My Views

“An action is something that is in the agent’s power, and is chosen as a means to the agent’s end (G 4:427). Looked at from this standpoint, it is the end that supplies the reason for every action. But…there must be a reason for setting the end. The end [must be] good or valuable in some way; …or it [must be] an end that morality requires you to have…. So instead of saying only that the end is the reason for the action, it is more appropriate to say that the reason for setting the end is the reason for the action.” --A. W. Wood, "How a Kantian Decides What to Do," p. 266
“C [that is, consequentialism] holds that the function of a theory of value is to specify our aims, and the function of a theory of practical reason is to specify how to achieve them…. In other words, consequentialism specifies our rational aims, and then tells us to adopt whatever intentions will best bring about those aims.” --E. Anderson, "Reasons, Attitudes, and Values: Replies to Sturgeon and Piper," p. 539
"Given that for a person to act just is for the world to go in a way that it otherwise would not go, surely the question whether he ought to act had better turn on a comparison between how it will go if he acts and how it will go if he does something else—to repeat, there seems to be nothing else for it to turn on." --J. J. Thomson, Goodness and Advice, p. 8.
"All action is for the sake of some end; and rules of action, it seems natural to suppose, must take their whole character and color from the end to which they are subservient. When we engage in a pursuit, a clear and precise conception of what we are pursuing would seem to be the first thing we need." --J. S. Mill, Utilitarianism, chap. 1
“An end is an object of the free faculty of choice [i.e., the free Willkür], the representation of which determines it to action, whereby [the end] is brought about. Every action, thus, has its end." --I. Kant, Metaphysics of Morals, 6:384–385
"It is more important that our theory fit the facts than that it be simple." --W. D. Ross, The Right and the Good, p. 19

Below, I list some of my more important philosophical views and cite the works in which I discuss them. Although I risk coming off as pretentious, I do this for two main reasons. First, this list helps me keep consistent. For many years, I’ve tried to develop a coherent picture of morality, practical reasons, and the relations between the two. And I’ve found that keeping a list of all my positions has been helpful in making sure everything fits together within a coherent whole. 

Second (and this is why I’m making this public), I think that this list will help readers make sense of my views. Making sense of my views has proven difficult, as I accept a set of views that many take to be mutually incompatible. For instance, I accept both deontology and act consequentialism despite the fact that many take these two to be logical contraries, if not logical contradictories. I see myself as an act consequentialist in that I hold that what makes an act morally right is that its outcome (or prospect) ranks higher, evaluatively speaking, than that of every alternative. Yet, contrary to most act consequentialists, I accept that there are agent-centered restrictions, agent-centered options, and supererogatory acts. And I see myself as a deontologist in that I believe that there are agent-centered restrictions that are ultimately grounded in our duty to adopt an attitude of respect toward autonomous beings. 

So, unlike many others, I believe that we have duties not only to perform certain actions, but also to form certain reasons-responsive attitudes—that is, to form certain beliefs, desires, emotions, and intentions. Thus, I think that we not only have a duty to refrain from treating autonomous beings as mere means, but also a duty to regard such beings as ends in themselves and to respect them accordingly. And we have a duty to adopt certain ends, such as the end of promoting the happiness of others, and to do so even if we don’t foresee ever having the opportunity to promote these ends. Furthermore, I think that we have a duty to form certain intentions, such as the intention to cooperate with others on the condition that they're willing to cooperate with us. And I hold that we must form this conditional intention even if there’s no point in our doing our part in any collective enterprise given that not enough others are willing to do their parts in this enterprise. In any case, here are my views.

 

See also https://philpeople.org/profiles/douglas-w-portmore/views