The Philosopher as Personal Consultant
I have a problem with the concept of 'psychotherapy.' If it weren't for that, I could get right to my
main point, which is that therapy-which I would prefer to call personal consulting-- is something
for which being trained in the discipline of philosophy is every bit as good an academic
foundation as being trained in psychology or in medicine. In ways, philosophy is a better
background than either of these fields. I do not mean that philosophers are better therapists. I do
not think academic preparation is anywhere near as important here as personal traits and practical
training. My thesis is modest, if stated somewhat polemically: philosophy is a fine foundation for
a counseling practice, and these other fields are over-rated.
I. Therapy is a sick word
The practice of encouraging others to talk about their thoughts and feelings, trying to exercise
good judgment about when or whether to give advice, must be nearly as old as pre-historic
parenting. Making this something of a profession must go as far back as villages having
designated wise men and women. No group can justly call this their sole domain. But ever since
Freud (and Breur) wrote about "the talking cure" this has been too often regarded as the special
province of psychoanalysis and its myriad psychotherapy descendents. Training in
psychoanalysis was largely restricted to psychiatrists trained to think in terms of medicine and
the vocabulary of illness. So talking became treatment! Subsequently, forms of psychotherapy
not presented under the aegis of medicine came to be regarded as the province of psychology.
Psychologists are trained in empirical research into the purported causes of human behavior.
They are familiar with research on correlations between behavior and environmental
contingencies, which they tend to think of in a causal and deterministic language. Both
vocabularies smack of passivity: therapy is something you undergo, something done to you,
something supposed to bring about a change, a fix, a cure.
But what sort of activity is this? What is actually done? Listening, mainly. With empathy,
occasional interpretations, occasional advice. There is a focus to the discussions: the thoughts
and feelings and struggles of the person undergoing the therapy. There is a body of theory and
literature, much of it by persons known to be psychotherapists, which may inform the direction
and content of this talking and listening. These ingredients --- the kind of talking, the focus of the
discussion, the surrounding theoretical milieu --- are enough to give us a rough grasp of the
meaning of the word 'therapy'. They do not provide clear enough parameters to identify what
therapy is, with enough precision to settle territorial disputes about who ought to do it.
A monopoly on any form of human discourse is simply offensive. The idea that some forms of
discourse count as undergoing something by one of them is, at least, to be regarded with some
caution. The idea that such interactions may have a clear-cut and definitive outcome in which a
person is "fixed" or "cured" simplicitare, is, I think, naïve. The idea that discourse becomes the
province of specialists just because the subject matter is very important to one of the participants
is arrogant.
The idea that one might be excluded from an arena of human discourse precisely because one has
come to know something about it, because one happens to have become informed about ideas
which are, after all, part of the public's intellectual domain, is patently absurd. Neither do one's
communications become psychotherapy if and when one thinks about people in ways influenced
by theories about people which have been advanced by psychotherapists (Freud or whoever), for
this would have the absurd consequence of making the interactions of every decently educated
person in our civilization into psychotherapy. We all have been profoundly influenced by a
number of psychotherapists' theories.
Neither activities nor theoretical indebtedness will do for demarcating what counts as the
practice of psychotherapy. In sum, it is hard to see why therapy should be the property of any
group, and, indeed, even hard to see what therapy is. Even when all these ingredients are present
--- the kind of talking, the focus of it, the intellectual setting --- there is no really clear-cut
criterion for what activity counts as doing therapy.
II. Therapy is a context-dependent concept
The answer, I think, is that therapy is a context-dependent concept. Psychotherapy, to be
psychotherapy, must be represented as such, and must be thought of by both the provider and the
recipient as something undergone by persons for the purpose of their receiving treatment and
cure. As examples of context-dependent concepts: merely moving a chess piece does not count
as playing chess, even though the movement is indistinguishable from one by someone who is
playing chess. In part, you must think you are playing chess. Merely saying the words "I do"
does not make you married, though exactly these words will make it so in the right context. If
you have a sore back and your friend, or the coach at your gym, advises you to do sit-ups, or if
you have a cold and your grocer advises you to drink orange juice for the vitamin-C, this is not
the practice of medicine even though the advice, the activity, and the hoped-for outcome are all
identical to what you might receive from your physician.
