight and measure, we must make one caveat. In regards to the public weight and measure we are more correct to speak of a ratio that is constant – not a single number. And interestingly ratios are a measure of relativity. What is constant is the measure of relativity (the ratio) and not the unit measure.

Let us look at an example. The sign can be weighed with a scale to be 100 pounds. Anyone who labors to weigh the sign with the same type of scale system will arrive at the same number – 100. From this it is sometimes assumed that the number itself is primary and is not relative. But in this case we are mistaken. The actual number is merely an outcome of the units of the scale used. To measure the weight of the sign with a truly universal scale would require a scale that compared the weight of the sign to a fixed object in its Universe. This measure (a ratio) would then be a real constant and it is this ratio that is primary and not relative.

Now consider the laws of nature. Those that can be quantified are always ratios of time and space and never single numbers. The speed of light is not a constant number, but a constant ratio between a unit of duration (time) and a unit of distance (space). The numbers in the ratio 186,000 miles per second are arbitrary units. What is constant is the ratio that they express. Any people using any system of unit measures would eventually arrive at the same ratio, 186,000:1. All measurements, no matter what system, would be reducible to this ratio. Thus it is the ratio that is a constant. This is repeatable with gravity, etc.

There are just a couple more things to know about public and private qualities of perceived objects.

The only public qualities are:

    1. The number of objects under consideration.

    2. Their location relative to other objects in their environment.

    3. Their motion relative to other objects in their environment.

    4. The geometry of those objects, understood in abstract geometric terms only, not in the sense analogous to the impression, although derivable from impressions considered by the mind.

    5. The laws of nature that govern those object and their particles, understood in algebraic terms, once again not analogous to the impression, though derivable from it.

    6. The frequencies of vibrations understood as ratios of time and space – not analogous to the impression, though derivable from it.

The private qualities include all the sensations derived by the medium of the sense organs, including the eyes, mouth, nose, ears, nerves, and brain.

These qualities include:

    1. Color – includes the impression of light and dark, shape, line and hue.

    2. Sound, including pitch and volume.

    3. Fragrance

    4. Taste

    5. Touch, including numerous impressions such as ache, itch, tickle, nausea, vertigo, numbness, energy and exhaustion, hot and cold, pain in the eyes from light intensity, pain in the ears from loud noise, pressure or resistance on the skin, weight, and form.

    6. Apparitions of imagination.

Now we have made the public and private quality distinction very clear. It is time to see the past attempt to explain this and see why it failed. Then we will show the a coherent system that can account for it.

Chapter Six: Materialism

The traditional explanation for the distinction between public and private qualities is as follows.

The public qualities can be discovered by anyone who examines them in equal measure. For this reason they are called “objective.” It is supposed that these objective qualities inhere in the objective object and are independent of perception.

It is true that public qualities persist consistently for all who take the trouble to measure them, as we know from testimony. Thus they are independent of individual perception. However, the problem that arises in the view that the public qualities inhere in the objective object is that no one has ever been able to explain what they mean by this.

While it is not difficult to articulate a cogent sentence such as that certain qualities inhere in the object, the notion creates numerous irresolvable questions. We will cover some of them one by one.

What is the object they are inhering in?

In order to make the notion that public qualities of observed objects inhere in the object make sense, it is necessary to postulate an invisible metaphysical object or material that is independent of those qualities. For, what would “inhere in” mean without something to inhere in? This something has had many names in the history of thought – most notably material substratum and noumenon.

It must be fully understood that this something, whatever it is called, cannot be directly perceived, for all that is directly perceived are the private qualities. No one will deny that we can imagine no more than what it is possible to perceive by means of the senses. Since this something, whatever it is called, cannot be perceived by the senses it cannot be imagined. The substratum is thus not only invisible but beyond imagination and conception.

Remember that science is reasoned-based analysis of sensation upon our awareness. As such, the scientific method cannot deduce anything about the realm of reality that is beyond what is observable by existing means.

Thus materialism is not science, but metaphysics.

Beyond the fact that it is not really science, someone could still argue that there is nothing wrong with science adopting a fundamental metaphysical position as an intellectual anchor so long as it is good metaphysics. But is materialism good metaphysics?

There is only one reason for postulating the presence of an invisible and undetectable substratum. That is to explain the public private quality difference.

So to see if materialism is good metaphysics we should see if it actually achieves this aim.

In what sense do the public qualities inhere in or adhere to the invisible substratum? What exactly is the relationship that these words name? What is the mechanics of this relationship?

The answer is that no one has ever been able to propose an answer to these questions, because we are talking about something we cannot even imagine, let alone see.

How do the public qualities get into the brain or mind?

It isn't difficult to tell a story about light bouncing off the substratum and hitting the eyes and stimulating the nerves in the corneas. But remember that such an account imagines light as something analogous to the image of light spilling in through a window. But there is no reason to believe that light has such form. Remember it is the public quality we are talking about, which in the case of light is merely a frequency that can only be described in mathematical terms. To imagine it as a substance analogous to water or something in the percept is to commit the historical fallacy – where one reads into a process the results that occur because of that process. The same holds for the substratum that is imagined as analogous to an object in appearances.

The error in thinking is best seen with an example. Consider the stop sign again. A fallacy of reasoning is made when a person imagines that the public qualities of the sign – such as the geometric concept of a hexagon or the natural laws that govern the sign’s subatomic particles – behave and act just like objects found in the percept which have their relative extension, location and so forth. It is of course not denied that the stop sign has extension and location relative to other objects within the frame of experience – but to read these qualities into the cause of the experience is very primitive thinking. The actual sign does not really have location. It is not analogous to the sign that is seen. It is conceptual. This error of committing the historical fallacy is the main one made in current science, but this is likely to change very soon as consciousness increases.

Once the public qualities have arrived in the brain, how does the brain or mind convert the public qualities into private qualities? Or conversely, how do the public qualities, once they have arrived in the brain, convert themselves into private qualities.

This conversion has never been figured out. It is left hanging. It is called “the mind-body problem” and is accompanied by a parade of long but ultimately unsuccessful books attempting to solve it. Most attempts are merely linguistic attempts, hoping to solve the mind-body relationship with semantics in much the same way that the Bush administration tried to solve the problem of torture by playing with words and definitions. Such attempts satisfy their proponents, but no one else.

How did the invisible substratum of the world come into being?

Intelligent scientists avoid the postulate that 'it always existed' because there is no scientific basis for believing it. They don't know. They aren't even sure what the question refers to as there is no clear referent.

What are the natural laws, how did they form, what was the mechanics of their evolution, what is their ontological nature?

There are no current answers to any of these question. While they rightly belong within the scope of science (since the effects of natural laws are observable) science ignores these questions because its metaphysical approach to understanding nature at its core precludes even forming a guess.

The prevailing notion of an invisible substratum, whose sole purpose was to explain human experience of the phenomenal world along with the public and private qualities found in it, has not actually explained it.

From a scientific point of view a theory is an hypothesis that has gained a high degree of acceptance within the scientific community, and an hypothesis is an attempt to explain a set of observed phenomena.

Therefore, from the point of view of science, a belief that succeeds in explaining nothing is not a theory.

It follows that the belief that there is an invisible substratum, having explained nothing, is at best a poor theory and may not be a theory at all. Even to say it is weak makes no sense, for it manages to explain nothing. It can’t even be coherently understood.

There is a position in philosophy that there is an invisible world where mathematics exists. This world postulated by philosophers is believed by them to cause the phenomenal world (the world of our experience). However, they do not speculate how this is possible. It is not a theory, but rather a philosophical position without arguments. The only thing that the belief is meant to explain is the philosopher’s inability to resolve the private public quality distinction.

But as if it wasn’t bad enough that the substratum concept failed to explain the phenomenal world it was postulated to explain, it has an even worse problem. The notion of the substratum has added to the body of things to explain its own postulates which it has failed to explain. So while, in the beginning, there was only the visible world to explain, proponents of the substratum have added an invisible one. What is it? Where did it come from? How did it form? How does it work? The philosophers started out with only their experience to explain, and by postulating metaphysical entities to explain it that didn’t wind up doing that they wound up with more and not less to explain. This is working in reverse. There is one postmodern notion that famously takes this problem to its absurd conclusion – string theory. String theory adds and adds and adds entities to explain, but still never winds up explaining the only thing we ever really had to explain – experience.

Not only is materialism not science, but it is poor metaphysics. Of the view that there is an invisible parallel world of mathematics that mysteriously causes our experience – I can't see how to argue with it because I can't see how to even understand it.

The meaning of the opening story of the planet whose priests believe in a magical set of explanations that don’t explain anything, but are beyond repute, should now be obvious.

It’s time now to explain the only system that actually works.

Chapter Seven: The evolution of consciousness

Go back to the stop sign. Remember that we found in it two sets of qualities, those that are the same for everyone that checks them and those that are a little different for each observer.

The traditional way to conceive of this was to postulate that the public qualities were objective (inhered in the object) while the secondary qualities were subjective (inhered in the subject). This created a problem in forcing the theorist to postulate an invisible object. This invisible object wound up being conceived as analogous to the subjective one. This committed the historical fallacy and the theory never really had a chance.

After that the problem arose that this configuration could not really explain anything. That’s because it was wrong.

In actuality, both sets of qualities are subjective. But there is a public subject and a private subject.

Furthermore the private subject (the individual observer) is himself contained in the public subject.

In mystical vocabulary these two subjects are referred to as the individual mind and the Universal mind.

First the inorganic world (as public qualities) evolves in the Universal mind. Then the individual mind evolves in the Universal mind.

Thus you are seeing the public qualities (such as natural laws) from the vantage point of the Universal mind, and the private qualities (such as color and apparent shape) from the vantage point of the individual mind.

First the laws evolve as laws conceptually in the Universal mind. They are mathematical, geometric, i.e. purely conceptual. Out of the laws supervenes the body and organic world (not originally seen as such) and the body evolves by Darwin's laws. Once the body evolves enough to have brain and sense organs the public qualities (such as math) are seen as private qualities (such as color, sound, etc.). The body and brain are thus a medium or lens for converting primary qualities into secondary qualities. The relative location and condition of the body naturally shifts the image slightly and gives it an individual cast.

This so easily explains and accounts for the private and public qualities that it is hard to know what else to say.

