Introduction
Chapter 1: “CrissCrossing Landscapes of Religiosities”
Chapter 1 offers a critical overview of the themes of this book. In the preface to Philosophical Investigations, Wittgenstein remarks on how the approach taken in that book will not follow a uniform structure but instead will “criss-cross in every direction over a wide field of thought” (Philosophical Investigations, Preface). Since this book takes inspiration from Wittgenstein’s remark, exploring philosophical problems about religions that appear in particular discursive contexts in the United States and China, often at the boundaries of cultures, ideologies, religions, forms of secularism, and academic disciplines, the chapter will begin by exploring Wittgenstein’s philosophy and its bearing on diversifying philosophy of religion. First, I detail the philosophical approaches that emerged in Wittgenstein’s mature period, especially from the Investigations, the “Remarks on Frazer’s Golden Bough,” and On Certainty as they pertain to understanding and philosophizing about religions. Reading these texts helps one to see a set of complementary concerns and approaches relating to interpreting linguistic, social, and epistemic practices that Wittgenstein found useful for addressing or otherwise dispelling philosophical confusion. Second, I also briefly introduce the two focal points of the book in diversifying philosophy of religion: Chinese philosophies and religions and the intertwining of racism and religion in the United States, and lastly, I conclude the chapter with some preliminary reflection on the sorts of hermeneutical approaches that may be helpful in clarifying religious diversities.
Chapter 2: “‘Grasping the Difficulty in Its Depth’: Wittgenstein and Globally Engaged Philosophy”
Chapter 2 considers the question of the aptness of Wittgenstein’s philosophy for efforts aimed at diversifying the field. Comparative philosophers sometimes use expressions of Wittgenstein’s (e.g.,“language-games,” “form of life,” and “family resemblance”) in attempts to conceive of the discipline of philosophy in a broad, open, and perhaps global way. These Wittgenstein-inspired approaches indicate an awareness of the importance of cultural and historical diversity for approaching philosophical questions. While some philosophers have taken inspiration from Wittgenstein in embracing contextualism in philosophical hermeneutics, Wittgenstein himself was more instrumental than contextual in his treatment of other philosophers; his focus in his writings was on his own philosophical problems. Does this mean that Wittgensteinian philosophy is a poor resource after all for comparative, cross-cultural, or globally engaged philosophy (i.e., if it is properly Wittgensteinian)? Building upon the methodological concerns of 1, in this chapter I examine the relevance of Wittgenstein to contextually sensitive philosophy through studies of his conceptions of history and culture, his interest in Spengler’s philosophy of history, and recent scholarship by Hans-Johann Glock and Hans Sluga on the place of contextualism in Wittgenstein’s analysis of philosophical problems. Ultimately, this chapter advances the view that there are strong resources in Wittgenstein’s philosophy for those seeking a more globally engaged approach to the field, and philosophy of religion in particular.
Chapter 3: “Wittgenstein and Ascriptions of ‘Religion’”
Chapter 3 considers the relevance of Wittgenstein’s philosophical methods to considering problems relating to the concept of religion. When conducting philosophy of religion in a globally engaged way, the nature and boundaries of the concept of religion itself become a problem for philosophical examination. The last few decades have seen an increasing amount of studies of the history of the term “religion” and how it figures in conceptions of “the secular” and of cultural differences generally. A recurrent theme in these studies is that “religion” carries associations with Protestant Christianity and thus is not as universal a category as it might appear. The aim of this chapter is to use Wittgenstein’s contextually sensitive philosophy to obtain greater clarity about the contexts of ascription of religion status to various phenomena and thus to gain perspective on claims made by scholars who investigate the genealogy of the term. While there is good reason to be circumspect about uncritical use of the term “religion” (no less in philosophizing about religions or conducting interreligious dialogue), I argue that instead of abandoning the term or proffering a critical theory of religion, investigation of ascriptions of religion will help philosophers to perceive more clearly the social dynamics that have led to someone or thing being called religious and thus avoid equivocations that could obstruct the ends of philosophical inquiry or dialogue. This in turn sets the stage for the philosophical study of diverse religious phenomena—from beliefs to practices, institutions, and varied modes of religious belonging—a topic that will be the major focus of the following chapters.
Chapter 4: “The Problem of Evil in Critical and Comparative Philosophy of Religion”
Chapter 4 applies the contextually sensitive philosophical approach developed in the previous chapters to consider what is at stake in two recent uses of the problem of evil in expanding philosophy of religion. In particular, this chapter examines the work of Franklin Perkins in comparative exploration of problems of evil in classical Chinese philosophy (especially in Confucian and Daoist texts) and of Biko Mandela Gray in hermeneutically using the problem to critique narratives used to justify police violence against Black Americans. Approaching these cases with an eye to contexts of argumentation shows how the concept of family resemblances is helpful for making sense of the radically different philosophical projects across the broad field of philosophy. Rather than seeing these cases as varied forms of a common problem of evil, this chapter argues instead that the hermeneutical concerns animating both Perkins’s and Gray’s respective philosophical projects serve to remind philosophers generally of the value of metalevel attention to one’s own and others’ local contexts and existential purposes in doing philosophy of religion.