And when two people talk about the personal problems of one of them, the first trying to
understand and encourage the expressions of the second, and the second seeking to express
feelings and gain insight, they are not, on just that account, engaged in "doing therapy" even
though the way they communicate, and the sorts of things they communicate about, are exactly
the sorts of things that people called therapists or psychotherapists do. The activity does not
count as therapy unless certain surrounding contextual conditions are fulfilled, including their
both sharing certain assumptions about what they are doing.
I think the key conditions are these: (1) Representation. The consultant identifies himself or
herself as a "psychotherapist" or a "therapist." (2) Suffering. The consultee, or client, identifies
himself or herself as suffering from some sort of psychological or emotional problem or disorder,
or a physical disorder assumed to be psychologically or emotionally related, for which he or she
wishes to undergo some form of treatment in the hope that the problem can be cured or removed.
3) Expectation. The client believes that the psychotherapist may have the technical expertise to
bring this about. The psychotherapist will do something for and to the client, drawing from
certain theories, training, and technical know-how, which may bring about a change and cause
the problem to be cured or to disappear. (4) Diagnosis and prognosis. The psychotherapist
believes the client's problem can be diagnosed and treated in accordance with theories and skills
with which he or she is familiar and proposes to practice. (6) Explicit agreement. These
conditions and assumptions being shared by both persons, they deliberately enter a relationship
for the express purpose of attempting to treat the problem at issue, and, perhaps, related
3
problems, similarly understood, which may come to light. (7) Professionalism. Both understand
that this is a relationship entered into with a professional, who is presumed to have certain
relevant abilities, to have met the standards and codes of the profession, and that it is a sort of
interaction for which a fee is generally expected. (8) Passivity. While the client may be expected
to do certain things, once this relationship is entered into the client is regarded as undergoing
something called therapy under the guidance of a therapist presumed to be an expert and
presumed to be a healer. It is understood that if this is done well it may help the person, and if it
is done poorly or incompetently it may be useless or may harm the person.
III. Passivity
I believe that the absence of any of the contextual conditions outlined above suffices to make a
consulting activity not count as an instance of doing therapy, and want to underscore the
importance of those factors which emphasize assumptions of sickness, diagnosis, and passivity.
Many professional psychotherapists will not want to agree to this. I expect them to say that the
list does justice to the way behaviorally oriented psychotherapists may see themselves, and to
much of psychoanalytic theory, but there are numerous practitioners from the existentialhumanistic
modalities who will take exception to the various ways in which the client is
portrayed as passive. A reply might go like this: "I don't do anything `to' my clients. I don't `treat'
them. I don't heal the sick. I don't make them change, nor do I think I could, and I don't really
make them do anything at all. They choose to talk with me, and I choose to talk on a level which
I hope is meaningful to us both. Having talked with me, they sometimes decide to make some
changes in what they do. If they do decide to change, nothing that has gone on between them and
me is going to make them do it, or guarantee that they will follow through. What they make out
of our time together is going to have to be up to them. About all I can promise is that I will be as
fully with them as I am able, during the time we meet together."
Exactly! But if this is how these consultants see what they are doing then it shouldn't be called
therapy. The word practically reeks of the grammar of passivity: healing, treating, curing,
causing to be made well, something which makes things change, makes things different and
better. One doesn't get rid of these implications by the mere caveat that many psychotherapists
are moving away from the "medical model," or that the bulk of contemporary private practice is
with persons who are not so much "sick" as wanting to examine their lives and enhance the
quality of their experience. Nor do I think it an exaggeration to say that much of the public that
seeks out the counsel of a psychotherapist is lured by the presumed wizardry of these
technologists of the soul, who can discern your innermost thoughts and then set your life in order
for you. One can understand the incentives of economics and prestige, which would tempt
psychotherapists to keep their seductive, if misleading, labels. One can see why they might
maintain that image, which effectively sells them to the public, the lawmakers, and the insurance
companies. But that doesn't mean they are doing what their titles suggest they are doing.