Chapter Eight: The cosmology of substance

Note: The word "schema" means a way of organizing something. "Schemata" is simply the plural form of "schema."

Here I'll explain how the historical fallacy can be avoided.

Remember that the historical fallacy is when something found in an effect, brought about as the result of a completed process, is read into the process.

Going over it again – an example of this fallacy being committed would be imagining that the cause of our phenomenal world is much like our phenomenal world. When we fall victim to this fallacy while trying to explain the process that gives rise to our experience, we postulate metaphysical substances analogous to ones found in that very experience we're trying to explain, metaphysical moving objects analogous to ones we see, factors such as time and space analogous to those that condition our experience, etc. This is the primitive thinking that has caused an impasse for science. Once this primitive thinking is transcended, smoke clears and a full understanding of the mechanics of the Universe becomes attainable.

To avoid this error we must take special care not to postulate any metaphysical entities. Rather we must supplant the notion of inventing entities with consideration of an earlier evolutionary process of events and happenings that we already find all around us. By extrapolating a process of what is occurring, from simple to complex, rather than postulating original theoretical entities, we can avoid the errors of the past.

In addition we must not make the prior mistake of making an unfounded metaphysical claim that perception and the thing perceived are separate. By doing this we are inadvertently inventing a parallel world, and this is far too Platonic to work within the rules of science, which only accept what is confirmed by observation.

This does not mean that we assume that objects are in the individual mind – as in solipsism. This is a useless absurdity. Rather we must account both for the objective (public) and subjective (private) aspects of experience. Thus we speak of perception not solely as an individual possession, but as a global indivisible and self-evident occurrence. For no one would deny that perception is occurring. We thus postulate an evolution of this occurrence from simple to complex – and disregard the two-world metaphysics that has been our undoing.

We find that it is possible that the private experience is an outcome of an evolution of the public experience. For this to make sense, the public experience must evolve first.

Starting then at the beginning of this evolution:

Now if there is originally only a single indivisible eternal occurring of perception that sees nothing since there is nothing for it to see but itself, what could change this indivisible eternal occurring of perception in such a way that it would begin to see objects?

It is essential not to add anything to perception. That would just give us something else to explain. Thus we merely postulate 'ways of perceiving.' In the East these ways of seeing are called "sanskaras" and in my book I call them "perceptual schemata," by which I simply mean ways that experience might be organized.

The following is roughly how I explain it in my book:

The first perceptual schema was time. Seeing through and thus in terms of the schema of time (a way of organizing experience temporally) perception occurs temporally. The same is repeated with space. Seeing through and in terms of the schema of space, perception occurs spatially.

Through the schemata of space and time, pure relations (or ratios if it is more helpful) become conceivable to the Universal Mind that is beginning to emerge.

Now notice something: Space can only be understood in terms of time (i.e. through the schema of time) – for you must have here and then here. [In case this isn't understood, you can't conceive of a spatial separation between two objects when those two objects are conceived at the same time. A temporal sequence is necessary to apprehend a physical distance. Try it.] And motion is released as a potential as soon as you have both time and space. And natural laws (ratios of time and space) are conceivable as soon as there is time space and motion. Out of natural laws supervenes (through evolution) the inorganic world, and out of the inorganic world supervenes (through further evolution) the organic world. And in the organic world are forms with sense organs that allow perception to experience the organic world in terms of color, sound, and various other types of sense data. Thus the conceptual becomes tactile.

Notice that the phenomenal world (the complex world of experience) is accounted for without postulating any new metaphysical force or objects. All that is found in this 'story' is found all around us – such as time and natural laws and the self-evident occurrence of perception acting upon our awareness.

But what is accounted for (with less I remind) is far far more. For it accounts not only for the public private distinction, but also for time, space, and natural laws.This is consistent with Meher Baba's Theme of Creation. It is a scientific overlay that incorporates observation, time, space, motion, and natural laws, which are the core of science.Chapter Nine: Gross misunderstandings

Now there are so many implications to this new development. Many of them will be disappointing to people who feel hopeful about the "New Science" that prevails in popular books and science fiction. To explain away certain appealing notions will be as popular as explaining away the JFK assassination as committed by Oswald alone. But at some point it will be necessary for humankind to put away childish things. I doubt I'll be here.

The first is the notion of curved space. This notion is an outcome of the same kind of primitive thinking that produced the material substratum. The idea of "bending something" is a geometric concept. Geometry is a spatial concept. Thus space, which conditions geometry, cannot be bent. Nor can time be traveled or be made to move backward. These are all errors born of imagining space and time as substances analogous to substances found in space and time like water or plastic.There is no "space time fabric of the Universe." That is a childish notion. Laws such as the speed of light are ratios of time and space, and as such cannot be understood in terms of just one or the other. This fact led to a new metaphysical "stuff." Einstein was a genius, but his metaphysics was unsophisticated. Had he understood Kant he might have seen his error. Einstein used his excellent ability for visual fantasy to create a metaphorical model of space and time that wound up working and predicting events in space/time. But he went further and thought this meant that his model was a real metaphysical reality. This led to the false notion that space or "spacetime" can be bent. It is a misunderstanding. Space and time are merely ways of seeing things, not things. When you see through and in terms of the schema of time you see temporally. When you see through and in terms of the schema of space you see spatially.Additionally, things that have wowed and perplexed people for a hundred years are almost banal through this new way of understanding. If you read my book you will see how badly special relativity has been understood.

I'll briefly go over it here.

The speed of sound is 768 miles per hour. But if you are in a jet and a sound wave is chasing you, the wave will "appear" to you to be going slower – and thus the crests of the wave farther apart. Therefore, if you heard the sound from the jet you are in, it would be lower than it would be if you were standing still.

But light is different. Its speed (186,000 miles per second) is the same whether or not you are standing still or moving. To understand how weird this is, I give this little illustration:

Imagine Superman and Lois Lane are on the rooftop of the Daily Planet at night. Lois suggests to Superman that she test his super powers. She suggests she turn on a search light and see if Superman can keep up with the front of the light beam.Superman likes the idea and prepares to lurch into the sky after the beam. Lois flips the light on and Superman goes after it – traveling 186,000 miles per second. Now exactly one second after take-off, let's freeze the frame and see what has happened. It is so weird.

From Superman's point of view (he is traveling the speed of light) he experiences himself as not being able to keep up with the light beam. The front of the light beam appears to him to be 186,000 miles ahead of him – almost like he isn't moving at all. But if he looked back at the Earth he would see it is 186,000 miles behind him. What's going on? Remember, one second has gone by and he is traveling 186,000 miles per second, the speed of light. He should be keeping up with the light beam.From Lois' point of view it's an altogether different story. She sees Superman keeping up with the beam of light – flying right beside the front of the beam. What's happening?Had Albert Einstein, the first to guess that the speed of light was a constant, understood what time is he would not have been very disturbed. But Einstein thought time was something like the lines in his High School geometry book that he treasured all his life. So he fabricated an algorithm for a bendable space – one that bends differently according to the point of view of moving objects. This is where you get the notion of bending spacetime. It is just a misunderstanding of what time and space actually are. The speed of light is a natural law, a ratio of time and space. And both Superman and Lois Lane, along with all other sentient beings, experience the motion of light through the schema of this regular equation. The reason that Lois and Superman both see the light move at the same speed and why the speed of light trumps events in the macro world is that the speed of light is a lens in the Universal mind that precedes Lois and Superman's individual minds and even the world they live in. The laws condition the world of appearances. Appearances do not condition the laws. The paradoxes that this fact about the speed of light creates are only confounding to those who misunderstand the event. So the whole revolution of Einstein that has dominated science fiction and scientism for all these years is based on a gross misunderstanding of the nature of things. Note that the scenario described of Lois and Superman could never actually be experienced in the macro world due to the absurd speeds and distances. In other words, the experiential world is held together by 'good-enough' micromechanics.

Understood through the lens of perceptual evolution, the apparent contortions of special relativity are not particularly paradoxical. They are what one would expect. The system of evolved perceptual schemata actually predicts what Albert Einstein guessed – that the speed of light is the same for all observers. For if the law is in the Universal mind, and precedes the individual, the speed would trump considerations of so-called common sense that evolved to deal more with the surface of daily experience, and not its Universal Divine causes.

The same principle, of considering the place in the process of perception where a law arises, also fully explains away the esoteric scientism of quantum mechanics.

Plagues and Misconceptions

Chapter One: Explaining pure relations

In my book The Evolution of Perception & the Cosmology of Substance I use the term "pure relations" more than once.

I have never explained what I meant.

I write that God (though I deliberately don't use the word God in that book) first conceived the Universe in conceptual mathematical and geometric terms.

This is half right. If we think that God saw these concepts the way we do, we would be committing the historical fallacy, i.e. reading into the cause something that only comes about later.

So when we talk about a ratio of time and space as we find in gravity, we ought not be so silly as to imagine an anthropomorphic God literally thinking about such concepts as time, space and number as we conceive of them.

Rather we must accept that however God conceived of these first relations, that way is now beyond our overly burdened faculties and intuitions. Our faculties and intuitions are burdened by all this sophistication of language. God was not encumbered by that.

So I coined the term "pure relations" to communicate that such relations as God first conceived them were not so conceptually laden as we now experience them. Remember that God conceived such relations before name and form, for name and form arise out of those relations and not the other way around. In a sense the term "pure relation" is a placeholder for what I can't conceive – God's primordial imagination.

But I am never one to avoid explaining the unexplainable.

Once when I was trying to explain pure relations to a philosopher friend, I began to point to things. I said, "Forget the number and that concept, and just look with your eyes."

So here is an example of doing that. Let's say I take a piece of paper and I fold it in half. Now I fold that in thirds. Now I cut that up and overlay it in such and such a way. This creates a geometry after a while, but no numbers or words are used. You just watch me do it, playing around.

Now if you can hold in your head those relations, those ratios and divisions and additions and multiplications that you watched me perform wordlessly – and at the same time remove from your mind the pictures – what you are left with are the pure relations. That of course is impossible.

It is impossible not because it is impossible by some a priori principle, but because your mind is too burdened with assumptions, conditioning, etc. But you must imagine God as unconditioned. His mind is fully free in the beginning of time. So there is nothing to prevent him from doing this.