Chapter 5: “Epistemology and Acknowledging Religious Differences”
Chapter 5 considers whether or to what extent Duncan Pritchard’s approach to hinge epistemology of religion is helpful for thinking about religious epistemology more broadly (i.e., beyond Christianity). Pritchard has for nearly two decades been developing and defending “Wittgensteinian quasi-fideism,” a view built from Wittgenstein’s views on the nature of religious belief. Drawing on ideas from Wittgenstein’s On Certainty, Pritchard’s view is that religious beliefs, such as “God exists,” are hinge propositions, commitments to ways of seeing and knowing the world, not propositional attitudes about the world that are justified by evidence. This chapter argues that Pritchard’s quasi-fideism, while fitting for some forms of Christian thought and reasonable as a partial interpretation of On Certainty, overlooks the variety of ways in which Wittgenstein writes about certainties and religious beliefs; the ultimate aim of the chapter is to develop a Wittgensteinian approach to the epistemology of religions that registers the different epistemic dynamics in play among diverse religious traditions. The first part of this chapter critically examines Pritchard’s views on interpreting Wittgenstein on religious belief and the development of the notion of quasi-fideism. In order to discern the different ways in which Wittgenstein’s philosophy approaches the dynamics of religious beliefs, the second part of the chapter considers Wittgenstein’s remarks on “hinges” and “grounds” in On Certainty. The third part of this chapter explores whether a hinge epistemology of religions could address a wide variety of ways in which beliefs operate within diverse religious traditions, including both theistic traditions such as Christianity and nontheistic traditions like Buddhism. Depending on social context and historical tradition, religious beliefs may be in some cases susceptible to revision based on inquiry, evidence, or experience and in other cases hardened against revision.
Chapter 6: “Chinese Religious Diversities and Philosophy of Religion”
Chapter 6 provides a case study on Wittgensteinian approaches to diversifying philosophy of religion through inquiry into forms of religious engagement in China. Drawing inspiration from Wittgenstein’s “Remarks on Frazer’s Golden Bough,” this chapter identifies five themes relevant to globally engaged philosophy of religion that appear when paying close attention to Chinese religious diversities: the significance of the reception and use of concepts of religion; the plurality of ways that religiosities may at times be combined, the pragmatic ways that people may adopt religious practices, beliefs, and values; the plausible combination of avowed atheism with nontheistic religious ideas and practices; and the impact of state power over social manifestations of religions as well as what may even be classified as a religion. Attention to these diversities will help philosophers avoid confusion based on unwarranted generalizations about what religiosity must be and contribute to opening scholars’ imaginations to the wide range of human possibilities when it comes to religiosities and potentially generate new insights on similar phenomena in other social contexts.
Chapter 7: “Baldwin and Wittgenstein on White Supremacism and Religion”
Chapter 7 turns our attention to ethical and existential problems relating to the entanglement of racism and religion in American society. Approaching hinge epistemology with an eye to religious diversities has the added benefit of allowing for fresh insight into philosophical problems less frequently studied; one such problem is the interconnection between racism and local forms of religion in the United States. The ongoing resilience of white supremacism in the United States and its ambiguous relationship to religious traditions is a vexing problem for those committed to egalitarian ethics and pluralist democratic society. To shed light on this problem, this chapter contends that James Baldwin’s exploration of racism and religion in The Fire Next Time may be put into constructive conversation with Wittgenstein’s consideration of fundamental epistemic commitments in On Certainty. Out of this engagement, I argue that white supremacism in the United States may be interpreted as being like a Wittgensteinian grounding or “hinge” commitment and that this viewpoint illuminates some of the ways in which white supremacism may interact with various kinds of religious commitments. This chapter develops further the previous chapter’s insights into religiously diverse hinge epistemology in order to perceive some of the ways in which racist grounding commitments can become intertwined with forms of religious commitment. This combined analysis putting Baldwin and Wittgenstein into constructive conversation depicts the extent to which fundamental commitments about race affect people deeply, including the formation of their ethical and civic values, existential and religious commitments, and range of empathetic capacity. Furthermore, the chapter also details similarities between Baldwin and Wittgenstein when it comes to their contentions that there is ethical value in the clarification of language and work on oneself.
Chapter 8: “Religious Diversities, Racism, and the Ethics of Clarification”
Chapter 8 offers a critical retrospective view of the book and the four themes that have animated the previous chapters. A central contention of this book is that Wittgenstein’s approach to philosophical problems and to thinking about religions can contribute constructively but also critically to work aimed at diversifying the field. This chapter offers a critical overview of the themes the previous chapters have explored in connection with diverse forms of religion, the work of clarification, and philosophy of religion and then puts this work in conversation with some contemporary approaches aimed at expanding the range and nature of philosophy of religion. In particular, the chapter emphasizes that attention to religious diversities includes consideration of (1) the discursive contexts of terms like “religion,” (2) various religious phenomena, (3) the importance of social contexts, including forms of power within those contexts, for understanding the formation of religiosities, and (4) ethical aspects of clarificatory work itself in philosophy of religion (in terms of work on oneself and within one’s communities). Ultimately, the chapter considers the extent to which Wittgensteinian clarification of religious diversities and self-reflexive introspection is commensurate with contemporary research on hermeneutical justice. While Wittgenstein’s ethic of clarification reveals elements of epistemic and hermeneutical injustice, its aim is not to develop one overarching ethical point of view when it comes to philosophy of religion but rather to develop practices of self-reflexive local clarification.
Conclusion