If anything, the dilemma is sharpened for those theories and modalities of therapy, which
proclaim that they depart, form sickness language and deterministic assumptions. If, in actual
practice, all these varieties of consultants do not see themselves as curing sickness, then what
justifies them in calling what they do "therapy?"
4
But those approaches to therapy which more openly embrace passive language may also recoil
from some of its implications. This point may be put quite simply in the form of a challenge to
any persons who would call themselves psychotherapists: If a client were to complain to you that
you had failed to cure his or her problem, would you think that this client had fundamentally
misunderstood what you had to offer? And when you reflect on your actual practice, how much
of it, do you think, is a matter of what you do, and how much a matter of what it is up to your
clients to do? Do you really think that you cure them? If you are comfortable saying that (and
there may still be plenty of practitioners who answer this in the affirmative) go ahead and call it
therapy. If you are from the other end of the theoretical spectrum, and think that your clients
choose what they call their problems, then the best you can do is sensitively communicate this to
them in the hopes that they will choose to consider the options they already have. Then you don't
see them as sick, and you don't see yourself as curing. So why call it therapy?
My own sympathies will be clear enough. I think we can provide contexts that invite change. I
do not think we can fix people. I do not think that anyone really makes good on an offer to
diagnose an emotional disorder and then cure it. Human transformation is not a passive matter.
The conclusion: there is no such thing as therapy! So to represent one's activities as "doing
psychotherapy" furthers a false promise. It becomes difficult to say, with a clear conscience, that
anyone --psychologist, psychiatrist, philosopher-- ought to do therapy. It's rather like being asked
whether someone ought to practice witchcraft. If I don't believe in witches, I cannot honestly
advocate that someone practice the requisite craft.
IV) Should psychologists do therapy?
Enough quibbling about the word 'therapy'. Call it what you will: should psychologists do it?
There is an impressive amount of empirical research (something done by psychologists) which
indicates that independently of diverse theoretical orientations, effective psychotherapists have
certain personality traits. The three most frequently mentioned conditions or traits are empathy,
genuineness, and positive regard. Now on the face of it, and giving ourselves latitude for
generalizations, we may expect that any rigorous academic training, including psychology,
philosophy, or medicine, is liable to foster traits of intellectualization, affective detachment,
coldness, criticalness, abstractness, impersonality, insecurity and defensiveness swinging at
times over to grandiosity and snobbery. Indeed, some research suggests that a decrease in
therapeutic effectiveness goes along with an increase in graduate education!
One may well wonder whether the (any) academic background of a therapist is an asset, and
wonder whether it not only does not foster but even selects against or discourages traits regarded
as most relevant for effective therapy. Set in the larger picture of questions about whether
psychotherapy is effective at all, skepticism is sure to mount.
Three possible explanations for the apparently low correlation between therapist effectiveness
and graduate education come to mind. One is that there is little connection between academic
ability and consulting ability. A second is that formal education fosters the wrong sorts of
personal traits, or selects against them. The third is that there could be a positive connection
between academic background and consulting ability, depending on whether one's studies were
of a helpful sort. My guess is that a combination of the second and third accounts is likely right,
and that much of what people study in the academic work in psychology graduate school
5
(distinguished from internship experience) is not particularly helpful both with respect to content
and with respect to the way it is studied. Much of the psychology taught in universities
(particularly the prestigious universities, and not so much in the professional schools for
clinicians) is concerned with topics which have little bearing on the practice of consulting. Often
there is open hostility toward the applied realm of the clinician. This goes with the premium
placed on seeing the discipline as an accumulation of facts which are causally related and such as
can be described significantly only by propositions which have been empirically verified.
