A Brief Critique of Theological Fatalism

CRITICS OF THEISM, along with some theists, often claim that divine foreknowledge contradicts human free will. “Since God already knew what actions you were going to take,” they argue, “it follows necessarily that you had no choice but to take those same actions.” Basically, the argument for theological fatalism[1] holds God’s knowledge to be the ultimate causal agent of all future outcomes, hence the ultimate metaphysical outworking of the pragmatic principle that “knowledge is power.” It is my belief that properly understood, knowledge comprehends true states of affairs, but does not and cannot create them. (To put it another way: Even if God personally dictated our future, he would have to do so by means other than mere knowledge of our future.) There is accordingly no sound reason to believe that God’s prior knowledge of human decisions freely rendered should not represent a true state of affairs.

At stake here is much more than academic philosophy or theology. For Christian theists the issue of fatalism lies at the heart of our faith, for if the God we believe in is righteous, he will presumably only hold us accountable for decisions we make. As Davis and Manis state the problem, "If divine foreknowledge undermines human freedom, then it seems to follow that God is unjust in holding us responsible for our actions."[2] Like the argument from evil, the argument for fatalism seems designed to get humans "off the hook" for our behavior and to put God on the hook instead.

Zagzebski describes theological fatalism as "the thesis that infallible foreknowledge of a human act makes the act necessary and hence unfree. If there is a being who knows the entire future infallibly, then no human act is free."[3] There is certainly some intuitive appeal to this claim. Indeed, at a glance it appears obvious, if not entirely beyond dispute. Davis and Manis suggest, for example, that if God knew from all eternity past that Smith will call his wife tomorrow at noon then clearly Smith has no choice but to make that call. "God's foreknowledge is infallibleit cannot possibly be mistakenso there is no chance that Smith will falsify God's past beliefs about him when he acts tomorrow."[4]

My contention is that this appeal to the necessary "rightness" of God's foreknowledge of events blurs the distinction between logical necessity and metaphysical causality. It is admittedly logically necessary that if God has perfect foreknowledge, he knows the outcomes of all future decisions. But the question is: Does God's knowledge determine the outcome, or is the outcome instead a passive source of God's knowledge? Experience suggests the latter. After all, I know that you are reading this right now, but I also know that I am not a deity myself, and therefore I know that I did not cause you to read anything at all.

Consider the following set of scenarios:

1. At 8:15 Harold will be free to order anything on the menu.

2. God has infallible foreknowledge.

3. God infallibly foreknew that at 8:15 Harold would be free to order anything on the menu.

This first scenario suggests that God's perfect foreknowledge does not necessarily restrict free will, at least not with respect to a decision not yet made. In other words, it's a possible scenario. After all, the argument from fatalism specifically says that God's prior knowledge of a choice actually made must negate the free will to make any other choice. But on that argument there is no reason to think that free will should not be operative before any choice has actually been made. That is, even under the premises of fatalism foreknowledge does not negate free will to at least deliberate, i.e., to think over a choice. What then of God's prior knowledge of Harold's actualized decisions? Let's fast-forward fifteen minutes:

1. At 8:30 Harold will order a cheese omelet.[5]

2. God has infallible foreknowledge.

3. God infallibly foreknew that at 8:30 Harold would order a cheese omelet.

Again we have a possible scenario. But now the question presents itself, whether the free will Harold potentially enjoyed in the first scenario might have remained operative through the point of making a decision in scenario two. From scenario one it seems at least arguable that Harold will be free to order anything from the menu, but (it seems) only up to the point that he will have already ordered a cheese omelet. Free will after that point admittedly will have been forfeited with respect to that particular decision. So:

1. At 8:31 Harold will no longer be free to not order a cheese omelet, because he will have already ordered one.

2. God has infallible foreknowledge.

3. God infallibly foreknew that at 8:31 Harold would no longer be free to not order a cheese omelet, having already ordered one.

Free will with respect to Harold's decision thus becomes forfeited just at the point of Harold's having already made that decision. On the face of it, though, there is nothing in the forfeiture of Harold's free will with respect to a decision already made that would additionally preclude his free will prior to making the decision. All this would seem to yield the general conclusion: God's foreknowledge does not necessarily contradict human free will. Or alternatively: Theological fatalism is false. Once due attention is paid to the respective definitions and functions of free will and omniscience, the two are seen to be in harmony. Free will remains unrestricted in making decisions which result in unchangeable outcomes, and divine foreknowledge remains infallibly knowledgeable of everything knowable. In Harold's case what negates his freedom to not order a cheese omelet is precisely his prior act of having freely ordered one. There is no contradiction here, only a description of two states of being at two different times relative to the decison made. As Zagzebski suggests, “The necessity of the past and the contingency of the future are two sides of the same coin.”[6]

