2024. Explaining Content. [penultimate]
Having a mind involves having a perspective on the world. Creatures like us gather information about the world, form initial opinions, do some reasoning, form firmer opinions, make decisions about how to act, and eventually execute some of these decisions. All of these abilities depend upon our ability to represent the world—on having the world in mind, so to speak. We keep track of information using representations, we reason with those very same representations, and we act on the basis of those representations. Moreover, we do so partly in virtue of those representations' content. I'm disposed to token the concept DOG when I'm in front of dogs partly in virtue of the fact that DOG means dog. And you are disposed to go to the fridge to grab beer partly because you believe that there's beer in the fridge. A good theory of mental content—a view that tells us in virtue of what we represent the parts of the world that we do—must meet this adequacy condition, and let mental content be explanatorily efficacious. It turns out that meeting the explanatory efficacy condition is no easy task: since explanations (even partial ones) are asymmetric, many views end up incompatible with this adequacy condition. For example, information-based views of mental content take my dispositions to token the concept DOG in front of dogs to partly explain the content of that very concept, and so cannot appeal to that content in order to explain those dispositions. Similarly, functionalist views of mental content take your disposition to go to the fridge to grab beer to partly explain the content of your belief that that there's beer in the fridge, and so cannot appeal to that content in order to explain that disposition. In my dissertation, I develop a novel causal-historical view of mental content which is meant to validate explanatory efficacy. According to this view, the content of a mental representation is determined by the causal relations that are in place at the moment of its formation. In a slogan, this view claims that representation is re-presentation, where presentation is understood in causal terms. This view meets explanatory efficacy quite naturally. Our intuitive picture of mental representations is silent on what explains the formation of a certain mental representation. That is, we are not committed to any claim of the form 'S formed mental representation R because R means M'. Since, according to the Re-Presentation view, mental content is determined only by what happens in the context of forming the relevant mental representation, we are free to appeal to it in explaining all of the uses of that mental representation.