I point out in my book also that reason will show that it is necessary fact that the laws of nature precede in evolution the things that they condition. So this is not only a theory, it is a necessary fact.

Now of course what arises out of all this is the obvious possibility for sacred geometry. I am not a disciple of this path of interest, but I see what the geometers are getting at. Throughout nature, forms can be reduced to regular shapes and solids. Even sound and light.

I find this story about Meher Baba as a boy interesting in relation to all this about mathematics and geometry in the beginning of time and sacred geometry underlying all things.

Merwan did not like arithmetic and would complain to his father, Sheriar, about his school problem. Although he was intelligent, studying mathematics became a great headache to him and became his first source of unhappiness in life.

One day at the Padamji School during an arithmetic lesson Merwan had an overwhelming experience which he later described: "I saw a great glitter of circles with tiny points in them as if suns, moons and stars were being projected from those points." His teacher noticed that Merwan suddenly looked dazed or dizzy, and as he lost consciousness he fell out of his chair. She rushed to him and laid him on a bench, sprinkling water to revive him. After a while the boy regained consciousness and his teacher asked, "Merwan, are you all right? What happened?"

The boy muttered, "A halo ... I saw a divine halo!"

The teacher could not understand what the child meant and inquired, "Merwan, how do you feel? Would you like to go home?"

"I am all right," the boy replied, "I don't need to go home." But when the teacher resumed her lesson, Merwan sighed with regret, for after enjoying the noor state or the light of God – an experience of divine effulgence – here was this awful arithmetic again. He thought: "It would have been much better if I had gone home."

(Lord Meher, online version, p148)

I have wondered if the arithmetic reminded Merwan of its primordial condition.

In God Speaks Baba speaks of the "form." This is a metaphysical term that first appears as far as I know in translations of Plato.

I suspect that Baba is referring to the geometry and pure relations of the various forms. The reason you taste and smell as you do is said to be conditioned by the shape (geometry) of the atoms. Atoms, unperceived, are geometries in motion.

Baba spoke a lot about the numbers and geometries of the human form. By "perfect form" I think he is speaking of a perfect ratio – not perfect skin texture. Beauty that we see, in music or shape, I think is the outcome of "beautiful" geometries from the point of view of God in a particular state. There have been many signs of this given in nature recently, but they are ignored and misunderstood.

Let no one ignorant of geometry enter here.

Words inscribed above the entrance to Plato's Academy, 387 B.C.

Chapter Two: The Historical Fallacy

The historical fallacy (a fallacy in logical reasoning) is the most significant obstacle to a deep understanding of Meher Baba that I know about. The importance of understanding this fallacy in order to overcome it fully cannot be overemphasized.

Now understand that this historical fallacy is not some esoteric point philosophers know about that has only a fleeting application to the study of the works of Meher Baba. First of all, philosophers don't know about it. Not at Harvard. Not at Cambridge. If you add it to the list of fallacies on Wikipedia, editors will remove it because they've never heard of it and can't understand it. However, once you understand it, you will notice that Baba not only never commits it, but goes out of his way to help his readers not to.

The historical fallacy is when you think that some property that comes about only as the result of a process, can happen earlier than that process.

So let's say there is a process that makes time possible. But you keep talking about the process as if it is something that happens over the course of a year – in time. You're putting the cart before the horse. Or it's more like you're putting the cart before the wheel. That's impossible. You first need the wheel to have a cart.

Now carefully read this quote from Baba.

A whim is not a whim if it can be explained or rationalized. And just as no one may usefully ask why it arises, so no one may ask when it arises. "When" implies a time series with past, present and future. All these are absent in the eternal Beyond. So let us call this initial urge to know a "whim". You may call this an explanation if you like or you may call it an affirmation of its inherent inexplicability. The initial whim is completely independent of reason, intellect, or imagination, all of which are by-products of this whim. (Beams of the Spiritual Panorama p8)

Baba says that the Original Whim made reason and imagination. So how could it be understood or imagined? It can't exist in such terms as time and reason because it preceded them in the process of producing them. It is therefore necessarily independent of these qualities it produces.

First causes are so hard to understand because we are constantly picturing them in the terms of qualities and conditions that they produce. Those qualities don't apply to those first causes because the causes precede those qualities.

One example is the post-modern picture of the Big Bang, which is conceived as an event that produced, time and space, but is simultaneously imagined as having a place in time and space.

The failure or refusal of science to see this point is the cause of all their errors.

Sanskaras are also hard to understand until you overcome the limitation of this fallacy in thinking. Many of the qualities you experience in objects are really only produced in the act of seeing them that way, and don't apply to the perceiver. That is why the world we see can be full of diversity, yet we and God be one. It only sounds like a paradox until you understand the historical fallacy.

The most important implication of this fallacy is in understanding what Baba says about God. God creates the conditions of illusion such as time, space, number, law, reason, and duality. Thus God necessarily does not fall under the influence of these factors. Baba repeats this numerous times. But I have heard Baba lovers really confused by Baba because they haven't gotten this one idea. So they think Baba is being poetic when he says, "You and I are not we, but one." Or they ask questions like "Where is Baba now?" The question of "where" assumes some aspect besides his body was ever "in" space. Baba did and always will precede space. And you create space in the act of seeing it.

Philosophers have so consistently fallen into the trap of this fallacy that I have wondered if it has some special place in Maya. I have even wondered if it is the gatekeeper of gross consciousness.

All schools of philosophical thought fall into it, even Immanuel Kant, who assumed that many aspects of his "intuitions" had to apply to their cause.

    1. Ancients explained the presence of humans of the temporal world by postulating magic other ones called gods in another. They read the effect into the cause.

    2. Atomists explained particles of stuff by postulating smaller particles of stuff called atoms, reading the effect into the cause.

    3. Plato explained things in terms of magic other things just like them called forms, reading the effect into the cause.

    4. Materialism explains stuff we see by postulating a stuff we don't see called matter, reading the effect into the cause.

    5. Scientists explains time and space by postulating a moment in time and space called the Big Bang, reading the effect into the cause.

    6. Scientism explains life on this planet by postulating life on another migrating here, reading the effect into the cause.

The person who originally pointed out the fallacy was John Dewey in 1896, but it has gone ignored. Dewey was an American pragmatist philosopher and educator. I had already guessed the historical fallacy and was having a hard time explaining it to my professors. One day I picked up a book by Dewey, opened it, and there it was. You know how those angels are."a set of considerations which hold good only because a completed process is read into the content of the process which conditions this completed result." (John Dewey, The Reflex Arc Concept in Psychology, 1896)Giving an exampleHere's an example of how to apply this principle to critical thinking. For sake of illustration we'll attempt to come up with a theory of money without committing the historical fallacy. We must do this without using terms and concepts only understood from our experience of using money.

Let us suppose we want to know what money is fundamentally. We want a theory of money. It's not enough to hold up paper that's green. That's not money. Money has value. We have to account for that. The first thing I do is rephrase the question. If I want to know what money is, I have to know how it came into existence. How did it evolve? I'm asking for the process that created money. If I know this process I will know what money is fundamentally, and I'll have my theory of money. So I want to postulate a process by which money could have come about in a culture.

Obviously money has no value if it isn't seen to have value. For instance if I wound up back in the Stone Age, among cavemen, and I offered the cave men some money, they would scratch their heads and walk away.

There is a really good chance those cavemen wouldn't see the green paper in my hands as anything but paper in my hands. To have value, which is the essence of being money, the paper needs to be seen as having value. And it needs to have a special kind of value we could call 'trade-value.'

So the first part of my theory is that money is a symbol or sign (a representation) that people agree to see as standing for something else called "trade-value."

But this theory is incomplete, because monetary trade-value is an assignment we understand from our experience of using money. How, then, could I explain this concept of monetary trade-value to cavemen who have never traded with money before. After all they only value familiar objects they use, not symbolic value. Thinking the concept of trade-value was present in the process of inventing money would commit the historical fallacy. It would be reading something that comes about as the result of the evolution of money into the evolution of money. It would be reading the effect into the cause.

The trick will be to explain the epiphany of money as a way of organizing experience of symbols without telling a story that includes this way of organizing. We must see how the schema came about, not assume the schema was there to form the schema out of. That makes no sense. But that's what philosophers do. We have to not do that.

Okay, I'll attempt to tell a story of an evolution of money that does not commit the historical fallacy.Caveman Bob likes Cavewoman Lisa. Caveman Bob gives Cavewoman Lisa a scrumptious piece of meat to show her his affection. Cavewoman Lisa is really flattered and wants to be sure Caveman Bob knows she likes him too so she can keep getting his little morsels. So she gives Caveman Bob a painted stone. He acts like he likes it, dancing around the fire with it. He's a big flirt.

Now the painted stone has no value except to Caveman Bob. He can't really spend it anywhere. So money hasn't been invented yet, but he associates the stone with her glance when she handed it to him and it begins to stand for her affection for him in his mind. He actually starts liking it and he looks at it sometimes when he's hunting, thinking of Lisa.

The next evening, Caveman Bob gives Lisa another piece of meat. They both smile and the next thing you know Cavewoman Lisa is pregnant and living in a cave with Caveman Bob.

Lisa is trying to get things off the cave floor and is trying to drive a wooden stake into the wall to hang things up. She gets irritated that she hasn't a good stone to bang it in with. She shows her irritation to Bob and he goes looking for a better tool.

Now Caveman Bob sees that Shoonook has a great hammer-stone along with a lot of other tools. Bob tries taking it, but this makes Shoonook mad. To avoid a fight Caveman Bob drops the hammer and goes and curls up nearby to think over the situation. Finally he jumps up, grabs the hammer-stone, and runs into his cave yelling at Lisa. He gets chased by Shoonook. Caveman Bob is really scared but he really wants the hammer. He also wants to stay alive. So he looks around to see if there is anything he can use to persuade Shoonook to go away. He picks up a fur cape he no longer needs but that looks pretty nice and tosses it to the mouth of the cave. Maybe that will make him go away. Shoonook grabs it and runs off. "Tit for tat," goes wordlessly through Shoonook's emotional emotive mind.