The curious part about all this is God's knowledge of human freedom to make a decision whose outcome God alone knows in advance. But in principle human freedom is a knowable state, and God’s knowledge necessarily corresponds exactly with any given knowable state. In the state of human free will prior to a decision event the decision outcome is less than certain for a human decider; God’s knowledge of that state remains certain, as does his knowledge of the future state of restricted freedom created by the decision outcome. God’s knowledge of both states does not make his knowledge contradictory, but complete and comprehensive. This is precisely the sort of knowledge an omniscient God would be expected to have.

Again, the question is not whether a choice, once made, results in an outcome which cannot be changed. Decisions result in certain outcomes, quite regardless of whether an omniscient being exists or not. The question is whether a choice whose certain outcome also happens to be known by an all-knowing entity could have been freely made. There is no a priori reason to think that knowledge of another's behavior determines that behavior; the behavior, rather, is the source of the knowledge. So, an external agent’s prior knowledge would have no bearing upon the fact that decisions already made are unchangeable. To see that this is so, let’s revisit our breakfast with Harold and this time assume there is no God:

1. There is no God.

2. At 8:15 Harold will be free to order anything on the menu.

3. At 8:30 Harold will order a cheese omelet.

4. At 8:31 Harold will no longer be free to not order a cheese omelet, because he will have already ordered one.

Even with no God in existence, Harold remains just as free to order a cheese omelet at 8:15, and just as unable to not order one at 8:31. Harold's inability to not order one has, in a sense, been predeterminednot by God, who in this scenario does not existbut by his prior decision. Therefore whether God exists or not, every possible future is “predetermined” and free will does not operate, at least not with respect to prior decisions. Nonetheless, it remains logically possible that we are free to make decisions up to the point that we actually make them, just as we will be free to make new decisions in the future.

Now let’s add an omniscient God back into the mix. God knows with absolute certainty or perfect knowledge that Harold will order a cheese omelet at 8:30, and that afterward he cannot choose otherwise. But how exactly does the additional fact of God knowing exactly what Harold will decide entail a necessary violation of Harold's free will in actually making the decision? We have just seen that without God’s or anyone else’s knowledge of it, Harold's inability to not order a cheese omelet after ordering one would be just as certain. God’s knowledge of the future, then, would not make it any more certain than it would be without his knowledge.

If it is the case that a decision event involves free will in the consideration of choices at some given point in time, resulting in an irreversible outcome that holds at all points future to it, then in principle an omniscient being knowledgeable of all points along the timeline of all events would know not only of the element of free will inherent in the process of making decisions, but of the unchangeable outcomes that result from those decisions. There would be nothing contradictory or illogical in this.

_____________

[1] This essay was previously entitled, "A Brief Defense of Theological Compatibilism," and was meant originally, as it is meant now, to defend the compatibility of divine foreknowledge with human free will. But it turns out that more philosophers than not would say that "compatibilism" proper refers to the compatibility of free will with determinism rather than with omniscience or foreknowledgein which case this writing would perhaps appear to be a defense of Calvinism. I am decidedly not a Calvinist (more of an Arminian really), so I have retitled it to reflect my anti-fatalistic purpose. As a practicing apologist but not a professional philosopher, I have come to see that there are various compatibilisms. I am hoping for clarity's sake that there are at least fewer fatalisms; there cannot, after all, be many degrees of "none" when it comes to free will.

[2] C. Stephen Davis and R. Zachary Manis, Philosophy of Religion. 2nd ed. Downer's Grove, Illinois: Intervarsity, p. 45.

[3] Linda Zagzebski, ed. E.N. Zalta, “Foreknowledge and Free Will,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2011, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/free-will-foreknowledge/.

[4] Davis and Manis, Philosophy of Religion, p. 45.

[5] After pretty much completing a substantive revision of this article referencing my real-life friend Harold, who really does enjoy cheese omelets for breakfast, I did a quick search for "theological fatalism" and came across a blog posting responding to an argument for fatalism by William Hasker. It turns out that in Hasker's version, the first premise is "It is now true that Clarence will have a cheese omelet for breakfast tomorrow (Premise)," and goes on from there. See http://ochuk.wordpress.com/2012/02/16/a-response-to-theological-fatalism/. The common "cheese omelet" element in my argument and Hasker's is purely coincidental...unless of course God preordained it.

[6] Zagzebski, "Foreknowledge and Free Will."

Transcending Proof - Home