Psychology suffers from physics-envy. In search of the respect accorded the "hard sciences,"
psychologists are trained to think in terms of causal language, to measure "effectiveness" in a
context of "outcomes," and hence, when it comes to discussing therapy, are drawn toward
affiliating themselves with the cold pragmatics of what can be "operationally defined' and
measured. Academic psychology fosters competitiveness, objectivity, coldness, and distance, and
this is the usual background for personal consultations which call for subjectivity, warmth, and
involvement.
Carl Rogers managed to retain his traits of warmth and empathy, so it can be done. And yet it is
interesting that Rogers is well within the psychologist's penchant for wanting to talk about
effectiveness. Here one does not find much latitude for looking at self-exploration and personal
consultation as something which just might be intrinsically worthwhile, apart from the positive
(or negative) repercussions which may attend them. (Philosophers, artists, and pure theorists are
used to doing things simply because they think them important, and not simply as means to some
other end. This can be a good trait in a personal consultant. It is not a trait psychologists are quite
so often comfortable with.) Relatedly, we should question talk of what therapists "produce" in
their clients. On this score, the self-actualization theorists (Rogers amongst them) turn out to be
cheerful closet determinists. They believe that the provision of the desired therapists' traits -
empathy, genuineness, positive regard - will automatically produce positive change. I prefer to
think of the therapist or consultant as inviting something (self-expression, self-understanding,
and an exploration of self-deception) rather than producing (change, cure, improvement). The
effective consultant is someone with a talent for making invitations. Particularly with those
clients who are more or less getting along all right in life without much more than the usual
allotment of self-deception and human folly, the effective consultant is one who invites the client
into an intrinsically important sort of self-inquiry. It is not the consultant's business to "produce
change" but to invite looking and to join in trying to understand the person being looked at.
When we think of "therapy" as something, which might be undertaken because it is intrinsically
important to inquire into oneself, quite apart from its possible side-benefits, the research on
therapist effectiveness starts to fall into a different light.
I do not deny that the traits of empathy, warmth, and positive regard are appropriate to a
consulting relationship, which would invite deep and meaningful self-expression and selfinquiry:
they encourage a client's acceptance of his or her own feelings. I see no reason to
assume that these traits are encouraged by formal study of psychology. But more to the point, it
is my contention that the perspective of passivity is fundamentally inappropriate for clear
thinking about the actual practice of personal consulting, and that this is a point of view, which is
nothing short of rampant in psychology. I have been maintaining that personal consultation does
not do anything to anyone, doesn't bring about anything. At most, what personal consultation
6
does is provide a client with an invitation to examine his or her conduct, perhaps with the hope
that the client will remember afterwards that change is difficult, maybe unlikely or not worth the
price, but possible. We must wonder whether psychologists are going to be adept at either
comprehending or communicating an invitation to explore, simply because it matters, and to
change, but only if one wants. Psychologists are steeped in a tradition of causal language, and of
research which aspires to contribute to an understanding of what makes people do what they do.
If it is true that the grammar of "what makes people do what they do" is fundamentally
inappropriate for the task of inviting people to accept responsibility for the authorship of their
lives, then psychologists who practice personal consulting must either be wise enough to
transcend their tradition and training, dull enough to fail to see the conflict, or wishy-washy
enough to not have sorted this out. Even in the best of circumstances where the psychologist
transcends tradition, it seems to me that the psychologist will be working with the disadvantage
of having had less opportunity than another person might have had, to learn how to really think
through a theoretical perspective which does fit with what personal consultation is all about.
In this section I have argued that psychologists are very confused about what they are really
doing when they say they are doing therapy. I have also considered some reasons why, because
of an alienating academic background, a means-ends way of looking at the world, and clumsy
theorizing, psychologists might not make very good personal consultants.