But later Shoonook's wife admires his new fur cape. Later Shoonook goes to Caveman Bob's cave smiling and wearing the cape. Caveman Bob is scared but Shoonook keeps coaxing him to come out and starts dancing around in the cape. Caveman Bob covetously snuggles his stolen hammer-stone, thinking he is going to lose it now. But Shoonook keeps smiling. Finally he runs away and returns with his wife and another hammer-stone. He puts it outside the cave door and starts shaking the fur around his neck and pointing to his wife's neck. Finally Lisa gets what Shoonook is communicating. She goes and gets another fur cape for Shoonook's wife. Shoonook and his wife go dancing around and soon the whole clan has discovered "trade."

Now everyone is trading for things they desire and like. Everyone is happy.

Caveman Brown is sitting with his family, playing with his painted stone that his wife gave him long ago. They are very happy. Suddenly he puts two ideas together in his mind. Looking at the stone and thinking of "trade" he suddenly reorganizes his sense data of the stone. He has had an epiphany. "Trade-stone," he says to his wife holding up the stone. "Trade-stone!" Lisa looks curiously at him. He is so delighted he dances a jig. It will be some time before anyone else gets it, but that was the day money was born.Now we are ready to formalize our theory of money.Money manifests out of psychological apperception. Apperception is the process by which new experience is assimilated to and transformed by the residuum of past experience of an individual to form a new whole. Money is a way of looking at a sign or symbol. It occurs when a sign or symbol is looked upon as a representation of trade. This is then codified in a culture through cultural agreement. Money is a way of seeing. Money has no existence outside its being apprehended as such and this apprehension being agreed upon.

Chapter Three: Notes on the Original Whim

There are three ideas I want to get across on this page:

    1. The Original Whim caused time and space.

    2. The Original Whim is not the Big Bang.

    3. God was formless at the moment of the Whim so could not see, but by the urge created the first form through which to see.

Before there can be a meaningful discussion of the Original Whim there needs to be a pretty good understanding of the ordinary human sanskara.

Some people mistakenly think of sanskaras as tiny little things that float around like light orbs and are transferred from person to person like germs.

Sanskaras are really impressions left on the psyche by past experiences and they aren’t things at all. They are psychogenic.

Psy.cho.gen.ic

–adjective Psychology

having origin in the mind or in a mental condition or process

It is always best to use a simple example from everyday life to convey what sanskaras are and what they do.

Every time you do something or every time something happens to you, if you are happy or sad about it, that experience leaves a slight impression on you. That impression then affects how you look upon that kind of experience when it comes up in the future.

For instance, if you eat something and like it – next time you see it you want it. Conversely, if you eat something and it makes you throw up – next time you see it you don’t want it.

Every time you eat in a way that satisfies your hunger, you relieve your hunger but you reinforce your habit of eating. What is happening each time you eat is that you are erasing a sanskara left over by past eating, but replacing it with a new impression of pleasure from eating that will cause you to desire food again in the future when your stomach hurts.

So each experience of pleasure satisfies a latent craving, but establishes another craving in the future.

Each experience of suffering establishes a desire to avoid that experience in the future. Fear attracts the thing feared so that the fear can be overcome. But no sooner do we re-experience the feared thing then a new fear of it is created.

This is how sanskaras work.

It matters not if you do the thing or if you have it done to you or you just watch it happen. What is important is that you experience something happening and it causes you either happiness or sadness. That is what leaves the sanskara (impression) of it on your mind.

Note here a very important point. If you could somehow re-experience the thing desired or feared without feeling happy or sad about it (without having an internal reaction), it would exhaust the past impression and not create a new one. Baba explains this in Infinite Intelligence. Perfect masters have no internal response (because they have no sanskaras) and thus create no new sanskaras in themselves.

It should be obvious now that sanskaras beget sanskaras.

It goes like this and in this order:

    • Action – could be by you or to you, important thing is that it is an event you experience.

    • Impression – pleasure or pain from the action leaves either a positive or negative impression on you about that kind of event you experienced.

    • Desire or Fear – in the future you will either desire or fear that experience depending on your pleasure or pain.

    • Action – sooner or later the desire or fear to repeat or not repeat that experience will prompt you to re-experience it to satisfy that craving for repetition, or to satisfy a desire to overcome the fear.

    • Impression – no sooner is the past impression worked off in the new action, a new impression is left on the mind again of pleasure or pain and the cycle starts over again...

This is what causes evolution and the seemingly endless cycle of births and death called samsara.

Now we are ready to talk about the Original Whim of God.

Maya is the mechanics by which illusion is produced. Sanskaras are really the smallest building block of Maya. Besides reality, there is Maya (the mechanics of illusion) and nothing else. The world doesn’t really exist. It is just a mirage caused by Maya. God’s urge is to find himself. Maya is the method God uses to do that – first by seeing illusions, then by discovering his own reality against the backdrop of illusion. Then illusion vanishes and God experiences only Himself.

Now originally, before there was any of this illusion, there was God. But God was in deep sleep and did not know he existed. He was unconscious.

Baba says that somehow this vacuum state of God was stirred. This complete unconsciousness was interrupted, Baba says, by a desire by God to know himself. Baba says that no cause will ever be found for this first urge or desire. He says it was a whim, which by definition has no cause other than itself.

This Whim had no cause, but it happened. So Baba explains that the Original Whim of God to want to know himself was the “first cause.” This is significant to philosophers for they have never known what the first cause was.

When this Whim happened, there were some unique characteristics that never were to be true again. One is that there was no time. For this reason Baba always refers to this moment as “the beginningless beginning.” If it was just the “beginning” then that would imply a beginning in time, a moment along a time line. But the Whim happened prior to time and caused time to happen. (by "prior" in this instance I mean causally, not temporally)

Now remember that the original Whim was a desire. And remember the order of causation of illusion:

action – sanskara – desire – action, etc.

Note now that this first desire came before any sanskara or action. So there was no sanskara to cause this desire. So there was no reason to have had this desire. Now you see why Baba says it was a whim.

But, as explained, a desire leads to an action.

God was really next to infinitely fine at this point – there wasn’t much to Him in the sense of thought or consciousness. All there was in that instantless instant was this desire. So what ACTION could God in this almost infinitely fine state take?There are two I want to discuss. The first created distinction and time. The second created space.By the very desire to know himself, God formed the first way of seeing. He formed in himself almost unconsciously the notion of otherness, separation, a second. For in the sense of the question “Who?” is latent something outside oneself to be. This sense of distinction is the first schema of experience that we continue to see the world through today. We call it duality. When we perceive, we perceive things as distinct from one another and we look for something other than what we are – distinctly.Now the moment this desire existed and created this notion of otherness, of duality, this way of seeing in divisions, there was implicit in this a second notion of time. For there was instantly in the moment of the Whim a before the Whim and an after the Whim latent in its very happening. This first happening of the Whim thusly divided the past from the future in appearance. "Let there be lights in the expanse of the heavens to separate the day from the night, and let them be for signs and for seasons and for days and years" (Genesis). The Whim did not happen in time. How could it for it gave rise to time. Rather the Whim caused implicitly the impression of time in God. And instantly time became explicit as a way of seeing henceforth from that first momentless moment in the beginningless beginning.

Well, now having plenty of time, God looked around to see what he might be. And of course this act of looking around gave to God the distinct notion that there was somewhere to look – outerness – the notion of there being a there out there. Where was God to look to find this there out there that he felt existed, but in the far off reaches of his dreamt imagination? So, simply the temporal act of looking implicitly gave rise in God's imagination to a sense of space. So it was that this act of seeking had the unintended but fortuitous effect of making space first implicit and then explicit as a way of seeing. And we call this sense of seeing space.

So in the Whim itself there was the emergence of time and space.

This is in the Bible.

And God made the firmament, and divided the waters which were under the firmament from the waters which were above the firmament: and it was so. (Genesis 1:7)

And the next step is in the Bible too. This pleased God.

...God saw all that He had made, and behold, it was very good. (Genesis 1:31)

God took pleasure in what he saw. Now remember once again the order of the process of creation: desire – action – sanskara, etc.

God’s desire to know who he was – the Whim or first desire or first cause – caused in God the impulse to act upon his desire, i.e. to look about. This act effectively caused God to experience pleasure, and this formed in God the first sanskara (impression).

And of course from this first sanskara came the second act of imagination and so forth.

So what we see initially forming in God’s imagination are the schemata for all that He would later come to see, and then take himself to be.

Chapter Four: The Big Bang Misunderstanding

The Original Whim is not the Big Bang. In many ways there was a Big Bang after the Original Whim, but in as many ways this is misunderstood.

Scientists are confused about the Ground Zero event of the Big Bang. They are confused by a fallacy in thinking known as the historical fallacy. This is the error in thinking you make when you imagine the cause of a thing having the characteristics of that thing. It is easiest to understand this fallacy through examples.Example 1: Some tribesmen are sitting around a fire trying to explain where people came from. So they smoke their peace pipes and come up with the idea that magical people (gods) created them. The problem with this explanation is that while the tribesmen only had people to explain before, now they have people and magic people to explain – and they still haven’t explained how the magic people created the regular people except by their magic. Plato called this kind of infinite regress “the third man argument.” It’s a sign of a flaw in thinking.Example 2: Some Greeks are sitting around trying to guess what things are fundamentally composed of. So they come up with the notion of atoms (tinier things). The problem with this is that the Greeks now have their atoms to explain. Are they closer to understanding the first cause?

Example 3: An Enlightenment philosopher hunches over his desk in his attic. A candle flickers beside his inkwell. He is wondering what stuff is made of? So he invents an invisible stuff (matter). Now he has two kinds of stuff to explain.

Each one of these is imagining the cause of a thing to be analogous to (just like) the thing.

Now here is more tricky sense of the historical fallacy.

Example 4: A scientist in the 20th century is at his office contemplating the origin of time and space. He comes up with the idea that there was an explosion – and out of this explosion came with it – along with matter – time and space. He thinks about how this explosion must have expanded outward in space. He estimates at what point in time after the initial explosion the ball of matter, time, and space had reached one inch in diameter.He figures the explosion came out of a point and brought with it its own space and time. But he has imagined this event as if it were in space and time. He even imagines being there holding a tape measure up to it. He is picturing the cause of space like things in space. He is thinking of the cause of time like an event he sees in the world of time.In addition he is imagining all these events as occurring in terms of the relations of time and space (natural laws) that he finds in the phenomenal experience he's trying to explain, without accounting for how these laws came about.

