The Abstracts

Elmar Unnsteinsson

Desire, Belief, and Representation

Ruth Millikan has argued that the representational content of desire can be reduced and naturalized by saying, roughly, that the biological function of a desire is its own satisfaction. Some theorists have worried that this is circular, because the desire’s function then seems to presuppose a prior account of representational content. I argue that Millikan’s view can be developed in a way that fully takes care of the worry. Basically, desires are dumb, and the only content they have as such is that they aim at their own termination. However, the organism’s representational system will assign more sophisticated contents to individual dumb desires. Thus we arrive at smart desires - dumb desires combined with representations - which are easily explained by broadly biological considerations. Representations increase the effectiveness and efficiency of the organism’s attempts to achieve desire-satisfaction, especially relative to the vast network of dumb desires it carries over extended periods. This new account of desire has many advantages. For example, it explains the fundamental difference between belief and desire, makes a teleofunctionalist theory of representation more palatable, and helps to separate the representational properties of a state from its functional properties. 

 

Joey Pollock

Testimonial Pessimism

It is typically assumed that we gain a great deal of knowledge through the speech of others. However, an increasing number of views of communication in philosophy of language appear to entail varying degrees of testimonial pessimism. Pessimistic and sceptical consequences have traditionally been seen as compelling reasons to reject the views that entail them. In this talk, I offer an account of knowledge communication that embraces testimonial pessimism: we get much less knowledge through testimony than is popularly thought. I argue that, although this view offers quite a different picture of the role of testimony in our epistemic ecology, it nonetheless coheres well with certain plausible theses about the nature and value of knowledge, and with contemporary work on the nature of communication.

 

Henry Schiller

The Meaning of 'Wants' in a Theory of Rational Planning



What role do desires play in a representational theory of thought? Desire ascriptions are often used in explanations and justifications of behavior. In rational creatures like us, these ascriptions are supposed to correspond to internal representations that figure into the inferences that drive behavior. My argument is that desires get their representational contents from characterizations of the conditions in which a desire is satisfied. These characterizations have mind-to-world (belief-like) direction of fit. On the account of satisfaction that I endorse, desires are satisfied when certain mental states of wanting are brought to an end. I show how this account has implications for solving various puzzles about the communicative function of attitude verbs.



Ishani Maitra

Lying, intending, and deceiving

Traditionally, lying has been understood to involve an intention to deceive. There is a long history, going all the way back to Augustine, that characterizes lying this way. More recently, however, a series of examples have been proposed to show that lying involves no such intention. In response to these examples, many theorists have moved away from the intent-to-deceive tradition. In this paper, I argue that this is a mistake, in part because it leaves us unable to explain some moral features of lying. I focus on two kinds of purported counter-example to the intent-to-deceive tradition, and make three claims about these disputed cases. First, I argue that much of the evidence offered to establish the absence of an intent-to-deceive in fact doesn’t show this at all. Second, I draw on a more deflationary account of intention to argue that in some of these disputed cases there is an intent-to-deceive after all. Third, I look at some contemporary characterizations of lying, and argue that they are committed to implausible conclusions unless they also tacitly appeal to an intent-to-deceive. I draw some general conclusions from this discussion, both for lying and for other speech acts.

 

Eric Funkhouser

Mindshaping for Belief Signaling 

We are incentivized to have some beliefs because of what they communicate to others and the manipulations that they thereby induce. I have argued that, in virtue of having this communicative function, such beliefs are literally signals. Prominent among these are beliefs that function as signals of group identity and commitment (e.g., political or religious beliefs). In addition to having incentives to acquire such belief signals for ourselves, third-parties (e.g., family or in-group members) are often incentivized to mindshape us so that we acquire beliefs that communicate our group identities and commitments. This can be because they are invested in our social flourishing or otherwise benefit from us advertising our group commitments (e.g., we add to the group numbers or help maintain the signaling system). I will explain the purpose and form of such mindshaping, which is a special case of imposed self-deception. 



 

Ethan Nowak

Speech and the significance of style



The analytic philosophy of language is built around the idea that a speaker’s fundamental goal is to encode some information, a listener’s goal is to recover it, and a theory of language is successful if it can explain the exchange. Despite many successes, this conception obscures a point that is a central focus of research on language in other disciplines: how we speak is often at least as important as what we say. 

My aim in this paper will be to show how deep this platitude goes. First, I will argue that the best way to understand the style of our speech is to see it as a tool we use not to send messages, but to perform actions. Making sense of these actions, however, requires viewing one other as agents motivated by moral, aesthetic, and social reasons than are not ordinarily countenanced in the philosophy of language. Drawing on some comparisons with Confucian philosophy, I will argue that these reasons end up permeating nearly any conversation we have, which means that deep moral questions are ever present.