V. What are philosophers good for?
I think of personal consulting, and much of what others call therapy, as like dancing with another
person. Sometimes you lead, sometimes you follow, and sometimes the hardest part to learn is
how to stay out of your partner's way. You must understand your partner's way of moving very
well indeed if you are to follow it, move with it, and know what will embellish and accentuate
and what will interrupt. The "dance" of personal consulting requires the kind of intellectual
ability we should expect a well-trained philosopher to have, even if it also calls for traits and
skills philosophers are not likely to have. Philosophers are specialists in understanding people
who are notoriously hard to understand. What philosophers do is listen to, and think about other
philosophers, and their job is to pit their minds against the minds of some of the greatest
intellects our civilization has known, understand -- which is not the same thing as memorizing --
what those thinkers did say, would say, avoided saying, assumed or presupposed, who influenced
them and how, which ideas connect with which, and how it all fits together. They must be able to
do this so well that they can take the part of any major philosopher, know that philosopher so
well that they can become him or her "from the inside," and convincingly present a given
weltanschauung as absolutely right. Then they must be able to turn around and say exactly what's
wrong with it and why. This I advance as an a priori argument that any well-trained philosopher,
other relevant traits being assumed, ought to make a good personal consultant.
Perhaps all academic disciplines breed a degree of self-criticism that goes with a sense of never
knowing as much as one ought to know. But this is especially true in philosophy, which has
historically been one of the most self-critical and introspective of disciplines. Indeed, the popular
image of philosophers as not being good for much owes a great deal to philosopher's criticisms
of themselves, from Socrates on, and perhaps the world at large would not have had enough
imagination to charge the discipline with being useless if the philosophers had not, themselves,
intimated as much. It is no wonder that philosophers are insecure, given the stature of the minds
against which they must match wits, and given the complexity of the problems with which they
7
deal. Granted, philosophers tend to be "out of touch with their feelings" -- a drawback in a
consultant which would be shared by representatives of other disciplines such as psychology or
medicine -- but they are very used to keeping themselves in focus, to bringing a question back to,
"What do I make out of all this? How does what I'm trying to understand in this other person
match with what makes sense to me?" (The first person is offensive to many academics.) Some
philosophers may have managed not to lose their more affective sensitivities; for others, their
introspective habits may be a natural bridge to regaining their feelings. Hoping for the best on
that score, I would venture that the philosopher's habits of self-criticism and ongoing evaluation
of one's own views are a decided asset in a personal consultant. Perhaps the posture of the
confident physician is more "curative" in the realm of medicine, but in the larger enterprise of
personal reflection and consulting, I think we best invite self-scrutiny in others by modeling this
in our own conduct. Would you want a personal consultant (therapist) who exuded confidence? I
wouldn't.
Philosophers are in the habit of puzzling for what seems an eternity on the beauty of an esoteric
argument like Zeno's, which has it that an arrow can never reach its target and that motion is,
indeed, impossible. People from the empirical disciplines are more likely to shoot the arrow and
say, "See!" Who would you rather talk to about the way you look at the world?
Philosophers are in the habit of really concentrating for a long time on a theme, which many
would find boring and too hard to follow. They are in the habit of going back to the same
passage again and again, each time seeing it in a new and deepened way. This is an important
trait for a consultant, whose most urgent practical task will sometimes be, "How am I going to
stay alive through this hour, and remain interested in the same old story?"
In contrast to the empirical disciplines, which tend to view the acquisition of knowledge in a
linear or "building block" fashion, philosophers are used to treating little that is important as
settled. The perspective of a great thinker is treated as eternal, and discussed in present-tense
grammar: "Plato thinks...," rather than "Plato thought...." I find it hard to imagine a philosopher
being comfortable with the American Psychological Association's mandated style of referring to
works by their date of publication, and speaking in the past-tense success-verb grammar of what
so-and-so "showed" or "demonstrated." In philosophy, issues tend to remain present and open,
and are thought about in a way, which leaves one as ready to advocate as to criticize. In
empirical disciplines, such as psychology, claims are talked about in a way, which highlights
their date, summarizes them, and treats them at a distance. (It is pathetic to hear psychologists
speak about Freud as an interesting bit of history.) Here again, I urge that the philosopher's
training is appropriate for personal consulting.