The Original Whim was not an event like this. It was an event that preceded time and space.

Another misunderstanding that scientists have, also due to the historical fallacy, is imagining the earliest stages of inorganic evolution as having the kind of substance that we now conceive things in. They are picturing in their mind images and qualities that only arise much later out of their evolved sense organs.

It was a mathematical conceptual Universe before the sense organs evolved to give that Universe color and density as we experience them. In fact we can't even imagine that world as it was in its primordial state and as it remains unperceived by the individual mind. Even to say it was "mathematical" is incorrect if we imagine that mathematics to be like the one we use; and to say it was conceptual is wrong if by "conceptual" we mean the kind of conception we now have.

Thus all models of the Big Bang ought be understood to be only models for understanding, and not "pictures" of those events.

A more representative model would be like the one I keep pointing to where, instead of things created, what is modeled are the perceptual schemata that evolved in God's imagination by which to experience those objects. For the objects arise out of their being seen, not the other way around as currently supposed.

Really there was a Big Bang of desire, ideas, and perception. It is only in hindsight, through our evolved faculties, that we can now imagine those events as having the kind of substance we experience now. Science will not truly progress into the subject of first causes until it has a strong notion of Maya and the sanskara.

Chapter Five: Do I need a body to see?

This is a question that many people have asked themselves. The answer is 'yes,' but you don't need a body to look, i.e. peer into the inky nothingness.

In the beginning, God had the desire to know himself, which sent him off on a journey (in His imagination) to find what he might be.

This desire did not require a body, nor a cause. It was a whim. And this desire prompted God to look for himself, which was the first action. And this action pleased God and thus caused in God the first sanskara (or impression). And this first sanskara formed the mold for the first gaseous form which was so many levels more subtle than hydrogen Baba tells us. Through the medium of this most subtle first form God saw just a tiny bit, and this experience caused more sanskaras (impressions) and this formed more desires, actions and impressions, and thus more complex forms, and thus more complex images.

Eventually God found himself as a grub crawling along the ground eating mud. One day God woke up and found himself in a world as a person and by then there was so much to see and experience that he was entirely taken in – aware that he existed but ignorant that he was in fact the dreamer of all this around him. He took it as real.

So began the long process of wearing away all the impressions he had gathered in the process of forming the world that gave rise to his self-awareness while retaining his sense of being. When all the impressions had been worn away he was left with himself alone, which really speaking was all that ever had been.

Chapter Six: The Om Point

The Om Point is not a point in space.Even if you knew all the trajectories of all the stars and planets in the expanding Universe and you were to trace those trajectories in reverse to a point in space and a moment in time from which things appear to have Banged out, that would not be the Om Point.The Om Point is a subjective point. Out of this point the Universe oozes from the mind of God.To understand what a subjective point is, look around you at your environment. Then look within you at your thoughts and memories. What is in common between them? That which sees them. And where is this? If you contemplate you can trace it to a spot which feels as if it is between the eyes in the center of the forehead. But what is there at this point if you look in the mirror or take an X-ray? Nothing. Time, space, and your head come out of the point; the point isn't on your head or in time and space. This point is infinitely vast and the world of objects and thoughts is really infinitely finite. But seen through the schemata of time and space the opposite is experienced.

There is a sense in which each person is a Big Bang, a point out of which the Universe that is continuously emerging from God's imagination explodes into appearances. The sense in which this is true is called homeomerity, where parts contain the whole and the whole contains the parts. The example usually given is a tree, whose seeds contain the tree itself. Each soul is in the Over-soul and the Infinite Over-soul is in each soul. In this sense each one is a Big Bang out of which the Original Whim is expressed. Each day, from your point of view, the Universe expands out of you when you wake and contracts back into you when you go to sleep. In the course of lives experienced by a single atma Creation first evolves outward and then involves inward. Like this, from the point of view of the Over-soul (Paramatma) the Universe is projected in Creation and collapses in Mahapralaya. The point from which all three are experienced is the Om Point and is One.

Chapter Seven: The missing argument for materialism

Beware of people who say they hold a position but avoid discussing it with words like "It would take me hours to explain." Tell them you have the time.

To some it may come as a shock, but there is no argument for materialism. There is no defense for it. There isn't even an explanation of what materialism exactly is.

I should know. I did my thesis on materialist arguments against idealism. I had wanted to do my thesis on idealism – namely George Berkeley's idea that there is no such thing as matter but only perception – so I could understand it better. In my first discussion with my thesis adviser I asked, "Everyone seems to know that idealism is wrong, but I seem to have missed what the argument against it is. What is the argument against idealism."

His answer was flat and surprising. "There isn't one really," he began without entirely looking up at me. "Idealism was in favor in the nineteenth century and now materialism is. It's just fashion." I had to think about that and I have to say it still amazes me, even though it turns out to be true.

But he suggested I explore the question, and we decided to call my thesis "Refutations of Idealism."

This required that I study the history of modern materialism beginning with John Locke. For materialist arguments to examine we chose one of materialism's most luminous post-modern proponents, G.E. Moore. We chose Moore because he offered just the kind of argument I was looking for, sharp logic-oriented refutations of idealism. Moore wrote three major essays on the subject.

Then, to assess the success of these refutations, I wrote what one idealist would have said to his charges, George Berkeley. This might at first seem a bit unfair, since it could be argued that Moore was thinking mainly of his contemporaries and not the famous 17th century idealist. But Moore himself said that his arguments refuted "all forms of idealism." So my professor and I were both curious to see what I would discover.

It turned out that Berkeley had anticipated all of Moore's charges and had already written defenses against each of them two hundred years earlier. So this made quite an interesting thesis. I wound up having to say the obvious, that in the end Moore had failed to refute at least one idealist, George Berkeley, who from a western point of view is really the quintessential idealist.

So my thesis passed.

But that was not the end of the story. I later learned much much more on my own.

This whole time I was writing Berkeley's defenses of idealism from attacks by materialists, it had never occurred to me to ask what the defense of materialism was. Berkeley had. He had said there was none, not even an articulation of what it was. But it didn't fully dawn on me at the time quite how significant this is.

It took some time for me to digest just how damaging it really is for materialism that there is not a single logic-bound argument for it. Its only argument is that it is the intuitive view and common sense, which Berkeley correctly shows is nonsense when you see what materialism says. I will get into that further on. Philosophy is not the art of holding beliefs. Both idiots and ideologues can hold beliefs. Philosophy is the art of argument for beliefs. What did Shankara do his whole adult life? He argued against the Buddhists and dvaitas (dualists). He went from debate to debate. He defended his beliefs and refuted those of his opponents. Had he simply written refutations, he would not have been remembered. Any academic can write a refutation.

But let's go back to Moore. Even in Moore's own day he began to realize that his refutations were going nowhere. He kept wanting to think of a defense for materialism – against the idealist notion he found so repugnant – that everything is perception.

One day, near the end of his life and intellectually exhausted, Moore was giving a talk. Trying one last time to explain why idealism (the view that perception is all that is) was wrong and materialism was right, he got so frustrated that he finally just waved his hand angrily in front of his face shouting, "How do I know I have a real hand? Look! There it is!" Waving his hand in the air, his face turning red, the audience began to laugh. For this gesture was the main point of George Berkeley, that what we mean by a hand, a real hand, is the one we see with our eyes. Moore was inadvertently making the argument for idealism.Counter to what most people assume, materialism is not the view that what you see with your eyes is the actual world. Materialists call that view "naive realism." Materialists believe you see a representation (copy of some kind) of the real material hand. So for a materialist you don't see the actual world.Idealists do hold that what we see is the actual world, because for an idealist the only world is the one that is perceived, since the essence of things like tables and chairs (and hands) lies in their being perceived.

In his two main essays on the subject, Principles and Dialogues, George Berkeley shows that materialism doesn't really make any sense when it is examined closely because it isn't clear what the referent (the thing named) of the word "matter" is, or how this mysterious something accounts for experience. He also shows that the only defense of materialism that is continuously given by its progenitors, that it is plain old common sense, is ridiculous. He points out that if you ask any plain old man on the street if he thinks his hand that he sees with his eyes is not his real hand, but a brain-painting of some other hand discussed in a classroom, he will look at you like you're insane. The common sense view, Berkeley points out, is that the hand you see with your own eyes is your actual hand, and that there is no other.

Besides having no logic-committed argument, materialism also suffers from having no clear articulation. For if you ask what matter is materialists can only explain it is the one thing that exists. They can give other names for it such as the substratum. But they can't articulate exactly what they mean by such words. Matter also is impotent to explain our experience. For this reason they don't argue for it. Materialism isn't really a philosophical theory. A theory is an explanation of some observed phenomenon. Materialism can't even explain itself, let alone some phenomena. The only thing that materialism theorizes is that there will one day be a theory to go with the name. I once heard David Chalmers speculate out loud at a symposium on consciousness that his best guess is that materialism will explain experience in one hundred years. So, if materialism isn't a theory, what is it? It's a position not to be an idealist.

But why is it so important to a group of people not to believe something? What does this anxiety stem from?

Berkeley explained, and all the idealists after him have essentially agreed, if everything is perception, even that which no individual perceives such as an empty room no one is in, then it must be upheld by a Universal perceiver. And this demands the existence of God or Spirit. Matter, on the other hand, is said to be inert – blind and lifeless.

So materialism is not a belief in something. It is a group-commitment to create a bulwark against a philosophical belief that demands that God's existence is essential. Berkeley said all of this. I am only repeating what he has said.

That is why materialism defines itself as the belief in matter and nothing else. It is the "nothing else" that is the important part of the position, not the sensibleness of the idea. It is designed not as an explanation, but as a bulwark against explanations.

Sadly, believers in God have forever been defending their belief against attacks from materialists, yet they have been too busy to notice that there is no defense for materialism. And to make matters worse, post-modern Christian apologists have all come on board with the materialists in defense of matter – maybe in hopes of attaining academic credibility. That is why their apologia arguments for God don't really hold up. It is so ironic.

I hardly know what else to add.