 

Daniel Harris  (co-authored with Elmar Unnsteinsson)

Genre and Conversation

There are many different genres of human conversation. But there is no consensus on how to explain and describe these genres. Thus, many have assumed that all conversation is really a form of joint inquiry, or elimination of possibilities. Others tend to give long lists without any principled way to distinguish, say, storytelling from negotiation, or adversarial conversation from conciliatory ones. We propose and develop a new theory. In our view, genres are constituted by specific relations between the plans and intentions of participants. We apply Bratman's work on joint intentional activity to Grice's influential treatment of conversation as having an accepted purpose or direction. More specifically, we propose that genres are easily recognisable packages of shared plans, which help to explain the characteristic balance of a conversation: shared assumptions about shared plans make speech production and interpretation more efficient and effortless. We also distinguish cognitively basic genres from more local and cultural practices, which are often studied by sociolinguists, and argue that they are universal to the normal structure of human pragmatic competence.


 

Eleonore Neufeld

Generic statements ("Tigers have stripes") are pervasive and early-emerging modes of generalization with a distinctive linguistic profile. Previous experimental work found that generics display a unique asymmetry between their acceptance conditions and the implications that are typically drawn from them. This paper presents evidence against the hypothesis that generics display a unique asymmetry. Correcting for two important limitations of previous designs, we found a generalized asymmetry effect across generics, various kinds of explicitly quantified statements ("most", "some", "typically", "usually"), and variations in types of predicated properties. We discuss implications of these results for our understanding of the source of asymmetry effects and whether and in which ways these effects might introduce biased beliefs into social networks.

 

Thom Scott-Phillips

Great Ape Interaction: Ladyginian But Not Gricean

Non-human great apes inform one another in ways that can seem very human-like. Especially in the gestural domain, their behavior exhibits many similarities with human communication, meeting widely used empirical criteria for intentionality. At the same time, great ape gesture does not appear to exhibit the same open-ended richness of human communication. How to account for these similarities and differences in a unified way remains a major challenge. Here we make a key distinction between the expression of intentions (Ladyginian) and the expression of specifically informative intentions (Gricean), and we situate this distinction within a ‘special case of’ framework for classifying different modes of attention manipulation. We reinterpret video footage of great ape gesture as Ladyginian, and we describe how the attested tendencies of great ape interaction— to be dyadic rather than triadic, to be about the here-and-now rather than ‘displaced’, to have a high degree of iconicity, and so on — are products of its Ladyginian but not Gricean character. We distinguish several varieties of meaning that are cognitively continuous with one another, and we conclude that the evolutionary origins of meaning lie in gradual shifts in what modes of attention manipulation is enabled by a species’ cognitive phenotype: first Ladyginian and in turn Gricean. The second of these shifts rendered humans, and only humans, language-ready 

Sam Berstler

Higher-Order Deniability

This paper introduces higher-order deniability as a state speakers strategically aim to create. A speaker who aims to create higher-order deniability for her communicative act of G-ing has a tripartite intention.  She intends: (i) that her interlocutor know that she G-ed; (ii) that she herself not know whether (i); and that (iii) her interlocutor know that (ii).  Such a speaker is paradigmatically cooperative.  In part by creating a form of deniability for her interlocutor, the speaker aims to help both her interlocutor and herself “save face.”  This analysis shifts the dominant philosophical paradigm for investigating deniability, on which only selfish, underhanded, or manipulative speakers intentionally creating uncertainty about they mean.  It also falsifies several popular assumptions about the relationship between meaning and common knowledge.  This shows that the study of conversational “face-saving” directly bears on foundational debates in the philosophy of language.



Paula Rubio-Fernandez

The Cognitive Trinity of Common Ground

Human communication is built around interlocutors’ common ground (CG), or the information they assume to share. Despite having been the focus of intense interdisciplinary research for more than 60 years, we do not yet understand how CG works, or even what exactly it is. In this talk I will introduce a new research program that is essential to understanding CG: I propose to study CG as a product of cultural evolution. This approach requires identifying (i) those cognitive capacities that are required for the emergence of CG in human cognition, and (ii) how those capacities interact in (a) the development of CG through children’s social learning across cultures; (b) its formation through social interaction across the lifespan, and (c) its management in conversation across languages. I hypothesize that forming and using CG is a complex human ability that emerges from the interaction of three cognitive capacities — joint attention, joint memory, and the use of reference systems — under a rationality principle. This is what I call the Cognitive Trinity of Common Ground.