Philosophers are familiar in depth with a large spectrum of the most fundamental schemas
through which anyone has ever looked at anything. The chances of being able to follow, restate,
anticipate, and "dance" with a client in personal consultation have got to be markedly improved
by this training.
Philosophers are first and foremost theorists and they are good at thinking in terms of theory.
Now theories can get in a consultant's way, and it is not uncommon for psychotherapists to be
blinded and inhibited by being wedded either to a theory about a given individual, or a more
general theory about how one is supposed to be a therapist. Ideally, a theory helps you focus
8
without giving you blind spots, and allows you to fit specifics without forcing them; it should
augment the "dance" rather than constricting it. Philosophers are familiar with logical positivism,
which is pretty much the singular vision of psychologists, but do not tend to take it too seriously.
They are professionals at shifting quickly from one theory to another and being able to work with
many theories in a way, which makes sense of the details to which they are applied. Philosophers
have an extraordinarily rich repertoire of theoretical perspectives at their disposal, and are
especially adept at picking up new ones (such as may be offered by psychotherapists, or by
clients or students) and seeing their implications or assumptions. This fosters being openminded,
and cultivates an ability to make some kind of sense out of what practically anyone says
about anything. Other disciplines, by contrast, are often intellectually constipating.
Among the intellectual assets for consulting which philosophers in general ought to have, one
should mention the advantages of having in-depth familiarity with particular philosophers from
the tradition. There are many major philosophical thinkers with theories philosophers know well,
which are decidedly better thought-through than much of what one finds in the empirical
sciences. I refer to philosophical positions which are broad in scope, open-textured enough that
one can listen to another through this perspective without forcing an interpretation on what is
heard, and which are rich enough in specific insight as to provide a treasure-house of feedback. I
can readily imagine a consultant (or a therapist, if there is such a thing as therapy) whose
perspective was adapted from Aristotle, or Spinoza, or Hume, or Marx, or Hegel, or
Wittgenstein, or -- especially -- any of the existentialists like Nietzsche, Kierkegaard, Heidegger,
and Sartre, working in a powerful and inviting way. This is important if (a) having some
theoretical perspective which guides the way one "dances" is helpful, and (b) it is not as
significant as is popularly supposed just which theoretical perspective one identifies with for
one's "effectiveness" in consulting.
I shall conclude this section with very brief remarks on talents for consulting which philosophers
might have, depending on the specifics of their backgrounds; and shall comment critically on
specific therapy modalities for which philosophical training might be appropriate.
Anyone who has done any personal consulting and yet cannot sense the value of psychoanalytic
theory is, in my view, too dense to be interesting. I say this notwithstanding the flaws in
psychoanalytic theory, which I believe, are massive. I do not propose that persons not thoroughly
trained in psychoanalysis should (or even could) practice it. (I do believe that persons with
advanced education only in philosophy could be well qualified for admission to analytic training,
and there are a growing number of "Research Psychoanalysts" who are licensed to train in and
practice psychoanalysis after earning a doctoral degree in a discipline such as philosophy which
is not traditionally preparation for a mental health field.) I suggest, only, that psychoanalytic
theory remains singularly profound, and that any would-be consultants do well to become as
familiar with it as they are able. Because of the wealth of philosophical literature by philosophers
on psychoanalysis, it is not uncommon for philosophers to have familiarized themselves with
psychoanalytic theory in some depth. The exposure one is liable to get in graduate study in
psychology, particularly at a prestigious university (which often means an experimentally
oriented university) is liable to be grossly hasty and superficial by comparison.