Notice you will never see materialism defended in a fair debate. If a materialist debates he will speak in red herrings to divert attention back to his opponent. It is a common ploy in post-modern debates to play rope-a-dope, and sadly it works because the debate monitors are so unintelligent. Never confuse glibness, a fancy suit, and ten shades of cologne for intelligence.

I strongly suggest reading one or the other of the two works on idealism by George Berkeley, Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge or Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous. They are famous, eloquently written, short, and the only works he ever published on the subject. Each covers the exact same material, only Principles is written as a standard essay and Dialogues as a dialogue between two friendly neighbors. Berkeley is said to have been an exceedingly kind man. One contemporary of his wrote that he could find no man who had found a single fault in Berkeley's character, very rare for a philosopher. His philosophical writing, which included developments in the study of visual optics that are still taught in Universities, was all done in his youth by the time he was twenty six. He later became a Bishop. Just before the American Revolution he visited America and lived in Rhode Island with his wife in hopes of starting a boy's school in the America's. When funds were not forthcoming he returned to Ireland. The city in California was named after him, inspired by his Verses on the Prospect of Planting Arts and Learning in America, particularly the final stanza,

Westward the course of empire takes its way; The first four Acts already past, A fifth shall close the Drama with the day; Time's noblest offspring is the last.

Just a little post-note here. I always wanted to write with the kind of clarity that Hume and Berkeley had during The Enlightenment. I have to admit I cannot live up to their lucidity. Still, they say it is good to model greatness. One post-modern materialist, in his search for an argument against Berkeley, wrote that Berkeley's clear and lucid style of writing must be viewed with some suspicion, for it is easy, the author argued, to hide errors in thinking behind clear language. Yet he could not say exactly where these errors in thinking were. How absurd. How much more easy it is to hide mistakes in reasoning in garbled, confusing language. There is no level to which some materialists won't stoop to find a way to disparage Berkeley when they can't refute him logically. One of the most common arguments given that Berkeley must have gotten something wrong, was that he was a big enthusiast for the health benefits of tar water, a New Age pep-drink he had discovered while visiting America. As a matter of fact, a book by Berkeley on the potential benefits of tar water was a best seller in Europe, and the most financially successful book of his life. The argument has been put forward by his contemporary opponents that, since Berkeley was so duped over the alleged benefits of tar water, now known to be a benign beverage, he must have suffered from a rare but acute form of psychosis, and thus all his writing on perception should be viewed with utter skepticism. There is a name for this exact argument. It is called ad hominem circumstantial, and it is a logical fallacy. You are suppose to address the man's arguments, not the man. There is another popular argument that has been used against Berkeley's idealism. It is that what Berkeley is proposing is that when you leave a room, the room disappears. This is very commonly said of Berkeley's position by those who don't understand it well. Berkeley stated he did not hold this view in Principles. There is a name for this argument as well. It is called a straw man argument, attacking a position that the opponent does not really hold, and it is also a logical fallacy.

In fact Berkeley did make two mistakes in his writing. Berkeley died before Immanuel Kant published his Critique of Pure Reason. Had Berkeley lived long enough, it is possible he would have seen his error. It did not occur to Berkeley that the factor of time is also an idea in the mind of God. Had he realized this he might have guessed that the individual minds he conceived of were, ultimately, non-different from God, and that the separation between our minds and God's mind is itself a mere appearance. Berkeley never grasped that duality, caused by the influence of the intuition of time, might be a chimera. The second mistake Berkeley made was to think, like his predecessor John Locke, that number is a primary quality. Actually, it is ratios, not numbers, that are primary qualities. Neither Lock nor Berkeley appeared to recognize this fact. This error led Berkeley to assume that all qualities of experience are relative. While Berkeley correctly pointed out that measurement, as a particular number, is relative, he failed to recognize that natural laws are ratios of variables of time and space and ratios are not relative. Realizing this would have allowed Berkeley to see that there really are primary qualities that are the same for all observers. Had he recognized this, his instinct, I think, would have been to attempt to resolve his system a little differently, by placing individual minds, who see relatively, within the mind of God, who sees objectively. Had he done so it is possible he would have stumbled upon something very close to advaita vedanta. It is also possible that Berkeley knew more than he let on, and that he wrote only what he felt would not offend the church that became his career.

Chapter Eight: Sanskaras

From a metaphysical point of view the most important concept to grasp is the sanskara (Sanskrit for 'impressions' left on the mind by past experiences). Yet nothing is less understood generally.

It is not difficult to grasp what a sanskara is if you are not a materialist.

A sanskara is the smallest unit of your psychology – it's what makes you tick. But it's also what makes the Universe tick.

The best way to begin to understand what sanskaras are is to understand psychological apperception.

In psychology, apperception is "the process by which new experience is assimilated to and transformed by the residuum of past experience of an individual to form a new whole." (Ledger Wood in Runes) In short, it is to perceive new experience through the lens of past experience.

Example: We see a fire (visual perception). By apperception we correlate the appearance of fire with past experiences of being burned. Having combined present and past experience we realize this is a situation in which we should avoid placing our hand in the fire and being burned. (William James in Talks to Teachers)

Apperception is the Western concept that most closely expresses the function of the sanskara. But a sanskara is the actual impression through which we apperceive. The closest English equivalent term is "impression." To understand what we mean by an impression left on our mind by experience that then colors all subsequent experience, we can use the analogy of a pair of rose-colored glasses that color our perceptions when we wear them.

In Discourses, Meher Baba says:

The mental processes are partly dependent upon the immediately given objective situation, and partly dependent upon the functioning of accumulated sanskaras or impressions of previous experience... From the psychogenetic point of view, human actions are based upon the operation of the impressions stored in the mind through previous experience. (Discourses, 1967, Vol. 1, p. 54)

Psy.cho.gen.e.sis

[sahy-kuh-jen-uh-sis]

-noun

the origin of physical or psychological states out of the interplay of conscious and unconscious psychological forces.

So sanskaras are:

the imprints left on the subconscious mind by experience in this or previous lives, which then color all of life, one's nature, responses, states of mind, etc.

impressions derived from past experiences that form desires that influence future responses and behavior (karma).

the faint memories left on your mind by experiences you had in your present life or in past lives. that affect how you look at things in the future and how you will act.

From the point of view of one seeking moksha (liberation from Maya as well as births and deaths) understanding what sanskaras are and are not is useful. Through bhakti (devotion) alone one can avoid the issue of sanskaras as immaterial. But if one is inclined by his temperament to pursue the marga (path) of dnyana (gnosis, or real knowledge), then understanding sanskaras and their effects is imperative.

Real knowledge is attained when all the sanskaras are wiped clean from the mind and the soul is unfettered from all illusions. This attainment is called moksha. Moksha is achieved when all sanskaras are either worn out slowly by time, sloughed off more quickly through yoga (practices), or wiped out in an instant by a perfect master. However, Meher Baba tells us that perfect masters usually wait until a disciple is ripe for this intervention by becoming at least partially purified of ignorance. This means that any work we can do through yoga, the more prepared we will be to receive the final gift of moksha. So even for ones who hold to the avatar, the eternal perfect master, I think yoga is not useless.

Meher Baba explains certain practices for ridding oneself of sanskaras, some which work more quickly than others. In the form that he says works quickest (dnyana) he says that it is necessary to understand what it is you are removing. To perform these practices of renunciation without understanding the process that is being undergone, in other words with confused intentions, will have a reverse effect and produce new impressions. In dnyana marga, understanding what one is accomplishing is part of the action of accomplishment. Otherwise the action is merely mechanical and binding.

Thus, from a strict dnyana point of view, understanding of sanskaras is indispensable.

It is important to understand what sanskaras are not.

Sanskaras are not things analogous to objects in the material world. They do not have location or extension, mass or weight. They are not things. We can talk about them as if they are things, talk about objects like meat that contain sanskaras, but we mustn't misconstrue such language as conveying that sanskaras are actual things.

I will give some examples of how thinking sanskaras are things can be detrimental to their elimination. A person once told me that when people have sex, sanskaras are exchanged through the bodily fluids. The sanskaras, they told me, are in the fluids. If this were true, then one could have sex without exchanging sanskaras simply by using a prophylactic since this would prevent the exchange of fluids. In actuality it is the experience of the sex act that leaves impressions on the mind. In fact it isn't even the experience, but the internal reaction to the experience – of either gladness or sadness. A perfect master could have sex, experience the sex, but imbibe no sanskaras because he is unaffected and unimpressed by the experience. He has no reaction. He has no reaction because he has no sanskaras, but that is another story.

Another idea is that sanskaras are given off from things. If this were true then one could escape new sanskaras by simply isolating himself. To really isolate oneself from sanskaras one would have to isolate from his own awareness, which is impossible when in an awake conscious state.

By understanding that sanskaras are not things, one can see the futility of running from them, creating a physical shield between you and them, etc. One can begin to see that the removal of sanskaras is an 'inside job.'

For the clearest explanation from a true sadguru on the various ways to remove sanskaras quickly, read Infinite Intelligence by Meher Baba. Baba also explains exactly what sanskaras are, using the analogy of glass lenses and also a strip of movie film, the perfect master's relation to them, etc.

Baba explains how each method of yoga accomplishes the removal of sanskaras.

    • Bhakti yoga: The sanskaras are starved through self-forgetfulness in thoughts of the beloved.

    • Karma yoga: The sanskaras are spent through selfless actions that create no new impressions, due to complete detachment.

    • Dnyana yoga: The sanskaras are killed by giving the body the reverse of what it demands.

In one sense, sanskaras are all that is happening around you. In a sense the world is reducible to the action and interaction of sanskaras.

It may surprise some that Meher Baba's main book, God Speaks, does not mention karma even a single time in the body of the text, but mentions sanskaras 39 times and impressions 493 times (not counting the index, glossary, and footnotes).

Sanskaras are the building block of the true metaphysic. They are the producers of illusion, the working part of Maya. Yet they are so simple. All they are is ways of seeing caused by past instances of seeing that were in turn caused by ways of seeing, and so forth all the way back to the fist instance of time perception following the original whim.

The hardest part of getting the new metaphysic is wrapping your mind around the idea that the conditions of experience arise prior to, and cause, the experience they condition. Let me break down what I just said. When we say in philosophy that something is "conditioned" by something else, we mean that it can only exist on the condition that that other thing exists. This is the opposite of how our intuitions are designed to look at things.

I'll give an example. We look at some event and we note that it has a shape. We normally think that the shape is part of the thing. Well it is. But you don't understand why. You aren't really taking the shape from the thing, but rather your mind is using the shape to condition what is shapeless (Divine Effulgence) to take that shape. So the shape actually precedes causally the thing that has the shape. This is peculiar, for we think of the shape as being part and parcel with the object. In Infinite Intelligence Meher Baba gives the example of a strip of film. As each frame of movie film passes between the light source (the projector) and the screen, a correlating image is projected onto the screen. The millions of impressions (sanskaras) that pass through the mind, likened by Baba to film going through a movie projector gate, condition its experience in a substantive way on the screen of its experience.

Yet, and this is what is hard to understand, the sanskaras (film frames in Baba's analogy) are not analogous to the image on the screen. They are finer, more subtle. They are mere impressions left on the mind by past experience. They are the conditions of experience. They condition (form) your experience. The mind encumbered by sanskaras is called the "conditioned mind." When the mind is entirely unconditioned (no film strip) then all that is perceived is what was all along actually there – the Divine Effulgence or Natural Light.

How the Universe evolves by way of sanskaras

I do not think it was a coincidence that not one, but two, movie scenarios commissioned by Meher Baba in the 1930's to express his divine theme, were titled "How it All Happened." One was by the screenwriter Hy Kraft and associates; the other was a broad outline by that name given by Baba that formed the basis for at least three film treatments – one later retitled "A Touch of Maya." This title "how it all happened" is significant because, when explaining things metaphysically, philosophers have always habitually asked the question, "What are things made of?" rather than seek a process as their explanation. This latter question, what are things made of, actually expresses a rarely understood fallacy of thinking – i.e. reading into a process a concept that only comes about as a result of that process.

The Universe comes about by way of process. If we were to state this process most succinctly we would say, what is fine creates what is less fine.

If we take this simple principle – what is fine creates what is less fine – we can extrapolate that this complex dense course gross apparently robust substantive weighty smelly world we perceive is the result of something that is less of all these things, more fine. And if we extrapolate all the way back we come to the most fine thing which is described in endless ways by different mystics through all ages as spirit, divine light, consciousness, the Absolute, God. Through this sort of thinking we can extrapolate back, and the value of this to the mystic is that this furthest first original condition is also the goal of his journey – and not a mere mental curiosity. For Baba tells us the journey through duality is a big loop back to the source – a loop by which we attain consciousness.

I am the alpha and the omega. (Revelation to John 1:8, 21:6, and 22:13)

So in the beginningless beginning (the beginning that is prior to time so has no beginning) there was no such confusion as there is now. But the capacity for experience was there latent. Baba explains that the original whim stirred in God's creative and impulsive imagination – the desire to know himself, who was all there was to know. This first desire (of God to know himself) was the first cause of the first action.

And since there was nothing but God for God to act upon, and since God was formless and eternal, this first action by necessity happened only in God's imagination. And this action was looking to see what there might be to be. And this action created the first impression upon God's imagination, it left a mark. And this mark was time. For in the very instant of the first urge to know, there was latent in that instant, being an instant, an after the urge. And this sensation is called time, and time was then the first condition for all subsequent experience. In other words time was the first sanskara (impression) caused by the first action caused by the first urge or desire – God's urge to know himself – which Baba tells us was a whim and had no cause.

Now pause and take notice. You find time as a factor in all events that you perceive, even to this day. Or, more accurately, your experience of events is conditioned by time. You could not possibly experience any event, that has a before during and after, divorced from time. Time is a necessary condition of the experience of events.

Next, as God peered through the impression of time, he looked into his imagination for himself. And this act of looking or peering into the imagined void for something to be, unintentionally presumed an imagined distance between himself and beyond himself to peer into. This next condition or impression we call space. You encounter space in your experience every day as an apparent quality of that experience, but really it is a condition of your experience and not a quality of it. It is only after the fact of producing experience through the conditioning lens of space that you find space as its apparent quality.

Just as with time in relation to events, there is no possibility of experiencing an object divorced from space (location, shape, and extension). Thus space conditions the experience of objects. But also grasp that space is conditioned by time. Time comes first. Then by looking temporally here, and then there, space is imagined and grasped by God.

Now these conditions of experience (which are the same principle as human sanskaras, but acting in the imagination of the Original state of God), which are left behind by prior experience, then, over the course of Creation, build up the image world like so many glazes in a semi-transparent painting. With each additional glaze, the image grows more dense, more solid, more apparently robust and substantive. It also increases in its complexity. And of course now you find yourself surrounded by quite a convincing holodeck of illusion that you yourself have created in the act of imagining it – all for the purpose of finding out who you really are.

In regard to this analogy of glazes, remember how apperception functions. It is "the process by which new experience is assimilated to and transformed by the residuum of past experience... to form a new whole."

So the placement of sanskaras does not fundamentally begin in the human form or even the animal form or stone form. It truly begins instantly with the first instant of creation.

The Universe comes about by way of process. What is fine creates what is less fine. Fine thinking becomes absorbed in the contents of its thinking, somatizes its thoughts, and becomes less fine thinking. And that is how it all happened – as well as what it is.

This is the sense in my book The Evolution of Perception and the Cosmology of Substance that I say the notion of evolving perceptual schemata is the most simple of all theories. I did not mean that this notion is the easiest to understand at first. Rather what I meant is that it has only a single working part, i.e. the sanskara or perceptual schema, and, as I point out in my book, this isn't even a part in the literal sense of some thing independent of perception and working upon it. Rather it is the condition of perception. The sanskara, then, is the entire secret not only to how the Universe was formed in the Universal mind, in God's imagination, but also how to overcome the entrapment of its allure. Rid yourself of your sanskaras and you have broken the spell of illusion. You are now truly awake.

Chapter Nine: Time

The most confounding problem in philosophy is time. But in reading Baba's writing the problem vanishes as mostly self-created.

How can there be a process (an event such as Creation with a beginning, middle, and potentially an end) if there is no such thing as time in reality?

Realize that the first urge was real but all that apparently came as its result was in imagination including time. Everything but the whim, right up to the moment of moksha (liberation), occurs in imagination only. Thus the journey does not really happen at all. As quoted in God Speaks:

He returns to the door from which he first came out, although in his journey he went from door to door. (Maulana Shabistari, in Gulshan-e-Raz)

But then, how can the original whim happen at all if it had no beginning, has no end, and is eternal and independent of time? In what sense is it an event at all?

Remember what was said about fine creating less fine. Recall also what was said about the historical fallacy. To read into the first cause assumptions and conditions that only come about later as its result – is a gross fallacy. There is absolutely no way around it but to take the perfect master's word for it that there was an original whim. For we are trying to imagine through conditioned mind that which exists without conditions. And that is impossible.

But I am never one to avoid trying to fathom the unfathomable. The way I see it, the original whim is not an event that happened long ago in the way we imagine it, nor an ordinary occurance with a beginning, middle or end. Rather it is eternal and ever happening from the point of view of one state of God consciousness (Beyond State), has yet to happen from another (Beyond Beyond State), and happened long ago from the point of view of the God-realized human being. Even I can't get my mind around what I just said, but I said it.

The beginningless beginning (Meher Baba's phrase) is beginningless precisely because it ontologically precedes the condition of time.

Chapter Ten: What things are made of

We often hear people asking what things are made of. The answer depends on the context. A bicycle bicycle mechanic might say a bicycle is made of machine parts. A metallurgist might say it's made of metal. A chemist might name its atomic numbers.

But sometimes by asking this question we are looking for more than parts and sub-parts, but are looking for an account of things? We want to know what ultimately something is.

Physics attempts to describe objects and events in experience in terms of regular predictable laws.

Engineering attempts to apply these laws in physically useful situations.

But it is metaphysics that attempts to account for experience, along with its laws, time and space, and all its perceived qualities. This accounting is more than a mere description (chemistry or physics) or application (engineering). Metaphysics seeks explanation.

There is a common misconception that metaphysics deals with diaphanous conjectures about invisible substances. That is probably true of real-dumb-metaphysics, and it's equally true of real-dumb-physics. But it's not true of the more sophisticated sort of physics/metaphysics that we're talking about here. We're talking about the things we experience like cups and saucers, forks and spoons, and attempting to account for their presence in our experience without postulating anything that is not experienced.

As soon as one posits theoretical unobservable things as causes, one has delved into real-dumb physics or metaphysics. Examples include unobserved, theoretical, unquantifiable, metaphorical dimensions, strings, and matter. No one ever saw any matter, nor a tenth dimension. These things exist only in the imagination of their creators.

In the kind of metaphysics we're trying to convey, the causes are "observable" and are meant to explain the objects and events in your experience. This may sound a bit startling. I'll explain what I mean.

Let us say that I claim that time is a sanskara, a pair of rose-colored glasses that conditions our experience. Life apperceived through the sanskara of time appears temporal. Now I haven't postulated a new metaphysical thing you can't observe. For, when you look around you, you experience space all about. All we have done is reassign what was already there in our experience unexplained. While before it was an odd factor of our experience of objects and actions, it is now 'understood as' a schema of seeing. Nothing was introduced but an explanation, a reassignment, a greater understanding of what was already present in our experience.

When people begin to try to teach me metaphysics I am always on the lookout for two things. First is the mistake of assuming that the cause of X is just like X. The other is the positing of something they cannot point to and say, "that there is what I'm talking about."

Here is an example:

Some people speak of gravity as if it were an invisible thing. They like to call it a "force," whatever that means. They talk about "pulling" as if this action explains this invisible force. But when I talk about gravity, I pick up a spoon and drop it on the floor and I say, "Did you see that? That's what I mean by gravity!" I don't postulate something extra. Rather I assign that experienced dropping as a regular and predictable and quantifiable law of perception. I pick it up and drop it again to show how regular and predictable it is. I write down the formula that was abstracted by Isaac Newton from the same kind of event to show that it's quantifiable and never changes. It's that simple. Nothing is posited but the explanation – no novel invisible entities or powers to explain it. The cause of the action is moved from an invisible ghost world to your self-evident faculty of experience. Do you see?