Consider also: Wouldn't a solid background in ethics be appropriate for the sort of "value
clarification" which is coming into vogue? Struggling with values has always been an important
9
dimension of therapeutic practice, yet is undertaken by persons who often do not have even a
basic idea of how to think intelligently about ethical relativism, and who haven't the faintest idea
of what the genetic fallacy is or whether it is, indeed, a fallacy. Wouldn't formal training in logic
and critical thinking be the appropriate background for doing the consulting equivalent of
Rational-Emotive Therapy, which seeks, with conspicuous absence of warmth and empathy, to
challenge a client's illogical thinking and irrational beliefs? If consulting or therapy is the
business of challenging a person's muddled thinking (syllogistic healing?), that's what
philosophers do most. Wouldn't the appropriate background for what Glasser calls Reality
Therapy be to study the American Pragmatist's vision of epistemology and metaphysics? How
could anyone follow the theories of Jung who did not thoroughly understand Kant? Regarding
those practitioners who adapt heavily from Zen and Taoism: wouldn't it help to come from a
discipline where one studies these traditions? Wouldn't the application of a "self-actualization"
perspective better come from people who have studied really solid thinkers on this score, like
Aristotle and Hegel? Wouldn't a Radical Therapy best be pursued by someone who really knew
Marx? Wouldn't a feminist perspective on therapy come better from those who had really studied
feminism? Mightn't a Nietzschian scholar have as much of an insight-generating theoretical
perspective as an Adlerian? And, if one could be found willing, shouldn't a Wittgensteinian
scholar, used to contemplating primitive language games, quickly get the hang of Transactional
Analysis?
Finally, philosophers who have studied existentialist philosophers have a monumental advantage
as personal consultants, over the academic backgrounds of virtually everyone else. The
existentialists who philosophers know best -- Nietzsche, Kierkegaard, Heidegger, and Sartre--
provide well thought-out theories with profoundly specific applicability for the concerns of
personal consulting. This is widely acknowledged by psychotherapists, as is the fact that the
writings of these thinkers are obscure and practically inaccessible to the philosophically
unsophisticated. With fairly few exceptions -- such as Binswanger and Boss, who have made
important adaptations of Heidegger's work and Laing's profound indebtedness to Sartre, and in
Irvin Yalom's work) -- the therapeutic and consulting applications of existentialist philosophy
have only begun to be mined. By and large, the adaptations made by psychologists have not
vaguely approximated the sophistication to be found in the original sources and have been
grossly lacking in comparable rigor. More commonly, what one gets from existentially oriented
psychologists are the more banal and superficial themes, such as that it's important to be
authentic, everyone must make choices (this, likely as not, getting boiled down to a biological
imperative that we need to actualize, and will or will not do so depending on the environmental
contingencies), we all must face death, responsibility is scary, and meaning matters. If
existentialism is as relevant to consulting as psychotherapists say (I think it is much more
relevant than they have begun to fathom), then it stands to reason that the people to best mine its
sources are the people trained to understand them. If a theory of applied existentialism is
forthcoming it may best and most likely come from philosophers who are experienced in
consulting practice.
VI) Conclusions
Looking back over what I have written I find that I have not been sparing of polemics and
rhetorical flourish. I suppose I have grown tired of seeing philosophy dismissed by people who
are regularly engaged in doing philosophy without realizing it. A theory is a philosophical theory
10
when its principle claims are predominantly justified by arguments based on the implications of
concepts, rather than empirical data. Everyone does philosophy, frequently; not everyone knows
what he or she is doing. The role of philosophy, and the relevance of philosophical training, has
been pathetically under-rated. The contributions to an understanding of persons by the empirical
disciplines, in their role as empirical disciplines (gathering data and advancing hypotheses
strictly required to organize that data) have been vastly over-rated. The psychologists whose
ideas have been really influential here -- and I include the Freudians, the behaviorists, and the
existential-humanistic practitioners -- have been advancing theories, which were predominately
philosophical in character.