Now I'm always talking about my duck-rabbit demonstration of ways of seeing conditioning what we see.If you examine the picture to the right you can see a duck facing left or a rabbit facing right. Those long horizontal things can be the bill of a duck or the ears of a rabbit. But you can't see both animals at the same time. Your perception can shift from one to the other, back and forth. What is changing? Certainly not the picture. Your eyes aren't moving. What is changing is the construct (schema) through which you are organizing the lines in your mind.Now, had you never seen a duck, you could not see the picture as one. So your past conditioning (sanskaras) are required to condition what you see.

Now, what you are seeing happening – this change in what you see just demonstrated – is not some idle conjecture. It is an observable fact. All I am doing is reassigning what this event you observe taking place actually is. I am saying "that" is your sanskaras operating on your perceptions. Do you see?

Now, finally I want to address the title of this section – 'what things are made of.' In science it is said that things are made of atoms and atoms are made of quarks, etc. And this is an infinite regress – meaning it cannot arrive at a conclusion even in principle. It is a lost cause. What things are made of will continually demand another question "and what is that made of?" This will happen so long as we continue to explain a thing in terms of yet another thing. That kind of thinking can't satisfy the mind because it is fraudulent thinking that commits the historical fallacy. It is gross most-dense thinking.

What things are really made of is answered by another question, which is how they came into apparent being? And that answer is an evolution of perception – evolved schemata of perception that condition perception and give rise to perceived substance.Now there is a terrific movie called "The Maltese Falcon." It ends with the line by Humphrey Bogart, in reference to a priceless statuette of a falcon, "It's the stuff dreams are made of." What are dreams made of? If you can answer that you have uncovered what things are, ultimately, made of. Dream-stuff is nothing but the event of dreaming. Dreams have no stuff independent of themselves. They instead produce stuff in the dream. That's what sanskaras are and what they do. They're the stuff dreams are made of.Chapter Eleven: Why multiverses & time travel don't exist

A common modern idea is that there are parallel Universes – by which is meant that parallel with us is another Earth living a different history.

Let me explain the origin of this idea. It has two parts. One is precritical interpretation of calculated events within the field of quantum mechanics. Initiated by Richard Feynman, this thinking makes the error of reading macro intuitions into micro events. Physicists do not understand that quantum events precede these intuitions and are merely the most primordial schemata of experience operating in the back of the Universal mind. They do not occur in space and thus are not analogous to macro events. This is explained in my first book.

The second reason for thinking there are parallel Universes is the post-modern habit of applying modal logic to physics. This is really stupid. Let me explain briefly.

Modal logic is the formalization of possibilities and impossibilities. What can be conceived or imagined by the logician is classified as possible, and what he can't imagine such as a square circle is classified as impossible. So they posit alternate concurrent Universes as possible because they can imagine such a notion. There are two problems with this logic applied to possible worlds. If anything conceivable is possible, then possibility is trivial, and if it is trivial it does not entail anything. So the modal logicians are picking their conclusions based on mere taste – they're just making it up.

The other problem is fatal.

The modal logician is imagining his parallel world. But in the act of imagining it, he is present in that world as its witness. For, to be conceived implies a conceiver. And since the logician is by necessity a part of the world of his experience as its witness, it follows that his imagined world is in this world also. He is only playing games in his imagination and thinks he is doing physics.

Now this idea of parallel worlds got spread far and wide because of science fiction movies. The parallel world is a very useful and picturesque story-telling device. Once people saw it in science fiction television shows, it became commonplace to believe in this fiction as nonfiction.

This is how all these novel science paradoxes (based on gross misunderstandings) get spread to the culture.

But here is the spiritual reason that these parallel worlds not only don't exist, but cannot possibly exist.

The reason there is only one Universe is that there is only one Om Point. And the reason there is only one Om Point is that there is only one God. And the reason there is only One God is that infinity cannot displace itself.

Meher Baba mentions universes often, but does not mean it in the science fiction sense of alternative realities with parallel histories. He means vast fields of space containing vast numbers of galaxies.

If you travel on outward journeys, there are infinitely vast fields in space which contain millions of universes with innumerable suns. There are 18,000 worlds in creation with human habitation. (Meher Baba, Lord Meher, online version, p6143)

People may wonder why I poo poo all these interesting ideas. Am I too unimaginative to accept them? Am I too conservative? Am I a party spoiler? No, I am telling you the truth. People have been grossly fooled by pseudo-science in the Kali Yuga. The true mysteries that Baba speaks of, that the masts experience, are far far more fantastic and impossible to imagine.

The difference is that one is invented in the imagination of gross plane men. And the other is a fact that Baba tells us. Again and again the path requires leaving something behind. There are numerous passages to this effect in the Bible.

When I was a child, I spake as a child, I understood as a child, I thought as a child: but when I became a man, I put away childish things. (1 Corinthians 13:11 )

Remember Lot's wife. (Luke 17:32)

There are 1.5 million Google hits for "parallel universe" and another 1.8 million for "multiverse", its hip new term. No wonder Baba wanted his theme of Creation to be expressed in a mainstream movie. Nothing sells ideas like the movies.

I should add that time travel, also postulated by post-modern physicists and popularized by movies and television shows, is also not possible. Time is a way of seeing. It is not a road you walk down where you can turn around and walk the other way, nor a river that can suddenly move up stream. These analogies are taken from things found in time, and are not applicable to time itself. In truth you yourself are not really in time at all, but only see things temporally due to the schema of time.

Baba confirms that there is no time travel when he says,

The past cannot be changed and has, as a chain of incidents, become petrified; but it continues to mold the present and shape the future of the limited "I." (Life at Its Best, p32)

Chapter Twelve: Certainty

There is an assumption (and we are often mistakenly taught this in High School or college) that if you make a prediction based on a scientific model, and an experiment proves you right, this means the theory you were modeling is proven by the experiment. This famously happened in the case of a star sighting during a solar eclipse that Einstein predicted.

This is false. There can be many models or explanations that predict the same thing.

Prediction, by way of a model, does not prove that the model describes reality as it is. It only proves that it is a working model.

For instance, engineers sometimes use the Ptolemaic model of the solar system – the one where the Sun goes around the Earth – to make correct predictions of solar positions. This does not prove that the Sun goes around the Earth.

In the more subtle case of Einstein's prediction, the fact that the star behind the sun could be seen during a solar eclipse could be explained by bending space, as Einstein thought in his model, or by simply saying that light has a small degree of mass, thus is pulled by the gravitation of the Sun the way satellites use the gravitation of the moon to swing like projectiles into outer space. In other words, no experiment proves any theory. In fact, most philosophers of science agree that experiments are used to test if a theory is wrong, not right. If a theory survives an experiment it survives to be retested another day. Science deals in hypotheses and theories, not reality, in data and not facts. One must never confuse their model with reality.

The notion that a theory is proven by experiment is naive science. Yet I see this method used often to convince people that science has all the answers. This blind faith in prevailing hypotheses may always haunt mankind – causing him to stay rooted in ignorance. It may be that only the individual moves beyond his deep-rooted conventions when he is ready. But sadly, science should know better. The best of what science is comes from its ability to discern empirical data from fact, models from reality, and theory from knowledge. The loss of its spirit of detachment from its ideologies in recent times is really the temporary death of science.

From a purely rational point of view, there is only one thing that we mortals can know with absolute certainty. It is that we see things as we do. When I look out I can say without equivocating that the world shows up for me as it does.

Now anything else I say about it, such as its cause, what others perceive of it, whether it is real or illusion, eternal or ephemeral, are mere theories unless one has the gnosis of the sadguru. As for me I haven't a way to compare the veracity of one theory with another beyond its elegance, simplicity, and completeness. They are all exactly and only merely possible conjectures. The reason is that there is no way to derive anything logically from the nature of your experience. You can't even derive (as Descartes incorrectly thought he had) that there is a witness. For, there might be this experience with no witness, simply happening like a verb. How could you dispute it? By applying some language game?

Descartes wrote, "I think, therefore I am." But he failed to notice that his premise "I think" already assumed his preferred conclusion. So he was only pretending at logic – for had he not pretended he would have had to admit that his logic was impotent without a master or gnosis. When we are honest, even the intuitions upon which logic is founded are suspect. For no matter how complete logic is internally, it has no external justification. So don't let anyone ever try to fool you into thinking that anything is really known by mortals besides that Creation appears to each man as it does. We know nothing, and can know nothing with the conditioned mind. We only experience as we do. And we would have no clue why if not for the clues given to us by the master who asks us to look around and notice this or that and explains things to us.

Only one who has gone beyond the mind can really know anything at all.

So when science tells us what we now know on the cutting edge, laugh. For that is the collapsed science. That is the naive science. It isn't worthy of its name.

Inevitably, we want a science whose objective is the reparation of the heart by turning it away from all else but God. We begin upon that science by examining what it is we are giving up, to see that it is not truth.

Conclusion

Everyone is aware that there is a divide between science and religion. It is worth pointing out that there has never actually been such a divide in mysticism.

Science repulses from the notion of bridging such a divide, believing that it would be abandoning its pure tenets. Actually it abandoned those hundreds of years ago when it began its venture into the ghostly metaphysics of materialism – which hasn't even a wisp of science to it. It is pure fantasy. There are some scientists who have tried though to make small ventures. Science as a Source of Inspiration by Lothar Schäfer is an example. But these scientists lack what only Baba can bring to science – which is a theme and purpose.

Generally, religion is far more open-minded than science is about bridging this divide. Even Pope John Paul II conceded that Darwinian evolution is true – and saw science as rightly outside the domain of religion.

But Baba has brought us some startling new revelations and much to think over. Probably we have seven hundred years at least of thought to do on what he has brought. Certainly there will be innovations soon as a result of his advent, as there were following the life of Muhammad. By some accounts, Meher Baba said that in seven hundred years he will be trained as a master scientist and speak in a language that scientists of the time will understand. I have wondered if it is also our scientists who will have caught up enough to be worth talking to.

About this bridge – I don't see science and spirituality as ever quite merging and being the same thing, but I can see a world in which science grasps the truth of the spirit and where the two are not incommensurable with one another. This new commensurability is likely to spawn that common language Baba talked about.

I hope I have made a start in the direction of that compossibility, and have inspired others to continue the long ascent.

Of course the search for moksha (the heart of mysticism) has to go far beyond such musings. But each tiny step plays its part.