Let me be more blunt. Psychology is shot through and through with conceptual muddles, which
any decently trained philosopher could demonstrate, in short order, to an attentive listener, with
any consecutive five pages of any psychologist's essay, picked at random. Under the guise of
empirical research, psychologists are typically doing philosophy, and doing it badly. Psychology
is founded on a causal perspective in its theories, in spite of the fact that in consulting practice
one cannot talk about human actions in consistently causal terms. It is riddled with unclarity
about the nature of explanation. It is lost in a sea of confusions about the status of mentalistic
language. In short, psychology is founded on a whole way of thinking which consistently gets it
into the kinds of troubles to which philosophers are sensitive. As long as theories about persons
are going to be so heavily philosophical, philosophers should be playing a central rather than a
peripheral role in developing theory of personal consultation.
There continues to be a desperate need for empirical research about what actually happens in a
consulting relationship, and that is what psychologists are trained to do in the bulk of their
academic studies. Yet the very tradition that is appropriate for conducting this research on
personal consultation is inappropriate for consulting practice. For there the task is not to stand
apart from one's clients and summarize the data about them, but to join with them in looking at
the world as they do, and understanding what it's like to think as they do. Little in the formal
academic training of psychologists equips them for this, which is, again, the sort of thing
philosophers do.
This is in no way meant to deny the importance of the applied experience psychologists and
psychotherapists have in doing personal consulting; they are the people who have mainly been
doing it lately, and they are the people to learn from. I would like to see psychologists and
philosophers work together as affiliates in the practice of personal consultation, and I am certain
that both theory and practice would advance dramatically from this association. Responsible
consultants will prepare themselves through extensive self-inquiry comparable to what they wish
to offer to others, will have extensive supervised training and practice, and, within reason, will
have supplemented their academic backgrounds with relevant study. Whether philosophers will
in fact be good consultants remains to be shown, so I would hope that philosophers who want to
do personal consulting will seek out these supplements from professional psychotherapists, who
at least have something of a proven track record.
I favor regulating who may represent themselves and their services to others with titles which
serve to recommend them. Terms like "psychoanalyst," "licensed counselor," etc., imply a
recommendation and sanction of training, and I approve of restrictions on their use. I think it
11
would be a mistake to carry this copy-righting of nomenclature so far that it would be practically
impossible for the unsanctified to find meaningful descriptive language with which to try to
honestly represent what they think they do. Hence I think that words like "therapist,"
"counselor," "consultant," ought to be left to anyone to use or abuse.
It will come as no surprise that I am opposed to regulating or licensing the sorts of
communicative activities which personal consultation and insight-oriented psychotherapy have
in common, for these are part of a larger human enterprise which ought to be open to all: talking
about things which matter, listening, trying to understand, empathizing, advising, challenging,
criticizing, interpreting, confronting, exchanging feelings and reactions, discussing dreams and
fantasies and frustrations, imagining and reminiscing, supporting, considering options and
choices. I do not think any person or group can rightfully prohibit any other person or group
from doing these things, nor from proclaiming themselves to be talented at it by whatever criteria
they like, nor from requesting payment for their time if they wish. There are, admittedly, dangers
in not regulating these things, which can be done in ways, which are stupid, inept, or wicked.
There are greater dangers in regulating such communications, and a more repugnant form of
audacity.
So I think it would be bizarre to believe that the philosophers doing personal consulting--- which
is to say, doing an important form of philosophy --- must wait upon the approving not of
psychologists. Neither is it realistic to expect a philosopher to be subjected to the whole program
of psychological education popularly regarded as a prerequisite for beginning training as a
consultant or as a "therapist." This would be an extraordinarily trying thing for philosophers to
do, requiring a kind of hasty thinking for which they have little aptitude, and for relatively little
intellectual or practical compensation.
Thus the philosopher who longs to talk personally with people as people, but timidly awaits
permission from the psychological professions, should be compared with what H. L. Mencken
said of the democratic man: "He is an ox whose last proud, defiant gesture is to lick the butcher
behind the ear
…."
J. Michael Russell, Ph.D.
Professor of Philosophy and Human Services
California State University, Fullerton
Research Psychoanalyst
Newport Psychoanalytic Institute